CHAPTER
ONE
With a look of pained
scepticism on an otherwise quite straightforward face, Stephen Jacobs, friend
and only guest that evening of fellow-writer James Kelly, said: "I can hardly
agree with you that Plato was a realist.
After all, he considered the Ideas to be of primary importance and the
objects, insofar as they had any reality at all, to be merely secondary. Unlike his great pupil Aristotle, he didn't
put the Ideas in the objects but
kept them separate, thereby emphasizing their superior nature. So how can a man who considers the Ideas
superior to the diverse components of the material world, which are deemed to
be merely imperfect copies of the originals, possibly be a realist?" He leant back in Kelly's armchair with a less
sceptical expression on his clean-shaven face and fumbled in the left pocket of
his dark-green jacket for some cigarettes.
Without giving Kelly a chance to respond, he proceeded to ram home his
point with the aid of a cigarette, the idea of which, he ventured to suggest,
would have been more real to Plato than the damn cigarette itself. "Fortunately, cigarettes hadn't been
invented in the fourth-century B.C.," he went on, "so no-one would
have been granted an opportunity to question the superiority of the Idea on
their account."
"Yes, but the point is that, for Plato, the Idea was
external to himself, it was something which had a kind of life of its
own," countered Kelly with an air bordering on supercilious defiance. "The Idea wasn't something that he
extrapolated from reality but, rather, something he believed he had discovered
in the external world, where it had a prior existence to him."
"Really?" exclaimed Jacobs as he lit the cigarette in
his hand with the aid of a glossy lighter and returned the no-less glossy
packet of Gauloise Longues
to its customary pocket. "That's
almost too funny for words, old chap. I
mean, what's an idea if not something related to one's mind, to the faculty of
thought? Can you imagine the idea of a
wheel floating about in space with more reality to it than the wheel of a car
or a motorbike?" He deeply inhaled
some tobacco from his cigarette, as though intending to throw up a dense
smoke-screen between himself and the idea of a wheel hovering somewhere in the
immediate vicinity. "But even if
the Idea was external to himself," he continued, having exhaled the
incipient smoke-screen in the general direction of Kelly's armchair, "even
if that was the case, he'd still be an idealist for attributing more reality to
the Idea than to the material object derived from it; for attributing more
reality to the idea of a wheel than to the wheel itself!"
"Perhaps he would," conceded Kelly, who was almost choking
in the detestable smoke his guest had unconcernedly bombarded him with,
"but he'd still be less of an Idealist than, say, William of Occam, the fifteenth-century philosopher who placed the
Ideas firmly in the mind instead of in the external world, like Plato, or in
the mind of God, like Plotinus. You might call him an idealistic realist, if
you like."
"Or a realistic idealist," suggested Jacobs, before
flicking some ash which had fallen on his lap onto the carpet and then
proceeding to rub it in with the heel of his right shoe without the slightest
show of embarrassment or remorse.
"But he was quite mistaken to consider the Ideas external to
himself, and, in my opinion, equally mistaken to consider them superior in
reality to the objects around him. If
Aristotle wasn't entirely right to put the Ideas into the objects themselves,
he at least showed more common sense than his early mentor where the claims of
Idealism were concerned. His was a more
realistic touch."
"Yes, I suppose you're right," murmured Kelly, who
looked as though he had just been defeated by Alexander the Great and was about
to be executed for political treachery.
For a while, however, silence supervened
between them, since neither man knew what to say next, nor had they any real
desire to continue the conversation along the same paradoxically intellectual
lines, each of them at cross-purposes with the other. Although they both professed to being
philosophers in preference to anything else, they were obliged to admit to
themselves that there were times when the subject of philosophy was virtually
anathema to them, times when they would rather have discussed the weather or
the results of the latest football matches, tired as they were of dragging
their professional lives into their social relationship. It was as though they had to keep reminding
themselves of the professional basis of their friendship from fear that it
would automatically crumble for want of solid support, since it was philosophy
which had brought them together in the first place.
Now
that they had come to a pause in their philosophical discussion, however, they
suddenly found themselves in the uncomfortable position of having to stare the
basis of this friendship in the face, which didn't seem as solid a thing as
when they had first entered upon it, some four years ago. But it was the thirty-nine-year-old Stephen
Jacobs who, with his talkative nature, re-opened the conversation on a note of
sympathy for Plato for having had enough sense to think an actual rose superior
to a painting of one, even if he hadn't had enough sense to think an actual
rose superior to the idea of one.
