6
BOTH
POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE: In speaking of antitheses we almost invariably put the
positive attribute first and the negative one second, as the following short
list should serve to confirm: good and bad, truth and illusion, pleasure and
pain, happiness and sadness, life and death, light and dark, love and hate, day
and night, heaven and hell, man and woman, boy and girl, rich and poor,
beautiful and ugly, high and low, yes and no, etc. To say that man's nature is good would hardly
constitute the truth; for in order to have any goodness at all he must have
sufficient evil from which to create it, he must have one tendency balanced by
another.
Granted that man is neither good nor evil
but both good and evil (which should not be confounded with a combination of each),
one can nevertheless assert that the positivity of
goodness generally leads him to aspire towards the Good rather than towards its
opposite which, being negative, can only take second place, as it were, to the
'leading string'. Thus, as an inherently
positive phenomenon, life is geared towards goodness, but to a goodness which
can only be maintained with the aid of evil.
Yes, Gide was
right to contend that man was born for happiness, in that man's strongest
predilection is to aspire towards the positivity of
happiness rather than towards the negativity of sadness. Admittedly, this happiness ultimately depends
upon the intermittent prevalence of sadness.
But sadness can never become the 'leading
string', or man's principal objective.
For the essential positivity of our being does
not induce us to pine for sadness when we are happy but, on the contrary, to
immerse ourselves in happiness as if it were a natural condition, as if we had
found our spiritual home. And this same positivity eventually goads us out of our sadness by
causing us to pine for happiness.
Now according to Schopenhauer - who is
virtually antithetical to Gide - happiness is merely
the absence of pain and thus a negative thing, whereas pain itself he saw as
very positive, a thing upon which life mostly depends. To follow Schopenhauer's reasoning here isn't
particularly easy, but it should be fairly apparent to most people that he was
somewhat mistaken. For as the accepted
antithesis to pleasure, not happiness, pain is really anything but a positive
thing, since we aren't driven by our essential being to pain but to pleasure,
so pleasure must be the positive attribute and pain the negative one. Not being content to muddle these antitheses,
however, Schopenhauer also saw fit to reverse their qualities and thus invest
pain with a positive attribute - a thing hardly guaranteed to enlighten one or
advance truth in this respect!
So do I therefore advise people against
reading Schopenhauer? No, I don't, since
there is much value to be gleaned from a serious perusal of his major works,
including The World as Will and Representation. What I do advise people against, however, is
being put off philosophers like Schopenhauer on account of their logical fallacies. There is
not a philosopher on earth who could escape criticism for one reason or
another, since there isn't one whose integrity as a human being exempts him
from error. Where one believes the
contrary, it can be assumed that one has been deceived by the mistaken
assertions of the philosopher concerned without in the least suspecting the
fact. No man is born to tell the whole
truth and nothing but the truth. Yet no
man is born subject to nothing but illusions, either!
A man who is prepared to give his favourite
philosopher's principal target of abuse (Hegel in the case of Schopenhauer) a
fair hearing or reading would strike this philosopher as more enlightened than
one whose willingness to do so has been severely compromised, if not completely
negated, by too slavish an adherence to him.