PART ONE: ESSAYS ON A DUALISTIC PHILOSOPHY
THE INTERDEPENDENCE
OF OPPOSITES: Work and play, love and hate, day and night, up and down, north
and south, big and small, high and low, pleasure and pain, man and woman, sun
and moon, yes and no, right and wrong, good and evil, health and sickness, in
and out, hard and soft, hot and cold, old and new, war and peace, quick and
slow, young and old, life and death, awake and asleep, rich and poor, tragic
and comic, for and against, truth and illusion, etc.
The duality of life would seem to be an
indisputable fact, a condition not permitting any serious refutation. For what happens when we isolate the word
'big', say, from the existence of its antithesis, 'small'? - Simply that the
word in question ceases to be meaningful.
By itself and totally isolated from the word 'small', our adjective is
reduced to a sound, the simple basis of a new word. We could speak of a big bird, a big
house, or a big garden but, not knowing what 'big' meant, we would be
none the wiser.
Thus we can see how absolutely
interdependent the words 'big' and 'small' really are, how they can only serve
a useful function when used in a mutual relationship. Once the polarities have been established,
however, it is then possible to conclude a bird 'big' in relation to a speck of
dust but 'small' in relation to a man; 'small' in relation to a house but 'big'
in relation to a moth, and so on.
It should therefore follow that unless
we accept the dualities of life as being interrelated, part of a larger whole,
and even, in a limited sense, the key to the metaphysical nature of reality, we
shall be perpetually deluding ourselves.
In other words, without hate there can be no love, without death no
life, without sadness no happiness, without pain no pleasure, without evil no
good, without illusion no truth, without realism no naturalism, and without
materialism no idealism.
Thus it can be assumed that a society
which strives to remove what it regards as a detrimental or undesirable
antithesis to a given ideal condition or concept ... is inevitably letting
itself in for a lot of futile and pointless labour. A tolerable world isn't a place where things
don't go wrong or where conditions are always pleasant, people happy, work
agreeable, and health unimpaired; for that, believe it or not, would soon prove
to be quite an intolerable one. But in
order that people may experience pleasant conditions, a degree of happiness, a sense of
purpose, and the joys of good health, a tolerable world will also include
correlative experience of unpleasant conditions, sadness, absurdity, and
sickness - to name but a handful of possibilities.
Hence when a person is feeling sad, he
ought to face-up to the reality of his situation by accepting its rightful
place and thereby bearing with it as a sort of passport to the possibility of
subsequent happiness. Indeed, if he is
something of a philosopher, and can sufficiently detach himself from his immediate
sadness for a few seconds, he may even think along such lines as: 'Without this
moment or hour of sadness, what happiness could I possibly expect today?' In doing so, he will be acknowledging the
validity of what might popularly be described as a means to a desirable end.
Naturally, I don't mean to imply that
people should think like this when inflicted with depressing circumstances,
but simply that they should learn to acquiesce in their various uncongenial
moods without vainly endeavouring to fight shy of them. For the trickery too often advocated by
people who foolishly strive to rid themselves of an unhappy mood, as though
secretly afraid to 'pay their dues', strikes me as little more than a species
of intellectual perversion. If we were
really supposed to lead one-sided lives, life would have been considerably
different to begin with, and it is doubtful that man would have conceived of
the dual concepts of Heaven and Hell, concepts which, on a more concrete level,
are clearly relative to life on this earth, and to a life, moreover, which
prohibits man from ever dedicating himself to the one at the total exclusion of
the other!
Therefore it can be deduced from the
aforementioned contentions that man's fundamental nature is typified by its
capacity for experiencing seemingly contradictory phenomena, viz. happiness and
sadness, good and evil, truth and illusion, which, if he is to do justice to
both himself and his kind, should be accepted and cultivated according to his
individual or innate disposition.
An author, for example, who may well be
'great' by dint of the fact that he accepts himself as a whole man, should
reconcile himself to the logical contradictions, cynical statements, brash
generalizations, callous accusations, superficial appreciations, cultivated
vanities, dogmatic assertions, etc., which frequently appear in his writings
(and constitute manifestations of his negative, or evil, side), in order to
safeguard his integrity as both a man and a
writer.
THE
CONFLICT OF OPPOSITES: My philosophy is neither optimistic nor pessimistic but
a subtle combination of both optimism and pessimism. Perhaps this respect for duality, this
acceptance of polarity, entitles it to be regarded as a metaphysics drawn
primarily from life itself rather than imposed upon it by the whims or perversions
of the human mind. Of course, its author
is aware that he may think optimistically whilst experiencing a good mood and
pessimistically whilst in the grip of a bad mood. But these separate inclinations are well
suited to the purposes of this philosophy.
For example, if he should one moment
secretly pronounce, after the fashion of Schopenhauer, that life is inherently
bad because there is too much suffering and not enough pleasure in it, he will
subsequently reflect, when the time and mood are propitious, that his previous
oracular pronouncement was largely attributable to the persistence of a bad
mood and/or uncongenial circumstances; that life was only 'bad' because he had
been in a negative frame-of-mind, had set up a chain of negative reactions and
accordingly dismissed optimism in the name of suffering, thereby passing
judgement in a thoroughly one-sided manner.
If, however, he should sometime
pronounce, after the fashion of Gide, that life is
inherently good and bubbles over with joy, pleasure, intelligence, etc., he
will later reflect, doubtless when the time and mood have shifted down a gear
or two, that his previous oracular pronouncement was largely attributable to
the prevalence of a good mood and/or congenial circumstances; that life was
only 'good' because he had been in a positive frame-of-mind, had set up a chain
of positive reactions and accordingly dismissed pessimism or, rather, affirmed
optimism in the name of wellbeing, thereby passing judgement in a no-less
thoroughly one-sided manner.
The claim that life is therefore both
good and bad, according to the context of the occasion or circumstances of
the individual, is doubtless a proposition that most fair-minded people would
be prepared to accept. But to proclaim,
like some philosophers, that life is either good or bad is surely to
misrepresent or slander it in such a way as to render oneself contemptible to
the more realistic spirits of this world!
Let it be hoped that we dualists can see life on fairer terms than they
did.
THE
NECESSARY ILLUSION: Just as one must know one's truths if they are to remain
valid as truths, so one must remain ignorant of one's illusions if they are to
remain illusions. Whenever the spell of
an illusion is broken one automatically becomes disillusioned, which is to say
somewhat saddened by the realization that what one formerly took to be the
truth wasn't really true at all but, rather, a misconception on one's
part. Thus, by way of compensation, the
shattered illusion then becomes a kind of negative truth, in that one can now
see through it and thereby establish a truer opinion on the subject. So, in a sense, one's illusions are all sham
truths until one becomes disillusioned.