"You might be able to sell a painting of a rose at ten-thousand
times the price of an actual rose," he continued, "but even so, the
actual rose cannot be improved upon - any more than you can improve upon the
beauty of an actual woman with the aid of a canvas, a brush, and a set of
oils. It's nature which has the better
of art, irrespective of what certain artists might think. Consequently it seems to me that a realistic
perspective relating to the value of art will always be found somewhere in
between Plato and, say, Wilde, rather than at either extreme. Then one wouldn't have to consider a painting
inferior to the Idea it endeavours to portray through the object or,
conversely, superior to the object it endeavours to improve upon through the
Idea." He flicked some ash from his
half-consumed cigarette into the small ashtray which stood conveniently close
to-hand and bowed his head, as though to aid himself think about something he
desired to keep private.
"Yes, I quite agree
with your realistic perspective," admitted Kelly smilingly. "If one could always strike a balance
somewhere in-between idealism and realism, one would certainly save oneself a
lot of unnecessary deceptions! It seems
that we're only just beginning to shake off the idealism of Locke, Berkeley,
Hume, Kant, etc., by accepting the external world as something which actually
exists as it is in itself rather than wholly dependent upon the shape our minds
choose to give it. We appear to have
been labouring for too long under the deception that our minds are really quite
different from the world around us.
Obviously, there has to be a subject/object relationship, but not to the
extent of making the object entirely dependent upon the nature of the
subject. Even Plato wouldn't have
approved of that, insofar as he found the object to be a pale copy of the Idea,
which was external to the subject."
"Indeed, eighteenth-century idealism is quite a different
proposition from Platonic Idealism," rejoined Jacobs, raising his head
again. "One can hardly expect the
minds of Locke, Hume,
"As a matter of fact I've been re-reading it," replied
Kelly enthusiastically. For Koestler was pretty much his favourite philosopher these
days, and the book in question unquestionably one of the master's finest. "As you may know, Koestler
developed a theory of 'holons' - a name he assigns to
phenomena which are simultaneously both wholes and parts, the phenomena in
question being complete in themselves, and thus wholes, but also dependent upon
larger wholes, and thus parts. A
phenomenon, be it a material object, an organization of material objects, an
event, a psychological process, or whatever, can be an autonomous whole one
moment and a dependent part the next, depending on the context. There's no clear-cut division between wholes
and parts, particles and wavicles, because there's
nothing which is entirely one or the other.
For example, we are autonomous wholes to the extent that we are
individual human beings, but we're also dependent parts in a larger whole,
which is human society. If we try to
live merely as autonomous wholes, divorced from the society to which we belong,
we'll soon find ourselves starving to death.
And if we try to live merely as dependent parts, as tools of society,
we'll probably find ourselves starving to death just as quickly, since we won't
be in a position to feed ourselves - not, as in the first case, because we haven't
earned the money, but simply because we'll have no desire or time to look after
ourselves once we have earned it."
"Yes, that sounds reasonably plausible," sighed Jacobs
while flicking through the book in his hands.
"There's a parallel of sorts with Whitehead
here, the diverse kinds of phenomena you mention having intimate connections
with Whitehead's 'actual entities', which cover more
than the merely material aspects of life.
He thought the world an 'extensive continuum' of events having
'extensive connections', or overlappings. That doesn't appear too far removed from what
you've just explained to me regarding the '
"Unfortunately I must confess to a rather scant knowledge
of Whitehead's philosophy," said Kelly, blushing
slightly, "but I can tell you that Koestler's
philosophy is closely related to the philosophies of Parmenides and, perhaps to
an event greater extent, of Hegel."
"Oh, in what way?" asked Jacobs who, though no stranger
to Koestler himself, had next-to-no-knowledge of
either philosopher.
"Well, he contends that the combination of parts into a
whole is greater than and different from the sum of the parts which form that
whole, thereby concurring with both Parmenides and Hegel to the detriment of
any behaviourist/reductionist credo," Kelly
promptly replied. "And he goes on,
like Hegel, to develop a tripartite system of logic as opposed to a purely
dualistic one, which leads him to emphasize the 'extensive continuum', if you
like, of humour, science, and art. He
defines humour as the 'ha-ha!' reaction, science as the 'aha!' reaction, and
art as the 'ah ...' reaction, returning to a dualistic framework to ascribe
self-assertive tendencies to humour and, at the other end of the spectrum,
self-transcending tendencies to art.
