PART ONE: APHORISTIC ESSAYS
THE
PHILOSOPHER AS MAN, NOT MACHINE: How often should a philosopher actually allow
himself to think, if he is to remain a relatively sane, active, healthy
individual, and not degenerate into some kind of impersonal thinking machine? Should he go out of his way to think
objectively when there is no apparent necessity for him to do so (as, for
example, when he isn't officially working), to drive his thought patterns over
the bounds of moderation to such an extent that he defies the urge to variety
in life and is eventually consumed, like Nietzsche, by an obsession with
thought, becomes saddled, as it were, with a plethora of intellectual
superfluities?
Undoubtedly, a man who regards himself as
a thinker must think sometimes. But an
over-fastidious approach to thinking, an over-obdurate inclination to think at
any cost could very soon render him anomalous, foolish, trivial, stolid,
boring, and unbalanced - to name just a few things. For whether or not the most thought-obsessed
people realize it, there is more to life than thinking, and a need certainly
exists in people for adherence to a given physiological situation - as, for
example, in refraining from thought when the need to do so is patently obvious.
If, therefore, a so-called thinker is to
avoid becoming an intellectual crank, he must respect his periodically natural
inclination to thoughtlessness and not endeavour, by contrast, to continue
thinking when the energy or requirement to do so is no longer there. Otherwise he may subsequently degenerate, if
he doesn't suffer a mental breakdown, into some kind of intellectual freak - in
other words, into someone who imagines that he ought to think as much as
possible, no matter what the circumstances, in order to
remain a philosopher, a man of genius, a cut above the common herd. Philosophy, however, refuses to take such
nonsense seriously! For the true
philosopher always goes his way as a man, not as a thinking
machine.
TWO TYPES
OF THINKER: It is wrong to assume that a man obsessed with thought is necessarily
a thinker, a philosopher, a genius. For
when a man is compelled to think out of habit from fear of not thinking, of not
appearing to be enough of a thinker in his own eyes, there is a reasonable
chance that he is less a philosopher than a dupe of his own illusions, a slave
of a mentality which assumes it necessary for a thinker to think as much as
possible, regardless of the subject or context, if he is to remain a
philosopher and not degenerate into an average mind. The idea of thinking, in such a head, is
ultimately more important than what is
actually being thought about.
For it must be admitted, from the converse
standpoint, that a genuine thinker - a man, in other words, who thinks not
merely for the sake of flattering his ego or filling a vacuum but, more
importantly, in order to discover something new about the world he lives in and
the best methods of adjusting himself to it - will always stop himself thinking
beyond a certain length of time simply because experience and common sense will
have taught him that that is the best course to follow if he is to remain
relatively natural, sane, perceptive, lucid, and mentally resilient. As a thinker, in this context, he will know
that his chief duty is towards himself, and not only for himself but inevitably
for the sake of other people as well; that his intelligence should therefore be
used to his advantage - as, unfortunately, is rarely the case with the other
type of thinker, a type who, obsessed by the urge to think, is essentially a
pathological phenomenon, scarcely a man of wisdom. For philosophy should have earnest
connections, after all, with the art of living wisely.
THINKING
SHOULD BE DIFFICULT: It is just as well that, for the vast majority of people,
so-called objective thinking is so difficult, that even those of us who
habitually regard ourselves as 'thinkers' are normally compelled to fight and
sweat for our deepest thoughts. Were
this not the case, were we not the hard-pressed slaves of thought, it is highly
probable that thinking alone would preoccupy us, and to such an extent and with
such intensity that we would be left with little time or inclination for
anything else.
Indeed, those of us who make a daily
commitment to putting thoughts on paper are only too aware of how difficult serious
thinking really is, and consequently of how pointless it would be for us to
complain against this fact or to criticize ourselves for not thinking well
enough. Yet if work were always easy, if
brilliant ideas invariably came to us without any difficulty, what challenge
would there be in doing it? And how many
of us would really care to have above-average thoughts flowing through our
heads all day anyway, thoughts which never allow us to rest but, as though prompted
by a psychic conveyor-belt, continue to plague our consciousness from morning
till night?
If, as Bergson
contended, the brain really is a limiting
device, an organ which, in addition to storing verbal concepts, usually
prevents us from thinking too much too easily and too continuously, then it is
just as well that it actually works, that we aren't subjected to an unceasing
barrage of brilliant and highly irrelevant ideas all day, but are forced to put
some effort into extracting any worthwhile thoughts from it. Was this not the case, I rather doubt that I
should have found either the time or the inclination to record such seemingly
gratified thoughts as these!
A
JUSTIFICATION OF BOREDOM: If man is protected against his thoughts by generally
finding it difficult to think (by which I mean to think objectively,
constructively, and continuously - in other words, above the usual plane of
subjective considerations, incidental fragments, brief recollections,
disconnected words, casual street-sign readings, intuitive insights, etc., and
beyond the moods or situations when thinking of one kind or another comes most
naturally to him), then one might justifiably contend that he is protected
against too much mental and physical inertia by the intermittent prevalence of
boredom, that scourge of the idle.
To most people, particularly the more
intelligent ones, boredom is a distinctly disagreeable condition, an emptiness
usually leading to self-contempt, which suffices to goad them into doing
something absorbing, into losing and rediscovering themselves in some
preoccupation, some form of activity or stimulant. Now if boredom had absolutely no place in
their lives, if mere existence sufficed to content them (as appears to be the
case with a majority of animals), what do you suppose would happen? Do you suppose, for instance, that they would
really do anything, would, in fact, be capable of living at all? The prevalence of hunger, thirst, lust,
changes in the weather, etc., would doubtless oblige them to satisfy their
respective physical needs as quickly and efficiently as possible. But, having done so, what would they then
have to live for afterwards?
Without boredom there would have been no
civilization - no art, science, religion, politics, philosophy, music, sport,
travel, evolution. In fact, without
boredom there would probably have been nothing of any consequence
whatsoever. For boredom is akin to an
eternal whip!
ULTIMATE
JUSTICE: Whenever something happens it happens for a good reason. Once a cause is committed to an effect there
is no turning it back. There is no such
thing as an accident which should have happened but didn't. A near-miss is a near-miss and not an
accident, even if the potential of an accident existed for a time. An accident which should happen will always
happen if the circumstances demand it.
Therefore whenever a person secretly or
openly condemns nature for its apparent injustice, for the fact, let us say,
that lightning struck a tree and killed someone sheltering beneath its
branches, or that a flood swept over a town and killed people and damaged
property, or that a volcano erupted and spilled molten lava down onto some
nearby townsfolk - whenever, I say, a person condemns nature on these and
similar accounts, understandable though his condemnation may be, he is unwittingly
turning his back on justice, on the justice of a world which would seem to be
saying: This cause is bound to have a specific effect; if people are in the way
of it, then that is their fault. 'A'
must lead to 'B' whatever the consequences or, put mathematically, 2 x 2 = 4
and not 5, 6, or 7. If you happen to be
sheltering beneath the branches of a tree when lightning strikes it (and the
lightning couldn't help arising), then you must suffer the consequences. If, by any chance, you sometime happen to be
in the path of oncoming lava, you must now accept the fact that it wasn't
necessarily destined to kill anyone but will only kill or maim people if they
are rash, unfortunate, ignorant, or brave enough to dwell under a volcano's
shadow. To suggest that the eruption
shouldn't occur would be as unreasonable as to suggest that mutually attractive
men and women shouldn't fall in love, or that 2 x 2 shouldn't equal 4, or that
a poison berry shouldn't prove highly detrimental to its eater. For whenever something happens, it does so
for a good reason.
An earthquake, for example, which has to
occur because secretly engendered by some planetary necessity which, unbeknown
to man, simultaneously safeguards and maintains the overall stability of the
planet, is not by any means guaranteed to occur in close proximity to human
dwellings. But if it does so, one ought
to bear in mind that (1) it had to occur in consequence of a combination of
subterranean planetary influences; (2) the people killed and/or injured by it will
normally represent only a tiny percentage of the total human population of the
globe, a percentage which will either die or suffer injury as a sacrifice, so
to speak, for the overall welfare of mankind in general; (3) these same people
might not have been afflicted by it had they built their dwellings elsewhere,
or if technology had evolved an efficient early-warning system which could
pinpoint the anticipated place of the quake and thereby give inhabitants there
sufficient time to abandon their dwellings and move to the nearest safety
zone.
Like molten lava, hurricanes, floods,
typhoons, and lightning, the earthquake kills indiscriminately, but it only
kills what is in its way. Hideous as
these things usually are, a majority of us would probably prefer the occasional
emergence of potentially death-engendering planetary phenomena to the wholesale
destruction of the planet itself brought about by a gigantic explosion in the
bowls of the earth. Large-scale explosions
fostered by man are undoubtedly dreadful enough. But experience of a gigantic 'natural'
explosion which ultimately tore the entire planet apart would be far
worse! For where the elements rule, the
elements decide.
If earthquakes, typhoons, volcanic
eruptions, etc., were not necessary, they wouldn't happen. Admittedly, science can give man the
advantage of anticipating them and even of directing the force of various
outbreaks of natural violence into a particular area or spot, as with lightning
conductors. But a civilization which got
to a point of trying to prevent the emergence of such phenomena could
eventually find itself paying the price of frustrating a series of
comparatively minor disturbances by subsequently bringing upon itself the
horrendous devastation of a major one.
For sooner or later a phenomenon which has been frustrated or repressed
too long will explode with a force that would have made the force of its
previously unchecked explosion seem relatively harmless.
Now what applies to the external world of
nature doubtless applies no less to the internal world of the psyche, where
neuroses and psychoses are the price one must occasionally pay for one's
sanity.
NO ESCAPING
EVIL: To a certain extent every age turns a blind eye towards most of its chief
evils. One of the main reasons for this
is undoubtedly helplessness, but others also include indifference, laziness,
societal hostility, class rivalry, moral hypocrisy, ignorance, lack of
imagination, and - probably most common of all - the inborn inclination of a
majority of people to take matters more or less for granted.
Knowing this to be the case, however, one
should nonetheless endeavour to attribute a reasonable justification to this
string of evils (whatever they happen to be and wherever they happen to
flourish). For not only do they
constitute a very common, perennial, and ineradicable
element in the life of a nation at any given time but, more importantly, they
also constitute a very worthwhile element in the protection of that nation's
psychic equilibrium, since without its evil side it would have nothing good to
boast of, and therefore be unable to exist.