But this realization, this process of
creeping disillusionment, doesn't automatically mean that one is steadily
getting closer to absolute truth, that one is 'cutting down' on one's illusions
and consequently converting the knowledge of their fallacies into relative
truth while simultaneously safeguarding one's inherent or acquired grasp of
truth. For as everything exists in
polarity, so must the newly acquired disillusionment subsequently make way for
other illusions which replace those one possessed at the time of becoming
disillusioned with a particular illusion, in order to maintain the balance of
opposites.
A philosopher who categorically asserts
his will to truth at any price, and thereupon declares himself to be the sworn
enemy of illusion, is, unwittingly, the victim of an illusion which presupposes
that truth can be acquired without a constant metaphysical price - namely of simultaneously maintaining and
acquiescing in illusions which must, of necessity, enter into his work from
time to time, thereby preventing the ultimate realization of his notably
idealistic ambitions.
THE
LEGITIMACY OF STUPIDITY: As each person retains his capacity for truth and illusion
throughout life, so, likewise, does each person retain his capacity for
cleverness and stupidity. That this is a
just condition hardly needs proving; for were he not subject to the experience
of both tendencies, he would have little or no prospect of maintaining
either. Hence his illusion guarantees
the continual existence of his truth, his stupidity the continual existence of
his cleverness.
To lament, however, over the realization
that even one's favourite philosophers, novelists, and poets display periodic
manifestations of illusion or stupidity is, willy-nilly, to display one's own
illusion or stupidity, since these authors must also be subject to the metaphysical
coercion of the human spirit and therefore be equally incapable of ultimately
transcending its dualism. Were a few of
them to remain wholly consistent with one's own mode of thinking, were even one
of them to do so, there would surely be reasonable grounds for assuming that
the impossible had come to pass, that one had come face-to-face with one's
double and somehow acquired exactly the same truths and illusions as had
previously been recorded by a man who hadn't so much as even suspected one's existence.
Consequently, it will be no great
surprise or hardship to an enlightened reader when he eventually comes to
realize that his attitude towards each of his 'favourite' writers is bound to
be ambivalent, to entail both agreement and
disagreement, approval and disapproval, faith and scepticism. For as there has never been two people
exactly alike in the world, so it is inevitable that one man's meat will
continue to be another man's poison.
Even the greatest writers must, of
necessity, be subject to the continuous prevalence of antithetical values, if
they are to live as men and not degenerate into lopsided monsters! The pernicious idea of someone's being 'all
too human' simply because he makes mistakes, acts stupidly, suffers from
ignorance, fosters certain misleading arguments, etc., is clearly founded upon
a superficial grasp of human reality (as though the person accusing another of
being 'all too human' on account of such failings wasn't, in reality, 'all too
human' himself for failing to detect their ultimate legitimacy!). But being 'all too human' is really an
indication of human perfection rather than of imperfection. For a man who never made mistakes, never
committed an illusion or absurdity to paper, would be
highly imperfect - a sort of computerized robot, and therefore no man at all!
MORE
POSITIVE THAN NEGATIVE: If illusions are only illusions insofar as man is
basically unaware of their illusory nature, can it not be deduced from this
that his real evil, stupidity, illogicality, injustice,
etc., only come to the fore when he is basically unaware of the fact, not when
he wills it? In other words, because the
life-force is essentially positive, because everything arises in nature to
fulfil itself, is not man's deepest inclination likewise to seek the positive
rather than the negative, to aspire towards his individual truth, goodness,
cleverness, profundity, logic, justice, etc. as an inherent inclination
rather than towards their opposites which, being negative, are things that he
is fundamentally unconscious of, i.e. in the sense that one is unconscious of
an illusion until one becomes disillusioned with it?
Men aspire towards truth while still
besotted with illusions, towards goodness while still fostered on evil, towards
social order while still subject to the chaos of their individual lives. They often think they are doing the right
thing when it subsequently transpires to being wrong; they often consider
themselves to be acting justly when, to those upon whom they have acted, the
consequences are manifestly unjust; they often imagine themselves to be doing
good when, to those who are the recipients of their goodness, the main
consequences are evil. It is only out of
ignorance that they act wrongly at all, but it is a necessary ignorance which
ultimately transpires to being justified, a fact which may well explain why the
dying Christ gave utterance to the words: 'Father, forgive them for they know
not what they do', and why Nietzsche asserted: 'Man always acts rightly'.
Thus man is largely ignorant of his real
evil, stupid, illogical, and superficial tendencies because his innate positivity generally leads him to treat every action as a
good, no matter what its nature. He
doesn't attack others, whether verbally or physically, simply for the pleasure
of doing so but primarily because he feels justified in doing so,
because, by a quirk of fate, context, experience, or life-history, he feels
that to be the right thing to do under the prevailing circumstances.
From the viewpoint of the people he has
attacked, however, his actions are almost certain to be condemned as evil. And for the very sound reason that whenever
someone acts cruelly to us it offends our prevailing sense of goodness, causes
us to feel outraged, engenders negative feelings, and is automatically
translated into an evil act. Because it
offends us we recognize it as an evil action, instinctively regard its
perpetrator in a negative light, and straightaway succumb to a misconception,
viz. that the aggressor is inevitably in the wrong. But even if it may appear so from our point
of view, this is insufficient to make it so from his and, consequently, each
side acting according to their lights, the antagonism continues.
If, therefore, man aspires towards
goodness without ever becoming wholly good, whatever he does from ignorance or
spite, wounded vanity or a sense of outraged innocence, the warrior impulse or
self-defence, which can be interpreted as evil, can never make him wholly
bad. And the same may be held true of
all the other polar attributes as well.
He will aspire to acquiring nothing but the truth without ever freeing
himself from illusions. He will
endeavour to boast of his cleverness without ever managing to completely rid
himself of stupidity. But let us not add
to that stupidity by bewailing the existence of these indispensable antitheses!
BOTH
POSITIVE AND NEGATIVE: In speaking of antitheses we almost invariably put the
positive attribute first and the negative one second, as the following short
list should serve to confirm: good and bad, truth and illusion, pleasure and
pain, happiness and sadness, life and death, light and dark, love and hate, day
and night, heaven and hell, man and woman, boy and girl, rich and poor,
beautiful and ugly, high and low, yes and no, etc. To say that man's nature is good would hardly
constitute the truth; for in order to have any goodness at all he must have
sufficient evil from which to create it, he must have one tendency balanced by
another.
Granted that man is neither good nor
evil but both good and evil (which should not be
confounded with a combination of each), one can nevertheless assert that the positivity of goodness generally leads him to aspire
towards the Good rather than towards its opposite which, being negative, can
only take second place, as it were, to the 'leading string'. Thus, as an inherently positive phenomenon,
life is geared towards goodness, but to a goodness which can only be maintained
with the aid of evil.
Yes, Gide was
right to contend that man was born for happiness, in that man's strongest
predilection is to aspire towards the positivity of
happiness rather than towards the negativity of sadness. Admittedly, this happiness ultimately depends
upon the intermittent prevalence of sadness.
