CYCLE
TWENTY-TWO
1. Most people would, in general terms, tend to
identify primacy with evil and supremacy with good, but that is really an
over-simplification of what is, in fact, a more comprehensive picture in which
not simply evil and good, but folly and wisdom are also to be found, and found,
be it remembered, as male complements, in subjectivity, to a female dichotomy
between the aforementioned objective terms.
2. In reality, primacy
is no more evil than supremacy is good.
Primacy is simply malevolent in both the objective contexts of negative metachemical evil and chemical good, and the subjective
contexts of negative physical folly and metaphysical wisdom.
3. Likewise supremacy is no more
good than primacy is evil.
Supremacy is simply benevolent in both the positive objective contexts
of metachemical evil and chemical good, and the
positive subjective contexts of physical folly and metaphysical wisdom.
4. Thus there is negative evil (malevolent) and
positive evil (benevolent), negative good and positive good, negative folly and
positive folly, and negative wisdom and positive wisdom, with the negative
options ever attaching to primacy and the positive options to supremacy.
5. The principal differentiating factor between
primacy and supremacy is therefore not evil and good, still less folly and
wisdom, but negativity and positivity, either of which
can be evil (metachemical) or good (chemical), not to
mention foolish (physical) or wise (metaphysical) in relation to competitive
malevolence or co-operative benevolence, depending on the context.
6. Thus we arrive at the seemingly paradoxical
but in actuality logically incontrovertible conclusion that evil can be
malevolent or benevolent, apparent in an inorganic or an organic manifestation
according to how the will does, and the metachemical
will most especially.
7. Likewise we arrive at the conclusion that
good can be malevolent or benevolent, quantitative in an inorganic or an
organic manifestation according to how the spirit gives, and the
chemical spirit most especially.
8. Similarly we arrive at the conclusion that
folly can be malevolent or benevolent, qualitative in an inorganic or an
organic manifestation according to how the ego takes, and the physical
ego most especially.
9. Finally we arrive at the conclusion that
wisdom can be malevolent or benevolent, essential in an inorganic or an organic
manifestation according to how the soul is, and the metaphysical soul
most especially
10. It should not be forgotten, however, that the doing
of will is always evil, whether in the per se context of metachemistry
or in the pseudo-evil contexts of chemistry (quasi-good), physics
(quasi-foolish), or metaphysics (quasi-wise).
11. Nor should it be
forgotten that the giving of spirit is always good, whether in the per se context of
chemistry or in the pseudo-good contexts of metachemistry
(quasi-evil), metaphysics (quasi-wise), or physics (quasi-foolish).
12. Similarly the taking of ego is always
foolish, whether in the per se context of physics or in the pseudo-foolish
contexts of metaphysics (quasi-wise), metachemistry
(quasi-evil), or chemistry (quasi-good).
13. Likewise the being of soul is always
wise, whether in the per
se context of metaphysics or in the pseudo-wise contexts of physics
(quasi-foolish), chemistry (quasi-good), or metachemistry
(quasi-evil).
14. Thus whereas the doing of evil is
always apparent (genuine) or pseudo-apparent (non-metachemical
'bovaryizations' of will), the giving of good
is always quantitative (genuine) or pseudo-quantitative (non-chemical 'bovarizations' of spirit).
15. Thus whereas the taking of folly is
always qualitative (genuine) or pseudo-qualitative (non-physical 'bovaryizations' of ego), the being of wisdom is
always essential (genuine) or pseudo-essential (non-metaphysical 'bovaryizations' of soul).