Paradoxical though it may seem, it is important
to note that evils of one kind or another will always exist, no matter what the
gonfalon, for the good of the people.
The assertion, however, that they don't exist when it is patently
obvious they do, is in itself a clear example of a particular kind of evil
which is fairly constant among certain individuals and institutions in every
age.
Granted, then, that an age may be
justified in turning a 'blind eye' to most of its chief evils, in pretending
them not to exist and quite often in not knowing of their existence, it
nonetheless has to be said that under no circumstances would it be justified in
categorically denying their existence, in asserting them to be a
figment of the popular imagination, since such an absurd attitude would amount
to a veritable refutation of all life.
It would, in fact, amount to something gravely unjustifiable in a world
where antitheses are ever the mean!
The fact, however, that society is
relatively integrated in every age stands to reason. For no matter what the situation, no matter
how bad things may appear, good and evil must always co-exist in various
degrees and guises, according to whether a nation is at peace or at war, even
if a number of the standards concerning the respective criteria of good and
evil are constantly being changed or modified in order to meet the demands of
the occasion. What man ought to know, and too often forgets
(though this is probably just as well), is that nature is ultimately wiser than
he, that he is the product of nature and consequently is guided and motivated
by it in every age, irrespective of what the chief political, social,
religious, moral, economic, agricultural, or industrial priorities may happen
to be at any given time.
The endeavour to create a perfect human
society is inevitably a gross self-deception.
For man can never attain to a society where, presumably, everyone will
be equal and all the assumed evil elements be eliminated, when the essential
nature of existence demands our acceptance of and acquiescence in the
continuous interplay of polar opposites: good and evil, rich and poor, truth
and illusion, ruling and ruled, noble and plebeian, etc., under virtually every
gonfalon throughout history. Were
mankind ever destined to arrive at such a 'perfect society', it would
undoubtedly constitute something distinctly imperfect, anomalous, and insufferable. In sum, one can only rob Peter to pay Paul.
THE WAY IT
HAS TO BE: Every age contains its quota of horrors, exploitations,
superstitions, taboos, stupidities, illusions, crimes, diseases, accidents,
mistakes, etc., and the modern age is clearly no exception. Assuming the human kind are not eradicated in
any future world war, it is quite conceivable that the more intelligent members
of generations to come may look back in
dread, amazement, and even bewilderment at many of the circumstances which a majority
of people take for granted today, just as, in focusing their critical attention
upon a number of the (to them) most unacceptable aspects of the Victorian Age,
people today often tend to disapprove of child labour, slave labour, the
imprisonment of children, compulsory naval and military service, birching,
hanging, and the extreme levels of social deprivation which existed among the
very poor in relation to education, housing, sanitation, health, diet,
employment, and earnings.
But the more fortunate members of a future
generation - one existing, say, about a hundred years from now - may well have
sound reason to be shocked, surprised, bewildered, or even amused by knowledge
of the fact that a majority of late-twentieth-century people lived quite complacently
in an age of widespread pollution, excessive noise, traffic congestion,
overcrowding, cigarette smoking, drug addiction, alcoholism, cancer, the
five-day week, metropolitan loneliness, tinned food, bottled milk,
capitalist/socialist antagonism, the threat of nuclear war, religious
anachronisms, life-imprisonment, impersonal bureaucracy, dogs' mess on
pavements, regular strikes, widespread unemployment, redundancies, football
hooliganism, and spiritual deprivation.
However, whether we like it or not, that
is the way it has to be. For the virtues
of one age are almost invariably the vices of another, the vices of one age the
virtues of another, and no age is totally perfect.
NO HOPE
WITHOUT FEAR: Every life is subject to the intermittent prevalence of
fear. When a man pretends exemption from
fear, it should be evident that he is almost certainly deluded, ignorant,
forgetful, superficial, or just a plain liar.
For, in reality, no man can be exempted
from fear - not, anyway, while he lives anything approximating to a normal,
healthy, thought-ridden existence.
But let us take a closer look at this
matter and unashamedly draw up a fairly comprehensive list of the most common
fears, particularly those which regularly plague the male mind: fear of losing
one's job, of having an accident, of becoming dangerously ill, of going deaf
and/or blind, of being sent to gaol, of becoming impotent, of not succeeding in
one's work, of going mad, of being taken for a fool, of losing one's
intellectual powers, of being misunderstood, of being rebuffed by a woman to
whom one is attracted, of being exploited, of being trapped in an ungainly
situation, of losing someone one loves, of insomnia, of solitude, of idleness,
of disgrace, of heights, of flying, of neurosis, of drugs, of arousing the
hostility or contempt of one's neighbours and colleagues, of the unknown, of
bullies, of thugs, of making a woman pregnant against one's wishes, of crowds,
of changing one's habits too often, of certain authorities, of what people may
be saying about one behind one's back, of being made to look a fool, of being
late for work, of oversleeping, of too much responsibility, of violence, of
incompatibility with another person, of premature ejaculation, of having one's
creative work rejected, of being noticed by certain people, of nightmares, of
not appearing to be brave enough, of not meeting the right sort of people, of
meeting the wrong sort of people, of being completely alone in one's old age,
of being struck by lightning, of being mugged or robbed, of going bald, of
catching a cold, of being alone in the dark, of losing money, of missing an
appointment, of telling a lie, of the police, of strangers, etc.
From this fairly generalized list of the
most common male fears (though many of them will doubtless be shared by females
as well), one can see just how pervasive fear really is in life. Not one of us who cannot admit to having
fears about some of the things in the above list and/or to having previously
overcome or outgrown certain other fears there.
Not a day passes but either something in or beyond the above list
troubles our worry-strained minds. But
could one imagine what it would be like to live totally without fear? Not if one is sufficiently human! For, as the philosopher Hume indicated,
without fear there would be no hope, and without hope there would be no life.
TWENTY
MISTAKEN IDEAS: As some modern philosophers have informed us, there are always
a large number of universally mistaken ideas to which many people are grudgingly
apt to cling, despite their proven fallibility.
Here, for the sake of exposing some of them, as well as perhaps
following in the hallowed footsteps of Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Bertrand
Russell, I list twenty ideas which strike me as being in this category:-
1. The
Universe consists of the solar system and the stars;
2. Space
is finite;
3. Man
is by nature purely rational;
4. Goodness
can exist independently of evil;
5. Man
is imperfect because he makes mistakes;
6. Man
can live without illusions;
7. The
proper sphere of art is truth;
8. The
sun revolves around the earth;
9. Population
in no way conditions human behaviour;
10. The most spiritual
people are of necessity the least sensuous;
11. Violence is unnecessary;
12. Religion is unnecessary;
13. Happiness is the absence of pain;
14. The survival of death is no mere hypothesis;
15. L
16. There is no moral-world-order;
17. God is nature;
18. The object of progress is to minimize pain;
19. Man is immune to the influence of his
external environment;
20. Solitary people are invariably lonely.
SLIGHTLY
EXISTENTIAL: To acquire a contemporary understanding of what Schopenhauer meant
by the world 'as our idea', or what it means to be living in a material world
which is partly fashioned by man, one need only endeavour to imagine how an
animal or a bird would view its immediate surroundings ... how, for instance,
an ordinary grey pigeon would see such inventions as a pillar box, a telephone
kiosk, a car, motorcycle, lamppost, statue, traffic light, clock tower, or
notice board.
Taken from what one imagines to be a
pigeon's point-of-view, one might suppose such human inventions to be of
relatively little significance, to be mere 'things' without names or apparent
significance upon which the pigeon can rest or about which it must move. Whether, in fact, our pigeon sees the pillar
box as a large red 'thing' or not, one can be fairly confident that it
possesses no equivalent symbol for 'red', that it can only see the pillar box
as something describing a particular shape and hue which is different from
other shapes and hues, and which may or may not attract its attention on that
account.
Therefore the world evidently presents a
very different face to a pigeon than what it generally does to a human being,
and this difference, this conglomeration of nondescript, nameless, purposeless,
and possibly colourless 'things', lends an extra dimension to what Schopenhauer
meant by the proposition 'the world is my idea', a world not only dependent on
the peculiar nature of human consciousness and of the relative distortion or
subjectivity which that consciousness necessarily imposes upon it but, in
addition, one largely fashioned by man for the benefit of men and having, on
that account, no similar common reality for anything else, be it pigeon,
sparrow, mouse, cat, squirrel, or dog - other, of course, than in the very
basic and self-evident sense of presenting external 'things'.
WORDS AS
OUR 'REALITY': In the human world there are 'tall trees', 'green leaves',
'blades of grass', and 'grey clouds', but in the animal, bird, and insect
worlds there are no such descriptions.
Such creatures see the world openly, nakedly, devoid of adjectives and
nouns. From their point of view cats do
not lie in 'the grass', birds do not perch in 'trees', and bees do not
pollinate 'flowers'. What we have
conveniently taken for their reality is only relevant to ourselves, since to a
cat there is no such thing as 'grass', to a bird there are no such things as
'trees', and to a bee there are no such things as 'flowers'. Neither are they aware that leaves are
'green' or clouds 'grey'. In fact, they
do not even know what leaves or clouds are, being so utterly accustomed to
living in a world without description.
But to ask ourselves a serious question -
do we really know what leaves or clouds are?
Are we really in possession of ultimate truth when we point to 'green
leaves' or 'grey clouds' and thereupon claim additional knowledge for ourselves? Let us confess, my readers,
that these descriptions, ingenious and indispensable as they are, in no
way penetrate to the essential core of things.
Let us confess to mostly being unconscious poets who manipulate
representative symbols without usually realizing that a 'leaf' in no way
explains exactly what a leaf is, much less a 'green leaf'.
And so we, too, are basically as unaware
as the animals, birds, and insects as to exactly what we are living with. We can never get to the heart of the world we
have metaphorically invented, and therefore must conclude the ultimate truth of
whatever confronts us in the natural world to be a refutation of our illusions
rather than the illusions, or symbols, themselves.
In other words, to establish anything
approximate to the ultimate truth about a leaf, one would have to admit our
knowledge of leaves to be relative and, hence, misleading, an attempt to
describe that which, in its natural essence, defies definitive
description. In sum, there are no
'leaves'; we have conveniently invented them.
And to the extent that we have named and thereby humanized such
existences, we have invented the rest of nature as well.