But sadness can never become the 'leading string', or man's principal
objective. For the essential positivity of our being does not induce us to pine for
sadness when we are happy but, on the contrary, to immerse ourselves in
happiness as if it were a natural condition, as if we had found our spiritual
home. And this same positivity
eventually goads us out of our sadness by causing us to pine for happiness.
Now according to Schopenhauer - who is
virtually antithetical to Gide - happiness is merely
the absence of pain and thus a negative thing, whereas pain itself he saw as
very positive, a thing upon which life mostly depends. To follow Schopenhauer's reasoning here isn't
particularly easy, but it should be fairly apparent to most people that he was somewhat
mistaken. For as the accepted antithesis
to pleasure, not happiness, pain is really anything but a positive thing, since
we aren't driven by our essential being to pain but to pleasure, so pleasure
must be the positive attribute and pain the negative one. Not being content to muddle these antitheses,
however, Schopenhauer also saw fit to reverse their qualities and thus invest
pain with a positive attribute - a thing hardly guaranteed to enlighten one or
advance truth in this respect!
So do I therefore advise people against
reading Schopenhauer? No, I don't, since
there is much value to be gleaned from a serious perusal of his major works,
including The World as Will and Representation. What I do advise people against, however, is
being put off philosophers like Schopenhauer on account of their logical fallacies. There is
not a philosopher on earth who could escape criticism for one reason or
another, since there isn't one whose integrity as a human being exempts him
from error. Where one believes the
contrary, it can be assumed that one has been deceived by the mistaken
assertions of the philosopher concerned without in the least suspecting the
fact. No man is born to tell the whole
truth and nothing but the truth. Yet no
man is born subject to nothing but illusions, either!
A man who is prepared to give his
favourite philosopher's principal target of abuse (Hegel in the case of
Schopenhauer) a fair hearing or reading would strike this philosopher as more
enlightened than one whose willingness to do so has been severely compromised,
if not completely negated, by too slavish an adherence to him.
NEITHER
ANGEL NOR DEMON: We are neither angels nor demons but that compromise between
them which is called man. It is as
impossible to prevent man from doing evil as it is to prevent him from doing
good. Even those people who imagine themselves to be what D.H. Lawrence described as 'lopsided
on the side of the angels' are undoubtedly deluded in supposing themselves to
be wholly good. How can anyone living in
this world be wholly good when our metaphysical condition requires that we
function according to the dictates of polar influences, and not degenerate into
some kind of moral eunuch hardly capable of killing a fly?
Indeed, when one realizes that not even
the saints can have been wholly good, what chance does anyone else have of
eliminating their evil tendencies and thereby transforming themselves into
something which transcends our physiological coercion to accept both good and
evil as equally important, equally interdependent, and, above all, equally
inescapable? One might as well try
squeezing a camel through the eye of a needle.
But how, then, do I define good and
evil? Simply by
relating that which proceeds from positive feelings to goodness and,
conversely, that which proceeds from negative feelings to evil. Thus a genuine smile is a good, a genuine
scowl an evil. Pleasure is good, pain
evil. Love is good, hate evil. Hope is good, fear evil.
Incidentally, one is indulging in evil
every time one complains about anything, since the tendency to complain
inevitably engenders negative feelings: anger, resentment, fear, or hate. One drops a hammer on one's foot and one
experiences pain. Pain is a physical
evil which causes one to curse. Cursing
is the inevitable mental evil which results from pain. One's evil is justified.
NO GOOD
WITHOUT EVIL: Just take a look at the history of philosophy, at the number of
philosophers from Plato to Kant who have designated men as either good or evil
without apparently realizing that a 'good man' or a 'bad man' can never exist,
never, that is, so long as men are compelled to conform to their individual
standards of polar exchange, which is to say so long as they live.
Naturally, certain men appear good
compared with lesser men, whose basic intellectual limitations, social
hardships, and poor breeding lead them to commit actions which a more fortunate
individual could only condemn. But this
is far from saying that those greater men are not susceptible to evils
themselves, and to evils, moreover, which conform to their class, occupation,
age, and physiological coercion as men.
No man can call himself good simply
because his higher intelligence, better standard of living, and finer breeding
enable him to refrain from what might broadly be described as the evil
tendencies of a lower class. It is not
enough simply to avoid torturing or murdering people, openly ridiculing,
cursing, raping, or fighting them; for one can usually do that without too
great a strain upon oneself if one is of a sufficiently independent and noble
turn-of-mind.
No, to become a 'good man' one would
have to give-up reading certain books, say, murder mysteries; give-up listening
to certain albums, say, hard rock; give-up watching certain films, say, horror
videos; stop thinking certain thoughts, seeing certain people, taking certain
sides, having certain beliefs, saying certain things, feeling certain emotions,
dreaming certain dreams, indulging certain fantasies, etc., and one would have
to give them up and/or or stop them to such an extent, to such a point of
exclusivity, that there would be very little left one could do!
But would this drastic strategy for the
eradication of personal evil in one's life really make one good, holy, saved? No, it wouldn't! For if one could get rid
of all one's evil inclinations, there would be nothing good to fall back on,
there would be no good left within oneself, since one's good inclinations only
thrive with the assistance of their opposites, not without them! One would simply exist in a manner
approximating to that in which certain Oriental sages have traditionally
aspired to existing: neither a good man nor a bad man but effectively a thing,
devoid of life, sitting under the branches of a tree all day with the
imperturbability of a rock.
Thus wherever the healthy tendency of a
will to life is concerned, there must always be
varying degrees of good and evil.
Conversely, wherever the unhealthy tendency of a will to antilife (death-in-life) is concerned, there can be neither
good nor evil but an existence betokening death - a sort of blasphemy against
life.
ONLY PARTLY
WISE: The world has never produced a single 'wise man', since the world is not
geared to wise men but to men, who can only be wise with the aid of their
folly. In order for a man to be capable
of wisdom at all, he must also be foolish.
For unless he is, there will be nothing for him to create his wisdom
from, since he will lack the polarity that guarantees it. Even Nietzsche, wise man that he seems to
have been on various occasions, was also a fool.
Do you disbelieve me, you 'wise' ones,
you who grew out of folly? No matter,
your disbelief will reinstate it. I am
foolish, you are foolish, we are all foolish, but because of this we are all
intermittently wise as well!
Indeed, whenever I see men aspiring to
be wiser than everyone else, men who are usually afraid to live ... from fear
that they should somehow transgress their wisdom, I see them for the half-fools
they really are. They would even go so
far, some of them, as to pretend to having acquired a victory over folly,
which, in reality, would also be a victory over wisdom; though they, being such
half-fools, couldn't be expected to know that!
But there you are: that, in simple
light-hearted language, is fairly typical of the human condition, of that very
logical condition which induces us to be wise intermittently rather than
permanently, so that, to revert to D.H. Lawrence again, we can avoid being at
'a perpetual funeral'.
