JEAN-PAUL
SARTRE
Sartre was
unquestionably the greatest of modern French writers and the one whose
philosophy had the most influence on his contemporaries. He was in many respects the antithesis of
Camus - a sophisticated northern Frenchman who was more at home in libraries
and lecture halls than in the natural world of Mediterranean neo-paganism. But he wasn't a transcendentalist, and if one
thing more than any other characterizes and limits Sartre, it is his general
indifference to and even ignorance of religious values - in short, his
materialist bias, which owed not a little, I suspect, to his Protestant
upbringing. The existence of men in a
meaningless universe was a taken-for-granted axiom of his Existentialist
philosophy, its inference that man is only free when he acts ... the
cornerstone of his mature thought. He
came at the tail-end, so to speak, of humanistic civilization in a bourgeois
country and, not altogether surprisingly, he didn't point the way forward to
post-humanistic civilization. He
remained a victim of his nihilism, convinced of the absurdity of human life but
persisting in his perseverance with it, if only because suicide would have
required more courage or resolve than he possessed.
It is hard to believe that anyone with such a bleak philosophy as
Sartre could be a great philosopher, and one may doubt whether, in the strictly
academic sense of the word, he was really a philosopher at all. Rather, one could argue that he was a
twentieth-century philosophe,
or combination of artist and thinker, an 'author' and 'writer', in Roland
Barthe's paradoxical distinction. A
philosopher should really be a man who writes philosophy and nothing else, and
to be such a man one must either have the means to support oneself, like
Schopenhauer, or acquire those means through some profession congenial to or
associated with philosophy, like as a professor at some university. Alternatively, there is the possibility of
one's being supported by a pension or dole, like Nietzsche, who nevertheless
had been a professor, as, of course, had Schopenhauer. But none of these categories would apply to
Sartre, who, following the termination of his short-lived pedagogic career, was
obliged to earn a living from editorial as well as literary work. Sartre was more than a philosopher and on
that account also considerably less than one!
Nevertheless in Sartre's case we are dealing with a man who was
a jack of all (literary) trades but, paradoxically, a master of many. To compare any one side of Sartre's
creativity with the corresponding side of Camus' ... is to see how
comparatively inferior the latter was.
As a novelist, Sartre's Nausea and his Roads to Freedom
trilogy dwarf the three very short novels and one medium-length novel by Camus,
both in technique and content - the former being less conservative and more
expansive than Camus', the latter ... both more intellectually and thematically
interesting. As a short-story writer,
Sartre's Intimacy displays greater imagination and intellectual depth
than Camus' Exile and the Kingdom.
As for the theatre, the disparity between the two men is even more
conspicuously in Sartre's favour, for his plays - the best of which, like Nakrassov
and Altona, are contemporary classics - both outnumber and outclass the
two or three original works by Camus. As
for philosophy, there is no comparison between Sartre's Being and
Nothingness or, for that matter, the even more complex Critique of
Dialectical Reason and Camus' two comparatively lightweight philosophical
works, The Myth of Sisyphus and The Rebel, which one could argue
are both reactionary and misguided.
Admittedly, the Lyrical Essays reveals an aspect of
Camus' creative scope which Sartre doesn't appear to have. But then there is no place in Camus - and
probably never would have been - for full-scale biographical works or
psychoanalytical studies like the ones by Sartre on Flaubert, Baudelaire, and
Genet, not to mention his essays on artists, such as the brilliant ones on
Tintoretto and Giacometti. Clearly,
Sartre's range of creativity both exceeds and surpasses, genre for genre, that
of his close contemporary.
That Sartre's work or, at any rate, the best of it will continue
to be read during the decades and centuries to come ... I have little doubt,
and I would wager that Nausea will constitute his principal claim to literary
immortality, with the probability of a philosophical work like Being and
Nothingness in accompaniment. Not
that Sartre's philosophy is particularly enlightened, or particularly
readable. But it subsumes and refines
upon a sufficient number of earlier twentieth-century philosophers to have at
the very least a certain historical significance. Even if it's only regarded as a record of
bourgeois decadence or of a civilization in decline, it will retain some
posthumous value.
Sartre's reputation for political affiliation with the Extreme
Left is too well-documented to warrant my dwelling on it in this essayistic
sketch. But although he gave a lot of
thought and time to politics, he never went out of his way to join a party,
including the French Communist Party, which he courted for a time. One might describe him as a social anarchist,
given his active sympathy for La Cause du Peuple and kindred
radical-syndicalist causes; though if he was originally a Marxist who then became
an Existentialist, his subsequent attempt to fuse the two disciplines wasn't
altogether convincing, and one must pin part of the blame for this on his lack
of a transcendental perspective, the possession of which just might have
precluded the anarchic modification of Marxism from taking place. But fundamentally Sartre was too much of a
bourgeois to ever be anything more than an enfant terrible to the
bourgeoisie and a sympathetic onlooker or fellow-traveller to the
communists. Anarchy, in one guise or
another, has long been attractive to bourgeois radicals, and Sartre's
existentialist variation on a Marxist theme shows him to be no exception. The Soviet Union, with its state control of
the workers, both politically and economically, proved disappointing to Sartre,
though he never sought to emulate Gide in attacking it. Instead he concentrated his political hopes
on a revolution in France which would free the proletariat from bourgeois
oppression and (presumably) leave them to do their own collective thing within
a broadly Social Democratic context.
Although one or two of Sartre's works give the impression that
he was a loner, he fared well from both friends and mistresses throughout the
greater part of his life, supplementing his long-standing platonic attachment
to Simone de Beauvoir with a number of short-lived, though for the most part
satisfying, love-affairs with younger women.
He was too well-born, too wealthy, and too famous to be a perverted
solitary, like Genet, and although his only autobiographical work, Words, gives one the
impression that life was a regrettable burden on him, nevertheless he did
relatively well out of it in terms of writing, travelling, loving, listening to
music, eating, drinking, smoking, and so on.
Even in old age, when reduced to blindness and unable to write, he had
to admit that his life had been well spent and quite successful on the
whole. There were still some things that
could be done, but France's most famous and celebrated intellectual hadn't done
too badly, even so!