PARTLY OUR
CREATION: What a strange moment it is in one's life when one realizes that,
ultimately, there is no such thing as a 'bumblebee', indeed, that there has
never been such a thing except in relation to human
cognition and imagination. The world we
have created generally suffices us. We
believe quite firmly in the existence of 'bumblebees', a type of winged insect
we can easily differentiate from other such insects but which, in the world
beneath man, is no closer to being a 'bumblebee' than anything else. As a named creature, it is both a truth and
an illusion. As an
unnamed one, a truth through and through. But we are of course unable to live without
illusions; we must give names to things in order to be able to differentiate
between them and, in doing so, fall into the trap of actually believing these
named things to be ultimate realities - something they in no sense are or ever
can be.
And so one day we realize that, together
with any number of other insects, birds, animals, fish, etc., the 'bumblebee'
is partly a figment of our imagination, a nameless creature which in our world
acquires a fixed position but which in its own world - and doubtless in the
worlds of numerous other nameless creatures - must forever remain a truthful
thing-in-itself, unknowable and unnamed.
With man, however, such illusions (and I
use the term in the special, if unusual sense, to which it here applies) are of
the greatest significance. We need our
illusions for the sake of our truths, so let us not endeavour to undermine
them. For what I have just told you is, after all, a truth acquired at the expense of an illusion.
TRUTHS BUT
NO TRUTH: The fundamental reason why we can never arrive at 'the truth' about
the world is that there is no single truth, i.e. human truth, but an infinity of truths which, in their various
manifestations, correspond to the different life-forms contemplating them.
Thus we can divide earth truths, as it
were, into human, animal, reptile, bird, fish, insect, microbe, and vegetable,
and then again into the 'truths' appertaining to each individual species within
the overall pattern; though the 'truths' of the seven kinds of life beneath man
will be correspondingly smaller and more restricted, as befits organisms with a
much narrower range of knowledge. Then,
of course, one must bear in mind the possibility of diverse kinds of life
existing on other planets, if not in this solar system then at least in solar
systems that we presume to exist both elsewhere in the Galaxy, of which our sun
is only a minor star, and in the thousand million or so other galaxies
currently known to man via the world's most powerful telescopes.
Hence the universe of natural truths is
potentially so great, diverse, and exclusive ... as to completely defy any
attempt man might make to establish a categorical criterion of 'the truth'
based solely on the limited and necessarily partial perspective of human
cognition. For truth, as we here
understand it, is eternally relative, not absolute, and thereby confined to
being a record of the human mind.
REALITY AND
REALITIES: When once one has understood that there are as many worlds as
separate species, one will begin to comprehend how diverse the so-called 'real
world' actually is, to comprehend its diversity in terms of numerous realities,
as opposed to just a single human reality compounded of specific shapes and manifestations
of life.
Thus one can speak, for example, in terms
of cat reality, mouse reality, pigeon reality, frog reality, shark reality,
wasp reality, owl reality, etc., in addition to human reality which, in its
legitimate desire for world-wide integration and strict categorization of all
existing phenomena, regularly overlooks the various realities confronting other
creatures in order to maintain and safeguard its own perspective.
Finally, however, one must break the
realities of the different species down into the tiny fragments which
correspond to each particular life, thereby arriving at individual reality, the
world within a world or, more specifically, the reality within realities.
HUMAN
DIVERSITY: Training people to do individual tasks is akin to turning them into
different creatures, insofar as one man becomes the rough equivalent of a horse
(taxi driver), another the rough equivalent of a fox (politician); one man
becomes the rough equivalent of an ox (labourer), another the rough equivalent of
a chameleon (actor); one man becomes the rough equivalent of a sheepdog
(foreman), another the rough equivalent of a sheep (worker); one man becomes
the rough equivalent of a spider (shopkeeper), another the rough equivalent of
a wasp (soldier); one man becomes the rough equivalent of an ant (builder),
another the rough equivalent of a squirrel (banker), and so on.
As they become more like their respective
tasks, so they become less like each other, the outcome ultimately being that
human society comes to resemble a very subtle, if artificial, version of the
animal kingdom, wherein one type of creature preys upon another to the end of
its days.
NO TWO
ALIKE: Might one not be correct in contending nature to be more hard-pressed to
create two beings exactly alike, exactly alike, that is, in every respect,
than to create four or five billion beings all different from one another? In fact, one could conceive of eight billion,
twelve billion, an infinite number of beings which nature would be in no way
prepared to replicate, not even where the instances of so-called identical
twins were concerned.
But how inexhaustible must be the human
face and frame! No two people exactly
alike, not even if you took everybody that had ever lived into account! And no two ants exactly
alike, either. What - no two
ants? But isn't that a patent
exaggeration? Don't all ants look
alike? Yes, of course they do. But only to human eyes, to eyes that are not
required to see ants as individuals but only
collectively 'as ants'.
As for the ants themselves, however, one
might well be correct in assuming that they can differentiate between one
another. And if they
can, why not sparrows, pigeons, flies, bees, and wasps? What is there to suggest that these other
species wouldn't be able to differentiate between themselves as well?
But, my dear reader, you know what that
implies, don't you? No two living
creatures exactly the same, neither at any time nor anywhere! Now that really is stretching the
imagination!
TIME
BELONGS TO MAN: Not only does man differ from other life forms in terms of
appearance, language, and custom, but also in terms of the fact that he alone
lives in a given time, whereas animals, reptiles, birds, fish, insects, etc.,
live in the timeless eternity of nature, and can therefore be said to exist
negatively.
What, for example, can a pigeon, cat, or
dog know of the minute of the hour, the hour of the day, the day of the week,
the week of the month, the month of the year, the year of the century, or the
century of the millennium? There is no
regulative system by which other life forms could be obliged to live in strict
accordance with twentieth-century procedure, for they have no criterion which
could enforce any such obligation.
Indeed, the fundamental ignorance of other
life forms as to the establishment of a timescale permits them a degree of
naturalness unknown to man, a naturalness which exists, moreover, in direct
opposition to the positivity of created time. For man, the creator of unnatural or artificial
criteria, can never wholly escape his consciousness of being in a given century
or of living from Sunday to Saturday in a certain month, and is thus forever
obliged to live outside of natural eternity.
In a sense, the only eternity known to him is that which is granted
through intense preoccupation - the transient forgetfulness of the burden of
time as induced by excitement, whether physical or mental, though especially
the latter.
INEVITABLY
UNREASONABLE: Every man will at some time or other be shamelessly unreasonable
towards some other section(s) of society in order to maintain his
reasonableness where it is most required, i.e. in respect of his personal
welfare. Hence he will consciously or
unconsciously adopt a superficially condemnatory view of particular people or
types of persons simply because, as a human being subject to dualistic
impulses, he has no other choice, since his metaphysical integrity demands that
he so acts in order to remain true to himself.
Thus this periodic unreasonableness is, on
a profounder level, a manifestation of his overall reasonableness,
insofar as he respects himself as a being who must follow certain prescribed
inclinations or limitations irrespective of the criticisms he may receive, in
consequence of appearing unreasonable, from other differently-oriented
'reasonable' people.
PUPPETS OF
LIFE: In theory, though rarely in practice, I do not condemn a man, no matter
how obnoxious he may seem, for being what he is, since I cannot understand how
a man with an acquired obsession - and we all acquire obsessions - can possibly
be expected to act in a way contrary to the dictates of that obsession. In other words, a man who is the inevitable
consequence of a combination of former influences is in no way qualified to ignore
them.
Thus, with regard to the individual, I do
not condemn a tyrant for being a tyrant.
I may disapprove of him, but reason compels me to acknowledge tyranny,
in all its manifold guises, patriarchal as well as political, petty as well as
great, as a fact of (dualistic) life, one of those disagreeable facts like
nightmares, earthquakes, wars, famines, and diseases, against which there seems
to be no ultimate deterrent.
For whatever a man does, he does because
he is basically unable to do anything else.
We cannot entirely shake ourselves free from the diverse contexts and
circumstances which have made us what we are.
To a large extent we are all puppets of life, ingenious marionettes who
dance on the strings of our respective experiences and occupations.
THE
NEGATIVE ROOT: Whatever exists naturally exists negatively, which is to say in
direct opposition to a positive quality which has sprung from it, viz. silence
in relation to sound, space in relation to matter, eternity in relation to
time, woman in relation to man, illusion in relation to truth, barbarism in
relation to culture, evil in relation to good, sadness in relation to
happiness, dark in relation to light, competition in relation to co-operation,
immorality in relation to morality, etc., so that whatever exists positively,
by contrast, exists to a certain extent unnaturally, or by dint of a degree of
effort. Truth has to be struggled after,
whereas illusion costs us no great effort, being everywhere the basic clay from
which truth is moulded. Goodness
likewise has to be struggled after, whereas evil, the primal source from which
all goodness springs, proves less difficult of attainment, being everywhere the
more natural state-of-affairs. And
happiness, despite superficial appearances to the contrary, is not our natural
condition but one to which we must daily aspire with a fresh resolve which, if
successful, will temporarily free us from the gruesome clutches of that
all-pervading sadness.
Yes, just as surely as the predominantly
positive man springs from the predominantly negative and, hence, more natural
woman, so do all the other positive entities known to us spring from a
like-source of negativity, as though in defiance of the root substance or
nature of things. But one must not suppose
this arrangement to be in any way reprehensible! For it is only by springing from and being,
as it were, enmeshed in the negative ... that man can aspire towards the
positive at all. How could it be
otherwise? One cannot have a positive
base at the bottom of nature, life, and the universe, a base from which
negativity sprang, for the simple reason that, properly considered, a negative
attribute cannot spring from anywhere, but must always 'give birth' to a
positive one.
Admittedly, the world is fundamentally
an evil place, but if it were not so, if it wasn't rooted in negativity, there
would be no aspiration towards or attainment of the good. Indeed, there would be no cause
for the good. Hence the intrinsic evil
of the world finds redemption in man.
THE
STRUGGLE FOR HAPPINESS: If one didn't have to fight for one's happiness on a
daily basis, if, by some remote chance, happiness was 'handed to one on a
plate', there would be little or no free choice left in the world, little or no
incentive for innately happy people to do anything, so greatly would the
intrinsic happiness of human existence content and preoccupy them. It is only, however, because our natural
condition is one of sadness that we are regularly goaded out of it by the
desire to acquire happiness, since no man can struggle from the positive to the
negative because the positive would be all-sufficing and thus unable or
unwilling to instigate any such procedure.
Hence it is ever man's fate to struggle
from the negative to the positive, from sadness to happiness, in accordance
with his thoroughly admirable desire to escape from what is disagreeable. And yet the positive can only be sustained
for a limited period of time, after which it must again make way for the
negative, in order that the phoenix of happiness may subsequently rise from the
ashes of sadness and thereby permit man his individual freedom. But man, as already remarked, never struggles
from the positive to the negative. On
the contrary, he merely subsides or relapses into it.