PERFECT OR
IMPERFECT: What, in the final analysis, is the chief distinction between a
perfect and an imperfect man? Is any man
perfect at all, or is human imperfection the eternal rule, the condition to
which all men must be reduced if they are to survive?
Some people would have us believe in the
moral imperfection of man as though it were an indisputable fact, one derived
from his 'sinful' nature and consequent need of salvation.
Others would contend that man is
mentally imperfect, and that his frequent mistakes, stupidities,
superficialities, illusions, contradictions, deceptions, etc., emphasize this
condition all too plainly.
Yet others, probably a minority, would
contend that man is usually mentally perfect, but that only a small number of
men are ever permitted to actually realize their perfection, the rest of
mankind being reduced, through economic and political tyrannies, to a state of
spiritual, moral, intellectual, and social deprivation.
Finally, there would be those who,
whilst acknowledging that man is usually mentally and physically perfect, would
contend that some men are either born or become mentally or physically
imperfect: that a person with a spastic body, a crippled limb, a mental
disorder, or a heart disease is undoubtedly imperfect when compared with
somebody whose body and mind are hale.
Yes, this latter case is probably more
relevant to most people living today than are any of the others. But let us take a closer look, if only from
curiosity, at what these other cases are saying.
To begin with, the church in virtually
all of its denominational manifestations, though especially the Catholic one,
believes quite emphatically that man is a sinful and, hence, imperfect
creature. The clerical servants of the
church believe in the imperfection of man, in what they take to be his
perpetual backsliding into sinful habits like sex and alcohol. Through regularly confessing these sins to a
priest, a man may secure forgiveness from God.
But, if he is to be logically consistent, he must confess everything,
not forget to mention anything or allow himself to overlook something which he
might foolishly regard as trivial and therefore hardly a sin at all. For God, being omniscient,
can still see into his mind and will know if there was anything which should
have been confessed to but which, for one reason or another, was overlooked.
However that may be, both the Catholic
and, to a lesser extent, the Protestant clergy believe in man's imperfection
and, thus, perpetual need of redemption.
They have, it seems to me, a somewhat partial view of man. They do not want to accept him in the round
but only in the part, with particular reference to his 'sinful nature'. For if they once accepted the dualistic
integrity of man, their conception of his imperfection could soon dissolve
under pressure of the following fact - namely that man can only be good because of his
intermittent evil, since his sinfulness, whatever form it may take, is
fundamentally the sole guarantor of his goodness.
But such an acceptance of man's whole
nature would not be to the lasting advantage of the clergy! For if a man's good actions (those stemming
from positive feelings) are fundamentally dependent upon the periodic manifestation
of his evil actions (those stemming from negative feelings), how can one
possibly maintain that he should strive to eradicate as many of the latter as
possible or, alternatively, confess what wrong he has done in order to be
forgiven? Undoubtedly a ticklish problem
for the clergy to address, particularly since their justification as priests
largely depends upon the contrary idea which, if pushed far enough, tends to
divide a man against himself, making him hostile towards his dual nature.
However, it is not for us humble
philosophers to attempt to change their views, since that would certainly be to
overlook the power of tradition and entrenched dogma. As a freethinker living in a country which
permits free thought, I shall simply put my case before the public tribunal and
pass on.
Which leads me to our second conception
of man's imperfection - namely to the assumption that his periodic mistakes,
stupidities, superficialities, contradictions, etc., are all clear examples of
it. Indeed, it is not only clergymen who
maintain this belief, but people from just about every walk of life. If they are figure clerks, then a wrong
addition or misplaced numeral is obviously, if regrettably, another instance of
human imperfection. If they are
teachers, then an inability to trace a certain date, name, or reference in
their memories may subsequently lead them to draw similar conclusions, though
not in front of the class! If they are
philosophers, the assertion of a particular contention that they imagined was
true, but which subsequently transpired to being false, will probably trigger
off a similar barrage of self-condemnation.
In truth, the numbers of possible instances are endless, though they all
point in the same direction - namely, the assumption that our respective
mistakes, failings, delusions, etc., are conclusive proof of human
imperfection.
But is man a computer, we may object,
that he should be exempted from error?
Is his evolution directed towards some future mastery of himself, some
grand epoch when the likelihood of a wrong addition, a memory failure, or a
fallacious contention will be rendered impossible? If so, then I must confess to having serious
misgivings about man's future! I can well
appreciate his use and development of computers, but I do not believe that he
should subsequently become computerized as well!
If a man makes occasional mistakes, then
let us at least have the insight to assume that he didn't commit them on
purpose (for no genuine mistake can be made intentionally) but, rather, that
they happened in accordance with a deeper law of his being, which effectively
proclaimed the justification of an occasional mistake as a means of maintaining
his overall efficiency and general ability to avoid making mistakes at certain
other times.
And the same may be held true, I
suspect, of his many other failings, each of which exists primarily to protect
and maintain his overall efficiency. So
I do not believe that a man should necessarily be classified as imperfect because
he makes mistakes from time to time.
Classify him imperfect if he never makes mistakes, has no faults, is
without stupidity, superficiality, illusion, or contradiction, if you
like. But the condemnation of his natural
condition is something of which I do not see the sense.
However, let us now progress to the
third possibility which, as we saw earlier, concerns the alleged perfection of
the Few and the imperfection of the Many.
To some extent, it is of course fair to suggest that most people are crushed
or moulded by fate into a particular way of life which can only be described as
constrictive. They may be obliged to
earn a living in uncongenial circumstances.
Their health is gradually undermined, their imagination becomes
increasingly circumscribed, their senses are dulled, their intellect becomes
progressively more stultified, their opinions become stereotyped, their spirit
atrophies, and their willpower, initiative, and self-confidence sustain an
irrecoverable loss. Yes, it is probably
fair to suggest that these sorts of misfortunes have befallen a great many
people; though it is probably also fair to suggest that a majority of them
don't seem to worry very much about it.
After awhile they take their condition for granted, not really being in a
position to do much else.
Indeed, for some people stultification
of one degree or another isn't at all a bad thing; at least it prevents them
from worrying or suffering too much in consequence of an acute awareness of
their deprivation. But, for others, it
is virtually the end of the road, a ghastly horror from which they recoil, as
from a poisonous snake. Probably no-one
can escape a certain amount of intellectual stultification, dulling of senses,
atrophying of spirit, etc., even under the best of circumstances. Yet there are those who regard such a
prospect or actuality with great dismay, much as though people were thereby
rendered imperfect and consequently unable to live as they should. It is a great evil of society, they claim,
that so many people should be crushed down for the sake of a minority who are
enabled to live to the maximum of their ability. It isn't right, they say, that a majority of
people should be compelled to live a sort of living death for the sake of a
privileged few.
Undoubtedly, this is the kind of
viewpoint one would ordinarily associate with certain types of communist
revolutionaries and social agitators.
But I cannot personally grant it much credence. It seems to me that those who think like this
are insufficiently aware of the temperamental, social, psychological, and
intellectual differences between people.