Science is defined as signifying a subtle combination of the two
tendencies, a kind of hybrid coming in-between the two thoroughbreds, as it
were. Now anything which has a
self-assertive tendency can be identified, in returning to the 'holonic' viewpoint, with the independent whole, whereas
anything with a self-transcending tendency should be identified with the
dependent part. So you can see that
humour pertains to individualism, whereas the keynote to art is to be found, as
earlier affirmed by Schopenhauer, in self-transcendence, in acknowledgement of
something greater than oneself. But if
one is to take this triad of humour, science, and art seriously, then it should
be fairly obvious that, contrary to popular belief, science and art are not
opposites but next-door neighbours, so to speak, in a tripartite spectrum
beginning with humour, which is therefore the logical antithesis to art. It seems that we've also deceived ourselves
for far too long on this matter, as on so many other matters, for that
matter."
"So it would appear," mumbled Jacobs, whose face was
partly hidden from Kelly by the book he was busily scanning, as though in
search of some hidden revelation.
"And so Koestler has effectively
demonstrated that there's a place for both dualistic and tripartite reasoning in
the world; that the one needn't necessarily exclude the other?"
"Precisely," confirmed Kelly with some considerable
satisfaction. "It's simply a
question of knowing when to employ one or the other modes of reasoning, not of
castigating that which you foolishly assume to be mistaken. In this respect, Koestler
has achieved a greater synthesis than most of his philosophical forebears, who
either emphasized triads at the expense of duads, or duads at the expense of triads. Although one could also argue that Koestler has put tripartite thinking on the philosophical
map at the expense of dualism, which is no mean achievement, and one, I feel
sure, that can only gain greater recognition and credibility as time goes
by."
Stephen Jacobs sceptically nodded his head before saying:
"Wasn't Huxley thinking along tripartite lines in The Human Situation?" He cast his gaze in the general direction of
the Aldous Huxley section of Kelly's meagre bookcase,
then went on: "I seem to recall your telling me something about that book
a few months ago, though I still haven't got round to reading it yet, despite
the fact that it was published some time ago.
"Perhaps you'll let me borrow it sometime, James?"
"By all means, take it with you this evening. It's something you ought to have borrowed
when I first mentioned it to you, though you seem to have a marked talent for
procrastination where books of that sort are concerned."
"It's an old family weakness, I'm afraid," confessed
Jacobs, smiling. "Still, I do get
round to reading them eventually, even if I'm not as keen as you on some of the
more recent philosophical publications.
I suppose I'm more old-fashioned really, and tend, in consequence, to
react against them."
"A statement which seems to imply that I'm also
old-fashioned, only less so than yourself," deduced Kelly, smiling in
turn.
"Well, there may well be a grain of truth in that implication," conceded Jacobs thoughtfully,
"though I didn't exactly intend to convey such an impression. I suppose a course in Wittgenstein's
linguistic philosophy would add more precision to my utterances."
"Provided you could understand his linguistics!"
confirmed Kelly.
There ensued another silence while Jacobs continued to flick
through the pages of Janus - A Summing Up. However, when his eyes alighted upon the name
of Konrad Lorenz, he halted in his flicking tracks
and uttered an exclamatory 'Aha!' sound, which was evidently in confirmation of
something he had been assuming for some time.
"I imagine Koestler got some of the
inspiration for his 'haha!' -
'aha!' - 'ah ...' spectrum from Konrad
Lorenz," he at length remarked, noting the positive reference to the
latter on the page before him.
"What makes you say that?" asked Kelly, feeling
slightly puzzled.
"Well, I've recently been re-reading Lorenz's Behind the Mirror, a
work which does, incidentally, have some bearing on what you were saying about
Platonic idealism a little while ago," Jacobs replied. "It seems the compromise between
idealism and realism you were advocating is the very thing that appeals to
Lorenz who, in opposition to the idealistic lopsidedness of late-eighteenth-
and early-nineteenth-century philosophy, is given to the view that the material
world isn't really all that different from the world as we see it, but
corresponds to reality as it actually is.