WORK AND
PLAY: I do not believe the man who tells me that he doesn't have any play
because his play blends-in with his work and thereby forces nothing but work
upon him. To hear this is almost to be
told that the man who says it doesn't really have any work either since, in the
final analysis, one cannot have a life which is either all work and no play or
all play and no work. Somehow, one has
to accept that one cannot work without play or play without work, even if one
chooses to pretend or imagine otherwise, since one would then have forgotten
what the true feelings or nature of work and play actually were.
No, I do not go along with the man who is
or, more accurately, imagines himself
to be a self-styled martyr of work without really being such. If his play isn't completely separate from his
work, then his work will ultimately be bad for him, whatever he happens to
think of it.
In fact, work and play are so
interdependent, and yet so radically different, that, unless one keeps them
apart, one will never get the most out of one's work, its being understood that
there is no surer way of weakening one's impulse for work than to cut down on
one's play or, as some people would have it, blend the one with the other. For the good worker, the man whose work means
more to him than just a wage, is ever the good player,
the man who plays to the maximum of his ability for the sake of his work. But if one wishes to cut down on one's play,
why not cut down on one's work or, better still, give-up working altogether.
NO FREEDOM
WITHOUT BONDAGE: Freedom is merely a temporary release from bondage, by no
means a permanent one. It is the
negative antithesis to the positive bondage, a reprieve from that which should
normally be the predominating influence in a person's life. Without bondage there can be no freedom,
without freedom no bondage. Whether your
particular bondage be in writing, painting, reading, lecturing, clerking,
washing, printing, sweeping, typing, building, driving, or anything else, the
essential thing is that you should be living as a freeman for the sake of your
bondage rather than as a bondsman for the sake of your freedom. For to live as a bondsman for the sake of
your freedom is to live negatively, to aspire from what may be termed the negative-positive
to the positive-negative, rather than from the negative to the positive as one
should normally do.
After all, it isn't so much the kind of work one does ... as to how one
feels about doing it that really matters.
One can live just as positively by being a clerk, a typist, a shop
assistant, a car mechanic, etc., as by being an artist, a manager, a teacher,
or an army officer. It depends entirely
on the type of person one is.
But if one is doing one thing and
genuinely desires to do something else - ah! that is
when one is living against the grain, living as a freeman-in-bondage rather
than as a bondsman-in-freedom, and should therefore do something to alter
it. For in a predominantly positive
life, a life that identifies with its work and can properly express itself
through that work, the freedom acquired once one's work is finished for the day
is always legitimately negative. The
individual concerned can afford, if needs be, to spend time chatting casually
to various friends and/or acquaintances, or watching a rather frivolous film,
or leisurely reading an inconsequential book, or going for a lengthy stroll, or
just idling somewhere by himself without feeling even the slightest need to get
down to some serious work, the kind of work he might otherwise feel that he
really ought to be doing in order not to waste any valuable time. But the man who
cannot 'waste' any time, after his official work is over for the day, isn't
living as well as he could be. In a
sense, he isn't really living at all!
FROM WINTER
TO AUTUMN: If, in maintaining our established terminology, we are in accord
that winter is the negative season of the year and summer, by contrast, the
positive one, then I deem spring to be the negative-positive and autumn the
positive-negative. Hence we find the
seasons following the sequence: negative, negative-positive, positive,
positive-negative, with the two divisible seasons, viz. spring and autumn,
progressing to their respective consummations in summer and winter. Since the positive always arises from the
negative, we find its earliest manifestation in spring, its consummation in
summer, and its gradual decline in autumn; the winter, or root season, being
the eternal negative from which the process of growth and decay must again proceed.
Strictly speaking, however, there are only
two (not four) divisions to the year, viz. winter and summer, in accordance
with the fundamental dualism underlining the activity of all life on this
planet, the transitional periods, as it were, of spring and autumn being an
inceptive extension of summer and winter respectively, and granting us a useful
analogy with the half-light states before dawn and after sunset, which we term
twilight.
NO 'MOTHER
NATURE': Nature has often been referred to as 'Mother Nature', a notion which
suggests a feminine or negative character when, to speak metaphorically, it is
neither feminine nor masculine but a subtle combination of each. For nature's only feminine season is the winter,
whereas summer is, by way of an antithesis, distinctly masculine, and autumn
and spring are a reverse combination of, in the one case, a declining
masculinity and an ascending femininity and, in the other case, a declining
femininity and an ascending masculinity.
Thus the notion of 'Mother Nature' is only
valid insofar as it represents half the truth, not the whole truth. For nature is effectively androgynous.
MALE AND
FEMALE PRIDE: A beautiful woman is usually delighted by the admiring attentions
of the good-looking men she happens to encounter in life. She takes much of her pride and happiness
from the fact that such men find her attractive and therefore worthy of their
admiration. Her face often betrays her self-satisfaction,
the knowledge that she is desirable.
Thus her pride is direct; it is rooted in herself
and requires no external props - other, of course, than the necessary or
desired means of adorning her body.
Not so, however, with a man! As a rule, he is not so
proud of himself as a kind of 'thing-in-itself', but mostly in relation to what
he represents, to the kind of work he does and the degree of respect or
recognition (if any) he can expect from that.
Take away his work and you automatically deprive him of the chief means
whereby he can feel admirable to himself.
His pride isn't centred, like that of an attractive woman, directly upon
himself but only indirectly, through the medium of what he has achieved and
continues to achieve in life. If he is
to be admired, it will be as a musician, lawyer, sportsman, soldier, doctor,
builder, disc jockey, politician, manager, painter, writer, etc., according to
the nature of his temperament, talents, and social position.
But if he is without work, then there is
very little that he can be genuinely proud of; he is not encouraged, by nature,
to regard himself as admirable in himself to anything like the same extent as
an attractive woman, and so he is inevitably at a distinct disadvantage to such
a woman in the same predicament. For men
and women are, and will remain, fundamentally different creatures.
AGAINST
FOLLY: It isn't necessarily unnatural to rebel against human folly but, more
usually, an indirect indication of one's own folly. For even if a man understands the
inevitability and, indeed, absolute legitimacy of folly, even if he recognizes
it as part of a duality which, in antithesis to wisdom, ultimately guarantees
its opposite, there is no reason why he shouldn't continue to rebel against it
precisely because of its periodic prevalence within himself. Hence his own folly will override his
intellectual acknowledgement of its ultimate legitimacy and, consequently,
enable him to continue acting 'unreasonably', or in apparent contradiction of
his theoretical awareness.
However, there is of course another and
perhaps more serious way of viewing the problem - namely, through the
realization that a man naturally looks down on his periodic folly because, in
addition to causing him inconvenience, it forms the negative antithesis to his
wisdom or good sense. After all, a being
who is essentially geared to the positive must consequently take rather
a condescending view of the negative, and so, by rejecting folly, he really
acts 'reasonably'.
Here is further proof, in explanation of
the above contradiction, that the power of practice is somewhat stronger than
that of theory. No matter what we know,
we can only act in accordance with nature which, in human terms, is far more
comprehensive than we may sometimes care to imagine.
SUSPENDED
JUDGEMENT: I have never seen a ghost and have absolutely no reason to believe
in the existence of a spirit world.
Where, however, spirits are claimed to manifest themselves in some way,
usually for the benefit of a communion of like minds gathered together at a
séance, it may be assumed that those taking part in the proceedings have been
conditioned to participate in a state of receptivity or expectation which, if
not permitting the entry of hallucinatory material into each individual
consciousness, at least permits a degree of such material to affect someone, if
only the medium.
Taking this contention at face-value, it
would appear that the self-discipline necessary for the attainment of the
requisite atmosphere is of consummate importance in determining the extent to
which one opens the door, as it were, into one's own 'spirit world' and
thereupon deceives oneself as to the extent of that world's objective
reality. For if one wasn't sufficiently
disciplined (or deceived) to begin with, there would be very little chance of
either audibly or visually fostering an hallucinatory
condition that would fully satisfy the demands of the occasion.
As, however, for those comparatively
eccentric types who inherit or develop a perverse hankering after such impalpable
entities as spirits, and who have, to be sure, encountered these entities
during the course of their individual travels - can one not simply presume them
to be especially susceptible to this particular form of hallucination? After all, the human world is undeniably
sympathetic to diverse manifestations of insanity, stupidity, self-deception,
etc., and - if I am not equally deceived in contending this - it is fairly
common knowledge that the human mind is capable of believing what it chooses or
wants to believe, not necessarily what it ought to!
Of course, the debate
between spiritualists and rationalists will doubtless drag on for some time to
come. But, in the interests of
rational investigation, I can at least posit the hypothesis that what is
commonly taken for a spirit by the spiritualistic fraternity is nothing more nor less than an apparently external recognition of
internally-induced phenomena, or some such similar quasi-holographic
derangement.... Perhaps, in seeking confirmation of this, one would do well to
consult the writings of Carl Jung for a thorough diagnosis of what the
subconscious mind is capable of engendering!
AGAINST
REINCARNATION: If man was wholly rational he wouldn't have evolved and, in many
cases, actually believed in the theory of reincarnation. For reincarnation is patently a superstition,
and one, moreover, which would seem to presuppose that, once having left the
body of a dead person, a highly-developed and self-motivated 'live' soul will
eventually find its way back to the world via the vagina of a mother-to-be and,
in forcing its way into her womb, somehow manage to link-up with the incipient
foetus there only to reappear, some nine months later, in the guise of a
new-born infant! Fantastic as that is,
one has then got to stomach the even more fantastic outcome of the parents of
this child eventually being able to recognize it as their own, to discern
within and upon its face various traits of their respective physical and
spiritual characteristics, and to thereupon consider it a legitimate extension
of themselves.
Now if, as we were led to suppose, the
child's soul initially came from elsewhere, the basic composition of this soul
must surely be different from that of the parents' souls either taken
separately or in combination - in fact, so different as to create a largely
incongruous human being the heredity of which the parents would have
considerable difficulty in claiming responsibility for.
But, of course, all this is absolute
nonsense, the sort of intellectual nonsense so adroitly exposed by Bertrand
Russell, and generally promulgated with the assistance of such pompous-sounding
terms as metempsychosis and reincarnation, to the lasting detriment of
reason! That mankind must ever succumb
to illusions of one sort or another, we know only too well. But they must be illusions that fool even the
philosophical inquisitors, not ones so well-worn and obviously vulnerable to
rational criticism that we have no choice but to obey our intellectual
conscience and sweep them aside in the interests of new truths.