A person who does what you or I might regard as a dull job isn't
necessarily worse off than one whose job is more exciting. It depends entirely upon the nature of the
person concerned. For if one isn't very
intelligent to begin with, then a dull job is not only the best thing, it is
the only thing, and anything else would be unsuitable. But if one is pretty
intelligent to begin with, then, conversely, a dull job would be
unsuitable. Now one cannot seriously
contend that a person born to a dull task has been deprived of an opportunity
to realize his perfection through, say, one or other of the fine arts, higher
sports, or professions, when it wasn't given him to realize his perfection in
that way. Yet this is precisely what
certain communist revolutionaries and social agitators are apt to overlook,
whether intentionally or unintentionally, when they speak in terms of social
inequality.
Frankly, one cannot really contend that
a majority of men must lead imperfect lives for the sake of a lucky few, when
the lives they lead are the only possible ones that they could lead
anyway. Is a man to be pitied because he
wasn't born with the potential of a poet, musician, writer, artist, or
philosopher when, by accident or design, he was born with the potential of a
carpenter, builder, plumber, tailor, or car mechanic instead? Would you demand of car mechanics that they
become playwrights in order to realize their perfection to the full,
irrespective of the fact that they may prefer being car mechanics and can
better realize their perfection in that way?
No, nobody but the most unreasoning of
persons would demand any such thing! For
there are as many ways of realizing one's perfection as there are people, and
what would suit one type of person could well prove the ruination of
another.
So I do not believe that people who are
unable to discover themselves in the more creative or authoritative spheres of
life should be considered unfortunate for having to do comparatively mundane or
servile things instead. Each man has his
own problems to live with, whether he be a king or a
beggar. Indeed, there is at work in this
world a vast levelling process which adds something here only to subtract
something there, which renders every
occupation, no matter what its nature, subject to certain drawbacks,
limitations, or hardships, and no-one in his right mind would really pretend
otherwise, no matter how unfortunate he thought he was, or how many uncongenial
experiences accrued to his particular occupation. Even in the most boring office jobs one may
be able to converse with one's fellow workers on occasion - a thing an artist,
writer, philosopher, or poet is seldom if ever in a position to do, bearing in
mind his solitary circumstances. But
even boring work is better than no work at all, and most people would rather be
bored at work than bored or, worse still, lonely and without purpose from being
out of work.
Thus, in returning to my original theme,
I do not agree with the notion that society requires a large percentage of
imperfect men in order that a small percentage of the total population should
be able to develop their potential to the full and thereby realize their
perfection. Where a man is
insufficiently intelligent or talented to do a highly skilled or responsible
job, he has absolutely no business doing it.
Where, on the contrary, he is sufficiently intelligent or
talented, then he will do his best to get himself accepted for it and,
eventually, he will probably succeed.
Whether he becomes a bookbinder, a sculptor, doctor, judge, architect,
or novelist, whatever he does will be right for him. There could be no question of coaxing him out
of it. For if all men
were born to do the same thing, the world would collapse in no time. A few billion artists would spell the
ruination of art, a few billion doctors the ruination of medicine, and nobody
would be able to realize or even discover his perfection at all.
But that a man should consider himself a
failure because he is not a poet or an artist or a musician ... is as stupid
and illogical as, for the sake of argument, it would be for a tortoise to
consider itself a failure because it is not a hare, or a mouse to consider
itself a failure because it is not a cat!
Let a man do what he can do as well as possible, let him live according
to his capacity, and he will soon discover his true worth. A person can be as satisfied in the humblest
or lowest-paid job as dissatisfied in the most exalted or highest-paid
one. It entirely depends upon the nature
and circumstances of the person concerned.
But let us now leave the above aspect of
the problem and turn, finally, to the more obvious criterion of perfection and
imperfection: the difference, namely, between a person with a sound, healthy
body and mind, and one, by contrast, who is afflicted with some serious mental
or bodily deprivation. Here we do touch
upon the essential distinction, the glaring inequality, between the normal and
the abnormal, the healthy and the sick.
The instances of human imperfection are
numerous, but they all revolve around severe mental or physical anomalies. Schizophrenia, mental retardation, and
various forms of advanced insanity are typical of the former; blindness,
deafness, deformed or crippled limbs, obesity, and various internal
malfunctions are typical of the latter.
But, whatever the anomaly may happen to be, there lies the basis of human imperfection. It has nothing whatsoever to do with 'sinning
against the Light' (unless, however, one's 'sins' are of such a grave and
frequent character that there is a strong justification for regarding them as
the direct consequence of some mental or physical disorder). Neither does it have anything to do with
making mistakes (unless, however, one does little else). Still less does it have to do with the type
of work one does (unless, however, one would rather not do any work at all and
simply rot away in sordid isolation).
No, the phenomenon of human imperfection is always chiefly characterized
by such anomalies as those to which I have referred, never or rarely by
anything else. For if
you are reasonably sound in body and mind, you are as perfect as you need to
be. And a 'perfect man' isn't
usually the exception; he is the rule!
PERFECT AND
IMPERFECT: You claim, my critical reader, that we are not perfect because we
make mistakes, commit stupid acts, suffer from ignorance, succumb to the flesh,
make war on others, twist truth into illusion, condemn others for things we
sometimes do ourselves, fail to live up to our ideals, give way to sloth,
contradict ourselves, forget what we ought to have remembered, and remember
what we ought really to have forgotten.
Why, then, do I pretend otherwise?
But I don't pretend, I know otherwise.
I know, for example, that one cannot be good without also, though at
other times, being bad, since one's goodness depends upon periodic evil
(irrespective of the fact that one may often be quite unaware of exactly what
this evil is or what form it takes). I
know, too, how important stupidity is in maintaining my intermittent
cleverness, how profundity only thrives because of superficiality, wisdom
because of folly, truth because of illusion.
Without my body I would have no spirit, and without food for this body
my spirit would be sorely troubled; in fact, it would be sickly preoccupied
with my body, and then, in a sense, I would be quite imperfect. For spirituality only thrives with the aid of
its opposite, not without it!
Oh, you say, but there are ugly people,
retarded people, spastic people, crippled people, stunted people, blind people,
and many other kinds of unfortunate people who, even given your questionable
criteria, are anything but perfect. What
do I say to that?
Yes, I reply, you are right. And that is precisely where real human
imperfection lies. It isn't so much in
what one does as in what one is. A
hunchbacked dwarf, for example, is clearly quite imperfect by normal standards,
as is a cripple, a deaf-mute, or a spastic.
We are usually somewhat disturbed by the imperfections of an ugly face
or, alternatively, of a face covered in sores, boils, pimples, scars, etc.,
and, to be perfectly honest with ourselves, we have every reason to feel
disturbed. But, since most of us have
some failings along these lines, since most of us can point to some physical
malady or deformity which regularly troubles us in life, is it not evident that
a majority of us are both perfect and imperfect,
and that our perfections, far from being completely independent of our imperfections,
are dependent upon them for their continuous participation.