Instead of making the world dependent on our particular consciousness of
it, as traditional idealism usually does, Lorenz contends that our
consciousness corresponds to the world and was evolved in harmony with it, so
that what we see isn't necessarily a distortion of reality but, rather, that
reality reflected in our minds. The fact,
however, that we're given to assimilating only a fraction of total reality
doesn't, of course, invalidate his contention, since what we do
assimilate as Homo sapiens is real enough in itself. It merely corresponds to a different reality
than to, say, fish reality, which has nothing whatsoever to do with the
assimilation of rain, snow, sunlight, wind, flowers, trees, etc."
"So I was right in thinking that we've finally got round to
believing in the reality of the external world!" exclaimed Kelly
mockingly. "Though I guess you
could say it had to wait for an age of materialism, with its cameras and
televisions, to give it due credit as a logical entity. I suppose Christianity was largely
responsible for the hold-up by insisting on the superiority of the Otherworld
to the detriment of this one. Yet some
people would still argue that conceptual subjectivity is intrinsically superior
to perceptual objectivity, and that the modern world has simply regressed from
the civilized plane to the barbarous one.
But isn't Lorenz's contention more a straightforward
appeal to materialism than a compromise between realism and idealism?"
"I don't think so," Jacobs replied. "He's simply getting us away from the
stupid or, depending on your viewpoint, highly civilized idea that the world
would cease to exist if we weren't there to witness it."
"Like, presumably, what
"Yes, though he was shrewd enough to point out that it
would continue to exist as an idea in the mind of God," confirmed
Jacobs. "However, the important thing
to remember is that any objective comprehension of things presupposes a subject
who comprehends; that there's a subtle interaction between subject
and object which inevitably implies a compromise between them. Unlike the earlier-mentioned idealists,
however, Lorenz doesn't accept the contention that our minds distort external reality. On the contrary, he endorses the
correspondence they have to it. That's
the difference, and that, believe it or not, is an important advance in the history
of Western philosophy!"
"One would think it crawled along at a snail's pace,"
said Kelly, who was by this time almost ashamed of being philosophical. "Either that or it has been pursued
almost exclusively by intellectual cranks hitherto!"
"I could hardly agree with that remark, James, which
I'm sure you don't seriously mean!" exclaimed Jacobs with a show of
surprise. "Still, we do have our
moments of amusement and exasperation at its expense, I'll grant you. But Konrad Lorenz
is a scientist, not a philosopher, and a scientist, moreover, who doesn't think
too highly of idealistic philosophers.
We can at least be grateful to science for continuing to support our
faith in external reality, even though it is becoming progressively weirder
with the passing of time."
Having returned the Koestler tome to
its resting place on top of the small bookcase, Stephen Jacobs glanced at his
wristwatch and informed his friend that he would have to be leaving. He had an appointment with his agent the
following morning and consequently wanted to get an early night. Since it was already
"Good luck with your appointment tomorrow," said
Kelly, opening the door of his Highgate flat.
"Thanks old chap," Jacobs responded smilingly and,
with a gentle wave of his free arm, he was off down the flight of stairs and
out, via the communal entrance, into the wet night.
'Oh well,' thought Kelly as he returned to the study and began
to survey its heterogeneous contents with an air of dejection, 'I suppose I
won't be seeing him for some time. Which is probably just as well, considering
he resents not being able to show off his philosophical knowledge to me as much
as he'd ideally like to, in view of the fact that I'm usually better informed
and even more up-to-date than him. I
think he has the impression that he ought to know more about philosophy than
me, bearing in mind that he's three years my senior and has been studying it
for a couple of years longer. But how
hard and how often has he really been studying it? And who has he been studying anyway? He thinks he's a philosopher, but he's
really a philosophical artist, a man who leans in the direction of philosophy
from a sort of literary base. He doesn't
have a Ph.D. and is consequently without a chair of philosophy anywhere. But how many genuine philosophers don't have
that? Almost every great philosopher on
record was a lecturer at one time or another - even Schopenhauer and
Nietzsche. Though the
former resigned his chair and the latter taught philology even after he'd been
awarded an honorary Ph.D. by his university. But at least he ended-up with a doctorate,
which is more than either Stephen or I have acquired. Still, why should one be ashamed of being a
man of letters instead of a bona fide philosopher with no literature to
his name because he is sufficiently preoccupied with his university post and
the writings which pertain to or supplement it?