SUPERSTITION
UNIVERSAL: Just as, up to a point, each man's filth smells sweetly to him
alone, so, likewise, does each nation's superstitions appear feasible to it
alone, the religious beliefs of certain other nations appearing little more
than childish by comparison. Yet people
are everywhere 'the double and equal of man', to cite Baudelaire, and thus
prone to the creation or maintenance of similar religious hypotheses themselves,
if for no other reason than their common humanity.
Now occasionally it happens that a
religiously-inclined individual actually 'sees through' the play of illusions
he had previously taken for truths, that he becomes disillusioned with the
superstitions of his community and, without fully realizing that people are
everywhere alike, anxious to compensate himself for this loss by adopting what
he then considers to be the superior and more rational beliefs of another
nation. So off he goes, with a distinctly
supercilious air, to the fresh pastures of Oriental, African, or Latin American
superstition, much consoled by the assumption that he has 'seen through' the
superstitions of his native land and, as a reward for this, is now about to
embark upon the study of a superior culture.
But to just what do you suppose all this
will lead? Either he will become
disillusioned with the new beliefs or, what's worse, fall a prey to them. And if the latter, then rest assured that his
understanding of human nature, with its rational/irrational oscillations, will
remain forever incomplete.
THE END OF
THE WORLD: I have heard talk that the end of the world will occur at a certain
predictable date in the near future, in fact either at the turn-of-the-century
or, according to the stronger views of the more pessimistic prophets of
eschatological clairvoyance and apocalyptic severity, within the next few
months (though one might suppose the world to be already finished and living
past itself and in spite of itself, so to speak, if one were to take the warnings
or predictions of these obsessed prophets of annihilation at face-value!).
However, considering that so many
discouraging predictions of this type have already outlived themselves and
become thoroughly obsolete, while the world has continued to exist, to change,
and even to progress, it appears only logical to conclude further developments
of this ominous mania equally doomed to irrelevance, ridicule, and
oblivion. Indeed, one might even hazard
a fairly optimistic if not altogether comforting guess that not even a nuclear
war would actually destroy the entire planet, would in fact cause it to
disintegrate. But if the world could survive
such a battering, then what-on-earth can all this 'end-of-the-world'
speculation be about?
Leaving religious considerations to one
side, I would imagine the end of the material world, as indeed the end of the
solar system of which this planet is but a tiny component, to have intimate
connections with the inevitable dissolution of the sun, an eventuality
apparently not liable to occur for another eight-thousand million years but,
nevertheless, one which, if man is to survive drastic changes of temperature in
the meantime and break away from this solar system in order to establish a
better life for himself elsewhere, would seem to contribute towards justifying
the evolutionary thrusts behind the various space-research programmes, and
thereby put a stopper into the fatuous mouths of those who foolishly imagine
that a myopic attention to the affairs of the world is all that really matters.
ART AS
IDEALITY: It is my firm contention that an artist is never more genuine than
when he adheres to ideality and, like Blake, Dadd, Dali, Turner, Picasso, Bourne-Jones, Chagall, Burra, Van Gogh, and Kandinsky,
invents a world largely of his own which contrasts with the everyday reality to
which one is normally accustomed. He who
paints me another world, creates unique images or, alternatively, reproduces
images from myth, religion, or literature, I regard as a genuine artist. The others, the portrait painters, realists,
and naturalists, I regard as craftsmen or draughtsmen, men who apply an almost
scientifically literal approach to their work, who create a hybrid which, in
sacrificing imagination to factual reproduction, is neither science nor art but
a mediator between the two, a sort of parallel to academic philosophy, which
usually has its boundaries somewhere between the realms of science and
religion.
But the truly creative artist deals
chiefly with the ideal, the world of the imagination. It is he who establishes an antithesis to
science and temporarily frees us from the oppressiveness and overwhelming
seriousness of factual truth. His greatness is guaranteed by the combination of
two indispensable ingredients - imagination and technique. With only one of these he is not an artist
but, at best, a dilettante or craftsman, depending on the ingredient in
question. With both, however, he is the
true spokesman and practitioner of a discipline which stands in an antithetical
relationship to science - not, be it noted, as its enemy, but as its
complement, the negative pole of a dual integrity and, consequently, a vocation
dedicated to the service of creatures who are unable to live without illusions
but must forever oscillate between the two poles if they are to remain
balanced, or relatively sane.
Yes, in the final analysis, art is
dualistically inferior to science, as illusion to truth. But science is in no way able to exist
without art, not, anyway, while there is anything approximating to a civilized
view of life in the world. For the two
pursuits are interdependent and therefore must remain firmly committed to their
respective tasks.
Strictly speaking, there is no such thing
as 'scientific art' (not to be confused with science-fiction), any more than
there is really such a thing as 'artistic science'. An art which deserts its rightful
responsibility in imagination to serve the cause of science, i.e. by drawing
inspiration directly from scientific fact, is unwittingly hindering both itself
and science by being insufficiently antithetical to it. An art which draws its inspiration from the
'real' instead of the 'ideal' is fundamentally perverse. In fact, it is no longer art at all but, as
mentioned above, a kind of hybrid, and very often a lost cause in a dark age.
No, if art is to do itself proper justice
it must find its chief inspiration within the imagination, within that
strangely disguised mythical world, surreal world, impressionistic world,
expressionistic world, abstract world, fantasy world, or any other 'illusory'
world which affords us an authentic contrast to everyday reality. Is it any wonder that those artists whom I
listed at the beginning of this essay have all achieved due recognition as
great painters? No, not if one
understands exactly what a true artist is.
Now what applies to the art of painting
applies no less to the 'arts' of music, literature, and sculpture, where
imagination and technique are still the tools most needed for the shaping of
anything artistically worthwhile. But
let us leave the final word on this subject with Oscar Wilde, whose Decay of
Lying remains one of the most eloquent, lucid, and pertinent dialogues ever
written in defence of art: 'Art begins with abstract decoration, with purely
imaginative and pleasurable work dealing with what is unreal and
non-existent. This is the first
stage. Then Life becomes fascinated with
this new wonder, and asks to be admitted into the charmed circle. Art takes Life as part of her rough material,
recreates it, and refashions it in fresh forms, is absolutely indifferent to
fact, invents, imagines, dreams, and keeps between itself and reality the
impenetrable barrier of beautiful style, of decorative or ideal treatment. The third stage is when Life gets the upper
hand, and drives Art out into the wilderness.
This is the true decadence, and it is from this that we are now
suffering.'
GREAT ART:
What one normally wants from art, to take a particular if arguably somewhat
conservative viewpoint, is a feeling that the work in question lies far above
one's own creative abilities. I mean if,
as so often happens nowadays, one is left with the highly distinctive
impression that, had one so desired, one could have done just as well if not
better than the so-called artist oneself, then the work in question is
obviously open to suspicion and probably leaves one either unmoved or, worse
still, dejected.
Now when, by contrast, one contemplates a
Dali, there is usually no doubt in one's mind that the scene or event it portrays
is a work of genius, that skill and imagination have been combined to virtually
the utmost possible extent to produce something both precious and
inimitable. It is great art, despite its
comparatively strange, wayward, and at times positively horrific nature,
because it still manages to convince the viewer of having something
extraordinarily ingenious about it which he could never hope to emulate
himself. With great art one generally
feels oneself to be in the presence of the divinity of man, of man become great
creator through the manipulation of a technique and imagination which induces
in one a feeling of amazement as to the seemingly infinite extent of man's
capacity for artistic greatness.
Unfortunately, however, modern art so
often falls short of artistic greatness (not to mention genuine art) because,
lacking both the requisite devotion and talent for the execution of anything
great, its practitioners have lost track of the essentially idealistic nature
of art and allowed their productions to become perverted into something so
pathetically commercial, and hence dominated by market forces, as to be
anything but artistic. It isn't, by any
account, a straightforward reflection of contemporary life that one desires from
art; for such a reflection can be captured exceedingly well by the
predominantly impersonal use of a journalistic camera. Still less is it the portrayal of a blank
canvas, or of a canvas portraying, at best, a few straight or squiggly lines
and cryptic blotches. On the contrary,
it is the brilliance, skill, imagination, spirit, purpose - in sum, the
personality which a great artist inevitably bestows upon his work that the
genuine art enthusiast desires, not the distressing spectacle of exhibits which
resemble the predictably banal productions of the average junior-school art
class!
NO HEALTH
WITHOUT DISEASE: Some people like to imagine that man will one day conquer
disease and that, in accordance with the fruits of social progress, he will
subsequently live in a utopia where health, justice, peace, happiness,
prosperity, sanity, fraternity, beauty, truth, goodness, and love will reign
supreme. Now while not wishing to
deprive such people of their fond hopes for the future, it nevertheless occurs
to me that they are unlikely to materialize in a life conditioned by dualistic
exchanges, as is invariably the case with human life. For it would certainly seem, if precedence is
anything to judge by, that health cannot prevail without sickness, justice
without injustice, peace without some form of war, happiness without sadness,
prosperity without poverty, sanity without insanity, etc., and that, as soon as
man plugs a hole in one context, a fresh hole eventually appears elsewhere, and
with greater determination than on the previous occasion, so that he is forever
juggling reality into new patterns, forever creating new manifestations of the
basic polar attributes.
Admittedly, there is a fair chance that
man may eventually come to terms with the common cold (bearing in mind that
there are a hundred or more different viruses with which to deal), influenza,
cancer (which also comes in many guises), schizophrenia, and other such
contemporary scourges. But no sooner
will he have done so than disease will acquire other manifestations in which to
maintain the polarity of health and sickness, thereby safeguarding the
existence of health while simultaneously providing fresh sources of
investigation for both doctors and scientists alike.
In sum, the fight against disease can in
no way detract from the fundamental integrity of life. This fight is not an indication of the
imperfection of life, as might at first appear, but a part of its overall
integrity within the human framework, with its dualistic criteria.
ILLNESS NO
OBJECTION: Suppressing common illnesses by the regular use of various drugs and
medicines usually reflects an audacious attempt by man to cheat nature out of
its rightful influence. For whenever a
common illness is prevented from running its natural course, it invariably
takes revenge upon the assailant by staging a fiercer resistance (much as a
soldier will put up a stronger fight when forced into a perilous situation),
thereby making one feel a lot worse.