But now I am confusing you, I hear you
object. First I speak of human
perfection, then of imperfection, and finally, to complicate matters still
further, of perfection and imperfection. Surely there is a contradiction here? Surely there is some fundamental
misconception here?
No, not at all! For if we have to pay for our truths with the
coinage of illusion, can it not be contended that, except in those
above-mentioned unfortunate instances where physical imperfection is too
severe, our overall spiritual integrity, or perfection, must likewise be paid
for with the coinage of physical imperfection, whether this imperfection be
internal or external, transient or permanent, of the brain or of the body? If one man has an ugly face, another may have
a handsome one riddled with spots, boils, sores, etc. If one man is short-sighted, another may be
long-sighted. If one man has greasy
hair, another may have greasy skin. If
one man suffers from his lungs, another may suffer from his heart. If one man is too thin, another may be too
fat, and so on and so forth. The
instances of physical imperfection are many, but they all seem to point in the
same direction - namely the overall integrity of the spirit.
According, therefore, to this contention
we are both spiritually perfect and physically imperfect. When one is both clever
and stupid, wise and foolish, profound and superficial, logical and illogical,
etc., one is spiritually whole, integrated, perfect! When, however, one contemplates the anomalies
of the body (of which the brain is effectively a part), it is patently obvious
that, in a majority of cases, the body isn't perfect. For short-sightedness, B.O., greasy skin,
obesity, boils, warts, moles, cysts, sties, headaches, bone diseases, bladder
trouble, and the thousand-and-one other things which constitute physical
imperfection can't exactly reflect the same kind of integrity as is to be found
in the duality of the spirit, and so, not being able to establish the body's
perfection by the very fact of their existence, these imperfections must
indirectly contribute to the perfection of the spirit as the legitimate
polarity to it.
So a 'perfect man' should be one whose
physical imperfections contribute to his overall physico-spiritual
integrity, rather than one without any imperfections at all. It is only when his physical imperfections
are of such a magnitude as to detract from his overall physico-spiritual
integrity - as, for example, in the case of spastics - that one is really
justified in regarding him as 'imperfect'.
A NECESSARY
DOUBT: When a person says: 'We can have no certainties, no-one can be certain
about anything', he is unwittingly displaying his tendency to illusion,
ignorance, and stupidity. For were he
not inclined to this kind of self-deception, he would know that certainty and
doubt are antithetical, that the one cannot exist without the other and,
consequently, that there must be a
degree of certainty in the world.
When I say: 'Mr Smith is a man and Miss
Brown a woman', I am absolutely certain about the nature of their respective
genders. Even if I didn't possess the
concepts 'male' and 'female', I could still be confident that they looked
fundamentally different, and that would constitute a certainty. Similarly, when I say: 'The sun provides the
heat and light upon which the survival of natural life on this planet so
heavily depends' I am again expressing a certainty. Were I to call it a doubt, other people would
have sound reason to consider me mistaken.
But there are, of course, things about
which it is impossible to be certain, like changes in the weather, who we will
bump into on the pavement, what we will dream in our sleep, where we will be in
ten years' time, how much money we will waste over the next six months, and so
on. The doubts we have about these
'uncertainties' effectively enable us to be 'doubtless' about the various
certainties about which it is absolutely imperative to be certain. Otherwise one may eat the poison berry.
NO SHAM
WISDOM: This philosophy would indeed be vain, stupid, and meddlesome if,
instead of putting me on the path to enlightenment, it goaded me towards a
refutation of our natural tendencies, i.e. of being stupid, deluded, illogical,
unjust, sad, evil, presumptuous, superficial, etc., when the need or
inevitability of such tendencies was indisputably manifest. For me to set out on the path of endeavouring
to eliminate whatever idiosyncratic predilections for folly I may possess would
be the height of folly! To imagine
myself on the road to profundity by making an earnest endeavour to eliminate
what superficiality I may possess would likewise constitute a similar
absurdity, making me superficial rather than profound.
If knowledge is to serve any useful
purpose, it must free me from the constricting prevalence of false wisdom,
render me increasingly aware of the obligations imposed upon a healthy life,
and lift me above the intellectual fog invariably engulfing the technical
nature of wisdom, morality, religion, politics, art, truth, metaphysics, etc.,
which blinds so many people to the essence of reality. It is all very well for a man to seek wisdom,
to require of philosophy that it teach him how best to live. But if that wisdom subsequently conflicts
with his deepest predilections as a human being and thereby transpires to being
little more than a caricature of wisdom, a metaphysical misunderstanding, an
inversion of terminology, a mere shadow play, a medicine where there was no
sickness or, worse still, a sickness where there had been no ill-health, then
it were better that he dispensed with philosophical formulae altogether and
learnt to follow his natural inclinations again - the very inclinations which,
in the final analysis, constitute the real sagacity of life.
ONLY ABSURD
SOMETIMES: There are certain modern philosophers and writers, not least of all
from the so-called 'existentialist' school of thought, who regularly conspire
in contending life to be absurd and, consequently, an imposition one would be
better off without - a contention which does, in fact, engender sympathetic
connotations when, under the prevalence of various 'trying' circumstances, one
genuinely feels oneself to be plagued by a farce
and secretly longing for oblivion.
Regardless, however, of the periodic
validity and current prestige of this philosophy, it nevertheless occurs to me
that one doesn't normally feel life to be absurd when, for example, one settles
down to listen to some choice record, read a highly engrossing book, eat a
savoury meal, drink a delightful drink, watch an exciting film, sleep an
eventful dream, ponder a selection of enlightening thoughts, kiss a pretty
woman, or take a well-earned rest. For
the mind is usually too preoccupied with what one is doing at such times to be
in any way seriously concerned with the then-largely irrelevant notion of
absurdity. As a standing maxim, one
might conclude that when one is content, the notion of absurdity is strictly
taboo!
But life does, however, seem absurd
sometimes and, whether or not we like this fact, it is probably just as
well. For without the intermittent
prevalence of absurdity, how could one possibly be expected to take pleasure in
life's reasonableness? Without absurdity,
there would doubtless be no reasonableness, just as without illogicality
there would be no logic, without illusion no truth, and without sadness no
happiness. A book dedicated to the
hypothesis of an absurd existence would appear to be a somewhat one-sided and
essentially absurd book. Indeed, it
might even suggest a distinct tendency, on the part of its author, to incorrect
living!
NOT
ENTIRELY SANE: Our sanity depends upon the regular support of insanity. Why, you may occasionally wonder, do we act as
we do, rarely bothering to consider the essential nature of so many of our
activities, but mostly pursuing them as though blinded to their consequences,
unaware of their 'actualities', of how strange, diverse, and persistent they
usually are? Clearly, because we are
insane as well as sane, because it is natural for us to exploit our insanity in
the interests of our sanity, our unconscious mind in the interests of our
conscious mind. How on earth could we
dare to call ourselves 'sane' in the first place, without its antithesis to
support us and grant our sanity a reliable foundation? How could there possibly be any sanity
in any of us, without the aid of its opposite?