What's wrong with being a philosophical artist? That's what I'd like to ask Stephen Jacobs,
though if I did it would almost certainly humiliate him, even make him take
umbrage. For he thinks he's a
philosopher. But philosophers don't
write literature; they confine themselves to lecturing on and writing about
philosophy - assuming, of course, that they hadn't been sacked from their
university, like Bertrand Russell, or induced to resign their post, like
Nietzsche and Schopenhauer, for one reason or another. Admittedly, Stephen writes philosophy or, at
any rate, something approximating to it.
But he can't earn his living from that; he has to write literature as
well. So, in a sense, he's probably
ashamed of having to compromise himself against his deepest intellectual
predilections.... If he was genuinely a philosophical artist, on the other
hand, that sort of thing wouldn't particularly bother him. He'd be nicely poised between literature and
philosophy, glad to take refuge in the one whenever the other became either too
oppressive or too restrictive. But
because he secretly yearns to be a philosopher, and has little taste for
literature, he finds the idea of being a philosophical artist beneath him. Yet he's neither a genuine philosopher – much
less an artist-philosopher/philosopher-artist - nor a genuine artist. He's a total misfit. A failed philosopher and a bogus artist! That's the way I see him anyway, and that's
the way I believe he is, even though he'd be the last person to admit it. For if there's one thing he's a genuine
master of, it's the art of self-deception!
Of that, there can be no doubt!'
By now James Kelly was beginning to feel slightly more pleased
with himself than he had done all evening. He was taking revenge on Jacobs for all the
humiliations the latter had wittingly or unwittingly inflicted upon him
throughout the course of the evening by means of this barrage of analytical
thought, which he aimed at his colleague's professional integrity with the
express purpose of smashing it to bits, if only in his perverse imagination,
and thereby firmly establishing his unquestionable intellectual superiority
over the man.... Not that Jacobs was a permanent thorn in his side. On the contrary, he could think of plenty of
people who would have created a less favourable impression on him. But, all the same, he knew that their
friendship wasn't particularly sincere, that it didn't run very deep. For one thing, their temperaments weren't
entirely congruous, Jacobs being no less critical and moody than he was
easy-going and optimistic, while, for another, they wrote quite different books
and lived in quite separate worlds.
Naturally, they did their best to pretend that these worlds weren't all
that far apart whenever they were in each other's company. Nevertheless, there were times - as had
occurred more than once this very evening - when the effort of maintaining
mutual regard proved too much for them and an embarrassing silence interposed
itself between their respective pretences.
Needless to say, such occurrences were by no means unheard of in human
relationships; there were always contradictory or even antipathetic elements endeavouring
to undermine the basis of even the most solid friendship. Even so, there was a limit to how many of
these elements one could be expected to tolerate before things became too
burdensome and one was accordingly obliged to sever ties. Fortunately, however, things weren't quite
that bad between them at present, though that wasn't to say they couldn't have
been a lot better!
'As for me,' Kelly continued to reflect, as he sat down in the
armchair recently occupied by his guest, 'I have the advantage of being at one
with my vocation of philosophical artist, of being an intellectual hybrid
simply because, on the one hand, I don't want to be exclusively an artist and,
on the other hand, I've no desire to establish myself as an academic
philosopher, a man with a Ph.D. and lecturing post at some university who is
thereby enabled to write uncommercial treatises in
his spare time. Admittedly, one could
also be a philosopher without such qualifications if, by good fortune, one
had been endowed with a sufficiently large private income to enable one to
exclusively dedicate oneself to the writing of aphorisms, monologues,
dialogues, etc. But the vast majority of
philosophers aren't so fortunate, with the inevitable consequence that the
money they make from teaching philosophy enables them to continue writing
it. Yet I have no desire to teach
philosophy and, even if I were wealthy, I doubt very much that I would want to
confine myself exclusively to writing it either, since I value the creative
potentials of literature too highly.
And, conversely, I value thought too highly to be content with limiting
it to a literary guise and diluting it in the interests of plot,
characterization, description, etc.
Besides, you can never get to the ...'
His digital watch suddenly bleeping
'June the nineteenth,' he muttered to himself a moment before
the curtain of sleep drew across his waking consciousness and plunged him from
thoughts about his dinner invitation with the Searles
into the dreamful depths of his unconscious.
It was now June 14th.