Furthermore, it should be remembered that illnesses are not anomalous
occurrences which shouldn't happen but, on the contrary, very natural
occurrences which, if anything, strengthen one's taste for good health, so that
the unnatural and artificial suppression of them tends (except in the most serious
cases) to be utopian rather than realistic, the sort of disregard for polarity
and the interdependence of antitheses which, in other contexts, would lead to
the unhealthy suppression or, more accurately, attempted suppression of hate
for the sake of love, illusion for the sake of truth, evil for the sake of
good, or sadness for the sake of happiness.
But this disregard for polarity, this
attempt to eradicate an illness as quickly as possible (tied-up, as it
undoubtedly is, with the materialistic requirements of a consumer society),
only serves to complicate and aggravate matters - a salutary lesson which, if
properly understood, could lead to the judicious suppression of meddlesome
drugs or medicines and to the adoption, if not on the part of the medical profession
in general then at least on the part of the general public, of a more dualistic
view concerning the legitimacy of illness!
Needless to say, there is obviously
something wrong, ignorant, and even cowardly about a man who, at the earliest
intimation of a common cold, sore throat, headache, stomach ache, temperature,
or some other such minor ailment, rushes to the doctor or chemist in search of
a miracle-working cure when, in accordance with the fundamental workings of
nature, it is only from the illness itself that a genuine cure can come. Indeed, one might even suppose that the easy
availability of an artificial cure induces people to be less thoughtful about
their health. For is it not the case
that a majority of common illnesses are usually incurred as the consequence of
a stupid action, and can thus be seen as a kind of punishment and warning to
people to be more careful in future!
Be that as it may, one can nonetheless
maintain that illnesses generally contain their own cure, are by no means
superfluous occurrences, and should be left, in nine cases out of ten, to run
their natural course rather than be meddled with by an impatient consumer
society in the grip not only of market forces but of the market as such, and
which too often shies away from the dualistic integrity of life instead of
facing up to and bearing with it for its own good.
THE
'PLIMSOLL LINE' OF SLEEP: A life without sleeping, or a life where the polarity
of being awake and being asleep has broken down, would also amount, if endurable
for any length of time, to a life without waking, i.e. to a sort of
death-in-life, or perpetual consciousness of external reality which, in its
unrelenting intensity, would inevitably prove so intolerable as to drive one
either to suicide or, failing that, an asylum.
But a life with its natural quota of sleep is, by comparison, a
fortunate life - indeed, one doesn't realize just how fortunate
until one has regularly had experience of insomnia! For whether or not we realize it, sleep is
the greatest medicine we possess.
Consequently there is some truth in the
notion that a man who lives well also sleeps well. One might contend, in this context, that
sleep becomes a kind of 'Plimsoll line' of correct living, a guideline by which
one can establish an accurate criterion as to whether one is living naturally
or unnaturally, agreeably or disagreeably, sensibly or foolishly. I mean if, as is sometimes the case, we are
not sleeping as well as we believe we should, might it not be an indication
from our subconscious mind that we are living against the grain, as it were, by
either taking too much social and/or occupational responsibility upon ourselves
or, conversely, not taking enough?
Hence our insomnia could be interpreted as
both a warning and a punishment, a method employed by nature to stir us into
taking a remedial course of action. In
which case it should be evident that regular use of sleeping pills is not the
remedial course of action we should take.
For rather than rectifying the situation as it ought to be rectified,
i.e. through action establishing a more healthy and tolerable mode of life,
they usually further complicate it by imposing an artificial sleep upon us
which, by interfering with the subconscious, hardly compensates us for natural
sleep.
Thus we are running away from ourselves at
the very moment when we ought to be facing-up to and eventually overcoming our
personal difficulties, when instead of acting like a man who, because of
various problems in his life, drinks himself into alcoholism (and thereby makes
matters worse for himself), we should be noting the instructions which emanate
from our subconscious mind and subsequently set about doing whatever we can to
obey them, if for no other reason than our own good. For anything else is
inherently perverse and, as such, it can only aggravate the problem, to
increase rather than decrease our afflictions.
A WIDER
VIEW OF VICE: For a majority of people vice is usually associated with such
controversial or taboo subjects as hard-drug addiction, alcoholism, cigarette
smoking, pot smoking, prostitution, masturbation, sodomy, pederasty, gambling,
idleness, lechery, vandalism, hooliganism, and foul language - a list which,
though by no means exhaustive, suffices to indicate the general trend of
popular thinking. Now in accepting this
rather narrow view of vice, it seems quite unlikely that many people will come
to realize how loquacity, temperance, exuberance, lethargy, chastity,
sociability, conscientiousness, athleticism, art fanaticism, political
fanaticism, inquisitiveness, acquisitiveness, pomposity, presumption,
superstition, piety, ambition, reclusion, or anything else which might
ordinarily be regarded as a fairly innocuous if not praiseworthy inclination
often degenerate, when pushed beyond a certain point of intensity or duration,
into some of the most lethal vices of all!
Who, for instance, could seriously deny
that religious superstition or fanaticism of one kind or another has caused
more death and suffering, over the centuries, than hard-drug addiction,
alcoholism, and cigarette smoking put together?
Similarly, isn't the phrase 'excessive political fanaticism' likely to
engender rather painful connotations when one cares to reflect upon world
history, and most especially upon recent European history? And even prolonged chastity - what a terrible
vice that can be for making various people more argumentative, spiteful,
dissatisfied, intolerant, etc., than they would otherwise have been, if
permitted a normal, healthy sex-life!
But, in saying all this, let us not kid
ourselves that vice can or indeed should be completely eradicated. For, in all probability, one would first have
to eradicate human life. Either that,
or one would have to turn one's back on life to such an extent that it
inevitably took revenge upon one by becoming absolutely hellish, an
inclination, alas, which would seem to have possessed a perverse charm for
considerable numbers of obdurate, would-be ascetics ever since the dawn of
civilization, and one which in no way appears destined to be discarded or
outgrown while man retains a semblance of his innate and altogether
indispensable predilection for virtue.
MISUSED
CONCEPTS: It is commonly understood that words are symbols designating
concepts. Our ancestors at sometime
conceived the possibility of a symbol to designate the concept 'a love of
mankind' and named it 'philanthropy'.
They likewise conceived of an antonym to this symbol and named it
'misanthropy', or 'a hatred of mankind'.
Not content with this, they then sought to justify the existence of
these symbols, these concepts, by taking a bold step further and actually
applying them to various individuals, to people whom, in their conceptual
presumption, they somehow regarded as eligible candidates. Now in consequence of this social
indiscretion, later generations gradually became aware of the existence of
'philanthropists' and 'misanthropists' without apparently realizing that the
concepts behind these symbols had absolutely no foundation in reality, that it
was impossible either to love or hate mankind even for a few moments,
considering that 'mankind' is merely an abstraction. Thus followed the history of an outrageous
misunderstanding!
Of course, one can always love or hate the
odd individual here and there, one can even come to
feel similar sentiments towards a few people here and there. But to actually consider such love 'a love of
mankind' or such hate 'a hatred of mankind' would be more than a gross
misunderstanding: it would be the height of imbecility! For, in reality, one can no more love or hate
mankind than one can love or hate the fish kind, the bird kind, the animal
kind, the insect kind, the vegetable kind, or any other kind. In fact, it is virtually impossible not to
conclude that one can never be a philanthropist or a misanthropist under any
circumstances. For even if, in taking
the terms in a much wider sense, one does good (according to one's notion of
what constitutes 'the good') to one section of the community, it invariably
follows that one will necessarily do bad
to and fall out-of-favour with another section of it, and vice versa.
Hence I can only contend that the world
has never produced a single philanthropist: neither Buddha, Christ, Mohammed,
St. Christopher, St. Francis, Shakespeare, Florence Nightingale, Dickens, Marx,
Whitman, Gladstone, Tolstoy, Shaftsbury, Chamberlain, nor anyone else, and
never will produce one; that the world has never produced a single
misanthropist: neither Machiavelli, Swift, Caligula, de Sade,
Bonaparte, Baudelaire, Franco, Dostoyevsky, Stalin, Lautréamont,
Crowley, Nietzsche, Hitler, Mussolini, nor anyone else, and never will produce
one.
Indeed, it isn't an everyday occurrence
either to love or hate anyone at all, even one's closest companions. But to actually love or hate someone of whom
one has absolutely no knowledge, someone who is no more familiar to one than
the paintings or posters on the walls of the millions of bedrooms throughout
the world, is an utter impossibility! It
is something that people are unlikely to imagine possible so long as, firstly,
they acknowledge the exact implications of human limitations and, secondly,
they acknowledge the exact implications of the concepts they choose to
symbolize through words.
AGAINST
RACIAL INEQUALITY: Can one seriously contend that an Ash is superior to a
Beech, an Oak superior to a Hawthorn, a Beech superior to an Oak, an Oak
superior to an Ash, a Sycamore superior to an Elm, a Pine superior to a Yew, a
Fir superior to a Rosewood, a Yew superior to an Elm, a Sycamore superior to a
Pine, and so on? If so, on what
criterion does one base one's contention?
Is it enough to base it on the relative number of trees in each species
(those with fewest numbers being the most precious because rare), their
respective size, leafage, colouring, seed, strength, industrial usefulness,
age, etc., or would that ultimately prove somewhat presumptuous?
Admittedly where, for example, two Oaks
that had developed unequally in different environments were concerned, where
one had become sickly and warped because of a lack of fresh air, moisture,
sunshine, space, and official protection against both man and disease, while
the other had developed under the best possible conditions and consequently
become healthy and strong, one would of course be justified in concluding the
latter tree superior to the former.
However, what one could not do so confidently would be to set up a scale
of merit applicable to the most well-developed trees in each species, to assert
a Teak categorically superior to a Rosewood, or an Elm categorically superior
to a Hawthorn.
Similarly, in terms of the human kind (and
basing one's judgement solely within the confines of each class), can one
seriously contend that a Slav is superior to an Indian, a Turk superior to a Teuton, a Latin superior to an Anglo-Saxon, a Celt superior
to a Mongol, an Arab superior to a Zulu, a Mongol superior to a Latin, a Teuton superior to a Turk, a Jew superior to a Pict, a Shona superior to an
Apache, an Anglo-Saxon superior to a Zulu, a Bantu superior to a Kurd, an
Eskimo superior to a Lapp, etc., and then, in going far beyond that, draw-up a
definitive scale of racial superiority relative to the total number of races,
or presumed races, currently in existence?