A 'sane man' per se can never exist.
Why, then, do we classify certain people
as insane if, to a certain extent, we are all mad? Simply because we are
largely ignorant of the matter? Possibly. But, more
probably, because we habitually associate insanity with notions of
incompatibility, irrelevance, superfluity, extreme eccentricity, unrelatedness, ostracism, delusions of grandeur, etc. A person who talks to himself is generally
considered mad because custom and common sense normally prohibit us from
following suit, since it would make us conspicuously anomalous in a world where
most people talk to others. When a man
persistently talks to himself in public places he not only draws attention to
himself, whether compassionately or critically, but he makes it difficult for
other people to communicate with him.
Thus he is regarded as a madman for having employed his sanity/insanity
relationship in a manner deemed to be incompatible with society's requirements,
instead of keeping it moored to an established norm like normal conversation,
thinking, reading, writing, humming, whistling, etc., according to accepted
standards of procedure. Yet the man who
talks to himself is probably no 'madder' than the one who thinks to himself;
his 'madness' is simply more conspicuous on account of its audible nature, which
might well indicate that the 'madman' in question is simply more extrovert or
less intellectual than the habitual thinker.
However, as for those who generally do
their best to 'keep in line' and remain fairly consistent with society's
demands and standards, which includes the great majority of people, we shall
continue to regard them as 'sane' without entirely believing it. For if they are to remain sane in the world's
eyes, they must continue to cultivate their insanity as before, i.e. by taking
things more or less for granted and keeping uncritical track of social
requirement, as effecting and pertaining to both themselves and society in
general.
As a sort of afterthought to the above,
it ought to be clearly understood that insanity (as represented here by an
unusual arrangement of the normal duality) and a mental breakdown are two
entirely different things, since a mind which literally ceases to function - as
in the cases of Baudelaire, Maupassant, and Nietzsche - should not be confused
with a mind which continues to function, albeit in a highly personal and
irregular way - as in the cases of Swift, de Nerval,
and Pound.
NOT
ENTIRELY INSANE: What is a 'madman' if not a being whose
sanity/insanity duality has ceased to be of any use to society and become a
hindrance rather than an aid? That we
are all mad to some extent is, I trust, a proven if not self-evident fact. For even the most heroic of us are regularly
susceptible to delusions, illogicalities,
stupidities, idiosyncratic anomalies, obsessions, fears, perversions, passions,
exaggerations, uncritical obedience, irrational conformity, etc., which rarely
fail to puzzle or startle us when we regain our critical discernment.
Fortunately, however, we usually learn
to live with our individual oddities, just as we learn to live with their
several manifestations in other people's lives, to regard them as a fact of
life, to forget about them whenever possible, and to get on with our daily
tasks not only as a means of securing a living and keeping ourselves
preoccupied, but also of regulating our actions and keeping ourselves on the
rails, as it were, of society's track.
The three things one doesn't do is to question their validity, worry
about their consequences, or set about trying to regulate them in a manner
guaranteed to disturb the natural polarity of sanity/insanity within. Living with the brakes on is like driving a
car too slowly and carefully. Sooner or
later there may well be a serious accident and a screaming neurotic will be
dragged out from where, previously, there had been a stable, healthy and normal
human being.
What, then, is this
person who no longer is of any great use to society but must be kept under
regular supervision or, alternatively, left to fend for himself
in a world where, at best, he can only expect to do very menial jobs? Is he someone who is all insanity and no
sanity, someone who has tipped the polar balance so far in favour of insanity
that little or no sanity remains discernible?
Could any man be all of one thing to the total exclusion of its opposite
under any circumstances, that is to say under any permanent as opposed to
transient circumstances? No, I do not
believe so! For to be
all of one thing would be to destroy it, to cancel the polarity and thereby
render the remaining side without definition, substance, or reality as an
integral component in a dual relationship.
Thus if, as generally understood,
madness is essentially a question of degree, it is by no means a total
obliteration of sanity but, rather, an expression of the basic duality in a manner
deemed to be incompatible with average standards of behaviour. This, I believe, suffices to explain why
those deemed to be insane are usually unaware of their madness, take matters
for granted, and are more inclined to consider others insane by their standards
than to accept the standards which have been imposed upon them by society at
large.
Consequently, to remain sane in
society's eyes one must play the game as broadly understood by the majority, no
matter what that game may happen to be, in order to remain intelligible within
the confines of a given context and thereby pass muster as a being related to
others. A surrealist painter will be
considered sane so long as he continues to function efficiently within his
particular sphere of creative activity and doesn't foolishly encroach upon
other, unrelated spheres. He may, for
example, paint pictures of elephants with telephones on their heads, women with
moustaches, beetroots with legs, or mice wearing pyjamas. But as soon as he seriously contends that
people should dress their pet mice, bankers order telephones for lunch, or
office clerks stand on their hands all day instead of doing any work, he is
likely to be judged insane for having stepped out of his professional line and
made a public nuisance of himself.
Now if it is perfectly natural to refer
to a man who talks to himself or insults strangers in the street as a 'madman',
it nonetheless ought to be understood that, in the final analysis, there is
really no such thing as a mad man, any more than there is really such a thing
as a sane man, a good man, an evil man, a happy man, a sad man, etc., since men
are always a tension of polarities, a meeting-point of opposed though mutually
interdependent tendencies, and therefore cannot be wholly one thing or
another. Naturally, we are compelled to
simplify things, to define them in a way that will be intelligible to the vast
majority of people at any given time.
But from a philosophical standpoint, wherein the mind is determined to
make a conscious effort to get to the bottom of things, such pragmatic
simplifications afford us a worthwhile vehicle for analysis - indeed,
constitute the very justification behind our attempts, as philosophers, to
investigate life in a more detailed, resolute, sincere, and profound
manner. Consequently, we must not take
them at face-value, like the majority of people, but should concentrate on
digging beneath the objective surface of life, if only because we are intent
upon 'unearthing' some unique revelation, lifting it clear of obscurity, and
thereupon exposing it to rational investigation.
Now just as we contended that a man
cannot be wise without also possessing a degree of folly, so we also contend,
in inverting our thesis, that he cannot be mad without possessing a calculated
degree of sanity, since a mad man per se is more a
figment of the imagination than a genuine reality.
NO
HAPPINESS WITHOUT SADNESS: On the subject of happiness, I believe John Cowper
Powys, the exponent of what has been called 'elementalism',
makes a serious mistake in regarding thoughts as highly as he seems to, both
with regard to the struggle against sadness and the cause of its outbreak in
the first place, as defined, for example, in The Art of Happiness, one
of his most accessible books. For is it
not regularly the case that a person feels sad without having particularly gone
out of his way to think himself into it, or to involve himself in hostile
circumstances. That he feels sad simply
because our metaphysical condition as men requires a degree of
sadness, in order that we may remain integrated as human beings?
Now if this is so, how much more so is
it the case when a person feels sad because he has a damn good reason to, since
he can point to the fact that the weather is depressing, or his financial
circumstances are unfavourable, or his health is poor, or his hopes on a
particular subject have been dashed? Yet
in a world where dualities, disparities, conflicts, and tensions are the very
stuff of life, it would seem plausible to contend that sadness plays as
legitimate a part in the birth of happiness as happiness in the death of
sadness, and that we can no more aim for the one at the total exclusion of the
other ... than hope to stay awake without getting any sleep!
Instead, therefore, of waging an all-out
war on sadness, as some people would seem only too foolishly inclined to do,
would it not be wiser to accept the condition for what it really is - namely
the obverse side of a dualistic coin and, hence, the price we pay for our
happiness. 'Yes, I am sad,' you say,
'but this sadness will subsequently give way to a degree of happiness which,
through an unwritten law of my being, is largely a consequence of it.'
NOTHING
SUPERFLUOUS: That everything is interrelated, interdependent, interfused ... would appear to be the eternal rule of life,
a rule which makes it necessary for us to despise here in order to admire
there, to hate there in order to love here, to condemn here in order to praise
there, to reject there in order to accept here, to scowl here in order to smile
there, and so on throughout the entire range of human experience. When one realizes that everybody is a part of
the whole, a consequence of the whole, and that to consider certain parts of
the whole superfluous is effectively to turn against it, then one can only
conclude the people, creatures, and things one dislikes to be of
significance in so far as they make it possible to maintain the people,
creatures, and things one likes.
Similarly, if one values admiration one
can only conclude the people one despises to be of such significance to the
welfare of one's admiration that one would never be able to admire anybody
without them; that unless one despised, one would never be in a position to
admire in the first place, so that the despising is forever justified, forever
sanctioned by the lure of admiration.
But this is the case, it may be argued,
for every single sentiment a man may have, a case which ordains the absolute
legitimacy and necessity of his acting the way he does in order to maintain his
opinions, his prejudices, his predilections, and, above all, his
integrity. Let him curse this or that as
much as he likes; for unless he does so, he will never have anything to
bless. Even if you remove whatever he
happens to be cursing, even if you do away with it altogether, don't let that
beguile you into assuming that you are necessarily doing him a favour or
improving his lot! On the contrary,
would he not then have to find something else to curse, in order that he might
continue to bless?
BETWEEN DAY
AND NIGHT: Let us not delude ourselves into imagining, as too many philosophers
have done, that life is either difficult or easy when, in reality, it is both
difficult and easy, though, admittedly, not usually at the same time. Let us not delude ourselves either, in the
manner of the most pessimistic stoics, that life is
both war and suffering when, in reality, it is both war and peace and pleasure
and pain. Still less do we wish to
consider life an absurdity when we cannot help noticing its reasonableness too,
and can only conclude those who can't to be either poor-sighted or the victims
of rather serious mental aberrations.
No, we are not worshippers of the moon,
we dualists, and neither are we worshippers of the
sun! It doesn't become us to serve the
one at the expense of the other but, rather, to serve or, at any rate,
acknowledge them both. If we give a
little more attention, as men, to the sun than to the moon, is it not because
we are basically unable to do anything else, since something buried deep inside
our dual natures responds to the ultimate sovereignty of the active over the
passive, and thereby sets our bias in that direction?
Ah, but we do not pretend, for all our
natural inclinations, that the moon is unworthy of our attention. We aren't sufficiently extreme, perverse, or
deluded, in such matters, to suppose ourselves capable of thriving without them
both, and, to be sure, we have never heard anything from either of them to the
effect that we should. But when we
temporarily turn our faces away from the light of the one, is it not in order
that we may better learn to appreciate the light of the other, that we may so
shine ourselves, and in such a way as to do absolute justice to each? Truly, it is not for us to detract from the positivity of the one by foolishly belittling the
negativity of the other! There are quite
enough misunderstandings in the world already.
A MISTAKE IN
PLUTARCH: For those readers who may be interested in the possibility of my
theory being mistaken with regard to the interrelativity
and inevitability of both positive and negative antitheses within the
individual, there is a strong attack on such a theory in Plutarch's
dialogue The Cleverness of Animals, wherein the character Autobulus, cast as Plutarch's
father, puts forward to his old friend Soclarus a
refutation of the said theory by emphasizing what he takes to be the
impossibility of two completely contradictory elements within the same
person. Hence, according to Autobulus, the rational and the irrational cannot exist side-by-side, since the latter would eliminate the
former or vice versa. 'If,' he
goes on the say, 'to make sure that Nature is not curtailed in any way, someone
maintains that the part of Nature which has a soul must comprise both a
rational and an irrational element, then someone else is sure to say that what
has a soul must comprise elements capable of imagination and incapable of imagination,
capable of feeling and incapable of feeling.
The idea would be that these opposites, these positive and negative
antitheses about the same thing should be kept, as it were, in equilibrium. But when we consider that all things which
have souls must necessarily be capable of feeling and of imagination, it will
appear absurd to go looking, in this class of living things, for antitheses
between the feeling and the unfeeling, the imaginative and the
unimaginative. And in just the same way
it is pointless to find in living things an antithesis between the rational and
the irrational ...'
I have quoted the best part of the
paragraph under surveillance in order to make quite clear to the reader just
how Autobulus' reasoning is wrong. For, having come this far in my theorizing
and placed more than a little confidence in the authenticity of my argument, it
is not something that I would like to hide away, refer to obliquely, or leave
myself in any doubt about, particularly in dealing with a master like Plutarch. The mistake, then, clearly lies in the
coupling of elements which are in no way antithetical but, with the exception
of the rational and the irrational (which is paralleled by me in the essays
entitled NOT ENTIRELY SANE and NOT ENTIRELY INSANE, as well as having been
dealt with in considerably more detail by Carl Jung in his analyses of the
compensatory relationship between the conscious and the unconscious minds in
the totality of the psyche), distinctly contradictory. Instead of forming durable antitheses, they
would spell the elimination of each other.
Thus to be 'capable of feeling and incapable of feeling' is tantamount
to saying 'to be capable of truth and incapable of truth' or 'to be capable of
love and incapable of love' or, again, 'to be capable of goodness and incapable
of goodness' when, in reality, it is truth and illusion, love and hate, good
and evil, which form the antitheses, not the direct contradiction of the
positive element achieved through the total elimination of the negative one!
So Autobulus'
reasoning, although it may seem feasible at first glance, is really specious,
in that it posits false antitheses as real ones. Rather than the refutation
of feeling by unfeeling, why not the coupling of sympathy and callousness? We are all sympathetic in some contexts and
callous in others, as well we might be.