Can one? Would one ever be in a
position to do that? Hasn't almost every
race produced great men, attained to outstanding achievements in art,
literature, music, philosophy, architecture, medicine, religion, politics,
etc., and thus contributed to both the development and decline of the many
ingenious civilizations which have appeared throughout the six-thousand years
of man's reign on earth?
Surely it would be a gross stupidity to
maintain that an intelligent attitude to life ought to incorporate an awareness
as to which races one's race (if known) is either inferior or superior to,
other than in the relative sense of its being economically, industrially,
militarily, philosophically, culturally, politically, spiritually, or socially
either ahead of or behind certain other civilized races at any given point in
time. Surely it is quite enough, under
the prevailing restrictions imposed upon us by the absence of various
scientific certainties, to know one's race to be different, the inheritor of
particular advantages and disadvantages, and then to live in accordance with
those differences, whatever the consequences, for as long as that race
exists. Truly, a genuinely inferior race
would have died out long ago!
THE
TRANSIENCE OF DEATH: Death, as the living understand
it, is not antithetical to life but to birth since, like the latter, it is a
momentary phenomenon rather than something that extends over a long period of
time, the way life usually does. Once a
person has died, the phenomenon of death is consummated and the corpse
thereupon begins to decompose, leaving, after a number of years, scarcely a
trace of its remains. Now where, in
consequence of this process of decomposition, there is nothing or next to nothing
remaining, the word 'dead' has no real applicability. One cannot refer to a hole in the ground with
nothing in it as the hole of a dead person, even if it is still officially a
grave by dint of the fact that a corpse was once buried there in some kind of
coffin. And so it should be fairly
obvious that 'the dead' are really very transient phenomena, nothing to work-up
to the status of an antithesis to the living.
Montaigne's life, for example, came to an end in 1592, his
corpse doubtless quickly began to decompose, and one would, I guess, be quite
justified in believing that by 1610 the former essayist had been reduced to a
skeleton, to which one normally applies an 'it' rather than a 'he'. Thus, strictly speaking, one cannot say of Montaigne that 'he has been dead for over four-hundred years'
(since the process of death and decay only lasts as long as there is anything
approximating to a 'he' discernible), but simply that 'he died in 1592'.
Consequently, as an opposition to life
conceived as a period of time during which one is conscious of existing, we
have the not-life, i.e. the period before birth and after death which embraces
both foetus and corpse. As an opposition
to life conceived in terms of that which lives, i.e. the animate, we have the inanimate. And, finally, as an opposition to birth we
have - death.
PHILOSOPHY
VERSES INSULAR INTOLERANCE: One of the most useful things about the genuine
philosopher in relation to both science and religion, and even to art and
politics, is that, being neither partisan to the one nor to the other, he is in
a fairly favourable position to establish a general perspective as to what the
respective adherents of these branches of human activity are likely to think of
each other and, more importantly, what they each represent. Consequently, inasmuch as his authority and
vocation permit, he can at least draw attention to the danger inherent in
situations whereby the partisans of the one camp become so obsessed with the
furtherance of their own particular perspective that they completely fail to
take account of the other camp's perspective, and duly set about either
undermining it or, worse still, having the other camp done away with
altogether.
Now that may seem a somewhat exaggerated
not to say unlikely possibility in the context of Western pluralism, but it
nevertheless remains a fact that cases of this kind of insular intolerance and
misunderstanding are by no means as infrequent as may at first appear. There are, for example, eminent astronomers
who, with the most extensive knowledge of astronomical developments, are of
such an ignorance in astrological matters as to be of the opinion that this
latter field of activity is not only infra dig, but entirely unworthy
of the credence of rational minds and, consequently, of little if any
account. Now, in all probability, there
are eminent astrologers who, with a time-consuming dedication to astrology, are
likely to maintain a similarly unappreciative opinion of astronomy, or of
certain astronomical contentions, which, when one considers the limitations of
their perspective, isn't altogether surprising.
This is an example, in a somewhat
simplified and perhaps over-obvious way, of what I believe to be the tendency
of specialists to become so enclosed by the limitations of their own particular
fields of activity that they pose a danger to each other and, by extension, to
those who read them. Here, I think, is
where the philosopher - and the contemporary philosopher more than ever - can
prove of some use in his endeavour to maintain a wider perspective and, if he
cannot directly prevent the representatives of certain other causes from
regularly denouncing one another as enemies of enlightenment, at least draw
attention to the possibility that they themselves may not be as enlightened as
they like to imagine.
As an afterthought (and in extending our
discussion beyond the predominantly occult realm of astrology into that of
religion-proper), it ought to be borne in mind that we live in an age of
science rather than faith, a fact which makes it obligatory for a majority of
us to view life from a more rational angle than was formerly the case. For where our ancestors mostly viewed life
through 'religious eyes', and thereupon accused those who invented important
scientific instruments or in any way furthered science of blasphemy, we, in our
turn, are for the most part inclined to view life through 'scientific eyes',
and to accuse those who still believe in miracles or religious mysteries of
ignorance and superstition. The fact,
however, that both viewpoints are equally lopsided and partial only serves to
indicate that a more balanced perspective between the religious attitude
(whatever its subsequent manifestation) and the scientific attitude has yet to
be achieved. Presumably this will come
about in some future age.
In the meantime, however, a majority of
thinking people will doubtless continue to accept their inheritance as
offspring of the twentieth century and, in accordance with its Zeitgeist of
empirical secularity, continue to regard those who possess a vestige of true
religious faith as anachronisms, without wondering whether their future secular
or overly rational equivalents won't be similarly regarded by the more
'balanced' majority of a less sceptical age.
INDIVIDUAL
WISDOM: Wisdom consists, amongst other things, in not understanding everything
one reads, not liking everything one reads, not believing everything one reads,
and not remembering everything one reads.
A surfeit of wise ideas is, after all, another kind of folly, and there
are many gifted men who foolishly consider themselves wise on account of the
extent of their reading. What, do they
not consider themselves wise enough already?
Were they not born with the rudiments of wisdom, or
are they now somewhat uncertain, in this age of material prosperity, as to
exactly what it is?
Well, let us frankly admit that,
irrespective of any aid the dictionary may give us, wisdom is not something
that can be simply defined, since it takes as many forms as there are people,
and what would suit one person, at any given time, could well be the ruination
of another. For we all possess a wisdom
peculiar to our daily circumstances and, depending on the nature of those
circumstances, the kind of wisdom each one of us possesses must inevitably
manifest itself as folly to someone else, to someone who, living in a different
context, is not obliged to adopt identical tactics to us. There is no man who is without his quota of
wisdom. Contend otherwise and you draw
on your capacity for folly. Accept it,
and your wisdom automatically leaps to the fore.
The wisdom of this moment may give way to
the folly of the next. Whatever you
understand to be wisdom here, you may be obliged to pay for with foolishness
elsewhere. You don't become wiser
generally, but only in certain contexts.
Your given quota of wisdom remains the same whether you read all the
philosophy of the nineteenth century or exclusively dedicate yourself to
painting. The wisdom of the philosopher
is not the same as that of the painter.
Whereas the former may advise you to avoid taking various contentions of
a particular philosopher too seriously and will indicate, by way of
compensation, other contentions which he believes to be of consummate
importance, the latter may warn you against over-using a particular colour or
tone, and will draw your attention, it may be, to certain delicate harmonies of
tonal composition which he feels to be of great beauty and technical
significance. Their different kinds of
wisdom are largely applicable to their respective occupations and, as such,
they are as wise as they need be, each man having to contend with matters
strictly pertinent to his own activity and to no-one else's.
Inevitably, this is the case for
everybody. There is the wisdom of the
monk, stockbroker, lawyer, baker, clerk, postman, teacher, cook, etc. Each of them knows what he has to do and, if
he wants to survive, each one does it as well as possible, thereby being as
wise as he needs to be within his particular context. Now a poet isn't necessarily wiser than a
clerk; he is simply wiser in his own field.
Much of what he does is only relevant to poets, and consequently much of
what he says will strike a clerk as being somewhat foolish, just as much of
what the latter does and says will strike him as being
somewhat foolish, even though they are both doing and saying what they must.
But is a man any the less wise for
becoming a clerk instead of a poet? Some
poets may think so, especially if they belong to that vainglorious breed of men
who always consider their own profession superior to everyone else's. However, people of a philosophic turn-of-mind
will incline to think otherwise. For if
a man isn't really interested in poetry, and is insufficiently gifted in poetic
composition to become a professional poet, then his fundamental attitude to
poetry will probably be either one of mild curiosity or, more likely, general
indifference, so that any suggestion to the effect that he ought to have
taken-up with poetry instead of, say, clerking will meet with little sympathy,
its being inferred that not everyone was born to do the same thing!
Yet the logical implication of this is
something that the self-conceit of certain illustrious poets may make them
overlook - namely that men come in many shapes and sizes, in consequence of
which the means to salvation for one would surely be the road to damnation of
another!
No, it is not for us to presume a man less
wise for becoming a clerk, lawyer, builder, or grocer instead of a poet,
musician, painter, or sculptor, but to assume that whatever he does he does
because he is unable, for a variety of reasons, to do anything else - in short,
because it is the best thing for him. Heaven forbid that the human kind should ever
progress to a point where all men can become poets, composers, artists, or
writers simply because, with further development of machine technology, there
will be little or no requirement for anything else! Heaven forbid that we should look upon human
diversity as an objection, and subsequently endeavour to stamp everybody into
exactly the same mould!
Talented youths often imagine that life is
a battle for honours, a race to acquire the most prestigious places before it
is too late, rather than an exercise, amongst other things, in finding out what
one is especially good at and then in putting that ability or gift to the
service of mankind. But youth is only a
passing folly, an extra boost, as it were, to the essential nature of the
emerging man. For when he finally
emerges from his youthful pretensions into the more realistic perspective of
adulthood, he will realize that it is only within his power to do a few things
really well, and that he must do them to the best of his ability if he is to
pass muster on the world's stage.
Yet as to whether his particular
occupation makes him less wise than any of his differently-occupied fellows -
that is something I must confess to having serious reservations about! Perhaps he is mostly drawing upon his
foolishness when he does something he has no business doing, working in an
incompatible context, and consequently being a neurotic nuisance to both
himself and everybody else as well.
THE MEANING
AND PURPOSE OF LIFE: The meaning and purpose of life cannot reside in anything
which is subject to antithetical evaluation.
In other words it cannot reside in happiness, truth, love, goodness,
work, beauty, wisdom, knowledge, reasonableness, pleasure, virtue, etc.,
because of the inevitability and even necessity of sadness, illusion, hate,
evil, play, ugliness, folly, ignorance, unreasonableness, pain, vice, etc.,
which, by their regular (negative) intrusions, effectively guarantee the
intermittent prevalence of the former (positive) aspects of life, and are
therefore of crucial importance in the overall scheme of things.
No, the meaning and purpose of life has to
do with what Dr. Jolande Jacobi,
the Hungarian psychologist and disciple of Jung, terms 'the Way of
Individuation' - a development of the personality through the various stages of
life, with the invariable consequence of greater knowledge of the self both in
its relation to the individual and to the world generally. One doesn't foolishly strive to combat the
inherent dualism of life by taking an apparently one-sided though ultimately
self-deceptive stance in it. One
experiences this dualism as an eternal fact which, through its
comprehensiveness, inevitably redeems itself.
One could sum-up by saying that the meaning of life lies in life itself,
whereas the purpose of life is simply to live.
THE
INFERIOR NEGATIVE: Whatever exists in a negative relationship to the positive
component of a duality exists as its inferior, viz. night in relation to day,
illusion in relation to truth, evil in relation to goodness, sadness in
relation to happiness, pain in relation to pleasure, ugliness in relation to
beauty, weakness in relation to strength, etc.
The proof of this, if it isn't already self-evident, can be defined in
one of two ways, depending on the nature of the duality under consideration.
The case, for example, of night in
relation to day brings to our attention the fact that the night is simply a
time without sunlight, a time when one half of the earth has turned away from
the sun. Hence the night is quantitatively
inferior to the day because it lacks something that the day possesses - namely
sunlight. The case, however, of pain in
relation to pleasure brings to our attention the difference of quality between
a sensation which is disagreeable and one, by contrast, which is agreeable, the
former being undesirable and hence inferior to the latter.
Thus it can be contended that dualities
are essentially divisible into two categories: those which permit one to judge
the negative component quantitatively inferior to the positive one on account
of its lacking something which the latter possesses and, similarly, those which
permit one to judge the negative component qualitatively inferior to the
positive one on account of its undesirable feeling or sensation value. Examples in the first category include night
in relation to day, silence in relation to sound, darkness in relation to
light, ugliness in relation to beauty, weakness in relation to strength, evil
in relation to good, illusion in relation to
truth. Examples in the second category
include pain in relation to pleasure, sadness in relation to happiness, fear in
relation to hope, hate in relation to love, humility in relation to pride,
dejection in relation to elation, anger in relation to humour. The first category implies objective
phenomena, either internal or external, that we perceive but do not feel. The second category implies subjective
phenomena, either internal or external, that we feel but do not perceive.
FOUR
CATEGORIES: Dualities may be further subdivided, as I hinted above, into four
categories, viz. those which pertain to the Internal Objective, those which
pertain to the External Objective, those which pertain to the Internal
Subjective, and those, finally, which pertain to the External Subjective.
Those in the category of the Internal
Objective are dualities which we perceive internally but do not feel. Those in the category of the External
Objective are dualities which we perceive externally but do not feel. Examples of the former include
illusion/truth, sickness/health, past/future, absent/present. Examples of the latter include night/day,
dark/light, girl/boy, moon/sun.
Those in the category of the Internal
Subjective are dualities which we feel internally but do not perceive. Those in the category of the External Subjective
are dualities which we feel externally but do not perceive. Examples of the former include fear/hope,
hate/love, pain/pleasure, sadness/happiness. Examples
of the latter include cold/hot, rough/smooth, liquid/solid, soft/hard.
Thus it can be seen that both the Internal
Subjective and the Internal Objective signify abstract phenomena,
whereas both the External Subjective and the External Objective signify concrete
phenomena.
NEGATIVES
SERVE: Of what use would knowledgeable men be in any given subject if there
were no ignorant men in that same subject to learn from their knowledge? And of what use would ignorant men be in any
given subject if they were insufficiently ignorant to be of use to its knowledgeable
men?
But let us not deceive ourselves into
imagining the positive component of a duality to be in the service of its
negative component, i.e. that which commands ... to be in the service of that
which obeys, or that which helps ... to be in the service of that which
hinders, or that which hopes ... to be in the service of that which fears, or
that which loves ... to be in the service of that which hates when, in reality,
it is invariably the other way around.
Now as ignorance is negative in relation
to knowledge, one can only conclude the ignorant men in any given subject to be
in the service of its knowledgeable men.
Paradoxically, it is the pupil/student who serves the teacher/tutor
rather than vice versa.
SUCCESSFUL
FAILURES: No man is absolutely or strictly a failure; he is only a failure
intermittently. Whatever the level of
life on which he happens to be living, he will experience his periodic
successes together (though not simultaneously) with his periodic failures. A failure per se, if such a person
could exist, would be totally without successes. But to be totally without successes would
also mean to be totally without failures, since the former cannot exist without
the latter, the former are a consequence of the latter and therefore dependent
upon the latter for their existence.
We assume a person to be a failure when he
hasn't achieved something he desired, but overlook the fact that he may have
achieved something else, if only to disillusion himself with the desire in
question. Now many people whom we
customarily and perhaps even naively regard as successes on account, for
example, of their current wealth, status, fame, etc., may often regard
themselves in quite a different light - a light, I mean, in which only they can
see, and which exposes, amongst other things, their frustrated ambitions.
For where it may be the ambition of one
man to attain fame, a man who is already famous will have other ambitions, some
of which he may realize, others of which he may not. But, irrespective of their personal circumstances,
both men will experience similar feelings as regards their respective
ambitions, since they will be subject to the same conditions - namely those of
success and failure.
POSITIVELY
SELFISH: No man can be genuinely satisfied with the overall pattern of his life
as long as he leads a relatively negative existence, which is to say as long as
he is insufficiently selfish during the day. For whereas after a day of comparative
selfishness one's selflessness is established to a greater extent in the
evening, it is one's selfishness that is established to a greater extent in the
evening after a day of comparative selflessness. Hence to live in a relatively positive
manner, a manner in which an intelligent person should live, one would have to
adopt the former mode of existence and be comparatively selfish, i.e.
industriously preoccupied in a manner suitable to one's nature and abilities,
during the day, since, by contrast with the day, the evening is always
negative, and a relatively positive approach then will, of necessity, be
somewhat reduced both in its strength and its effect.
As is well known, the evening is generally
a time of repose, of acceptance and resignation, a negative counterbalance to
the positive struggles one is usually obliged to experience during the
day. It is not, ideally, a time for
selfishness. Only those who are
compelled, against their wishes, to lead a relatively negative existence during
the day would endeavour to make it so, though their selfishness will, as
already remarked, lose much of its effect and intensity in the process.
A
POSTHUMOUS B.C.: It seems difficult for someone accustomed to referring to
pre-Christian dates in terms of B.C. to realize that such dates are only
applicable to those who, like ourselves, look back from a Christian or
post-Christian society, not to those who actually lived in
pre-Christian times. The ancient Greeks,
for example, would not have thought in terms of 350 or 300 B.C., for the simple
reason that they had no idea that a man named Jesus Christ would appear in the
world approximately a few centuries later (in their future) and, unbeknown to
himself, subsequently become the source of the Christian calendar. Thus Socrates would not have been aware of
the fact that he lived from 430-399 B.C., since it was the Greek calendar which
prevailed in his time, rendering his concept of epoch considerably different
from ours.
Therefore it should be apparent that
reference to any date preceding the Christian era in terms of B.C. is strictly
a Western invention, a scale of historical reference only relevant to those
living in the A.D. centuries. However,
the fact that we are constantly deceiving ourselves in this matter of affixing
specified Western dates to peoples and individuals who would not have
recognized them should, I feel, be in some way more generally acknowledged,
especially by those who have a genuine interest in the study of earlier
civilizations, so that, as offspring of a later age, they may come to a better
understanding of the amount of fiction they habitually impose upon their
historical 'facts'.
SCHISMATIC
CHRISTIANITY: The decline of Christianity began not, as is generally believed,
in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries but, rather, in the sixteenth
century, which is to say with the formulation of the 'Augsburg Confession' by Melanchton in 1530, which officially signalled the
beginnings of Protestantism and, unknowingly at the time, precipitated the
downfall of Christianity. For with the
rise of Protestantism came an era of inter-Christian wars, of what we may term
the 'cannibalism of Christianity', when, ostensibly in the name of the same
God, Protestant killed Catholic and Catholic killed Protestant, and the
Christian civilization slowly bled itself to death.
Hitherto, in the various guises of
Catholicism, Christianity had fought as a single unit against Mohammedanism and
thus involved itself in religious wars, or wars between different world
religions. But with the rapid rise of
Protestantism in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the chief conflict
was fought not without but within the Church, which became plagued by
increasingly violent schisms from then onwards.
As a single unit Christianity had become
an extremely formidable force - indeed, so formidable
as to be religiously totalitarian. But
when divided into mutually hostile units, Christianity weakened itself in a
manner which no eighteenth- or nineteenth-century rationalist ever did. In a very real sense Protestantism was a form
of early rationalism, a forerunner of the Age of Enlightenment, and a force
without which that age could not have come into existence. For by dividing the Church, Protestantism
questioned the professed sovereignty of the established faith and thereby
considerably detracted from its claim to omnipotence. As the ferocity of the subsequent
inter-Christian wars testified, once the divide had been created it could never
be repaired. And so the 'cannibalism of
Christianity' continued to wreak havoc until such time as, with the progressive
weakening and decline of the Church, there was very little spiritual flesh left
to devour, and wholesale materialism accordingly became the order of the day.
LIVE
SYMBOLS: Words without spirit are dead symbols, devoid of meaning. But it is only the appropriate use of spirit
that gives life to the word and thereby makes it meaningful in the contexts by
which we live. One can imagine the
effect created on a group of listeners by someone who said 'I feel great' in an
apathetic tone-of-voice - a droll effect to say the least! And, similarly, someone who said 'I feel
sick' in an exuberant tone-of-voice would inevitably create a strange effect on
his listeners, one they would have considerable difficulty not equating with a
form of schizophrenic derangement!
Indeed, the extent to which words, as
symbols of conditions and things, are dependent
upon the requisite use of spirit would undoubtedly amaze a person unaccustomed
to hearing the many relevant feeling-values and variations in pitch with which
we customarily invest them in conversation.
And it is highly doubtful that, even in the case of a highly intelligent
recipient, such a person would be able to understand so much as a fraction of
all the things said to him through words which had been deprived of spirit
altogether, or at least to the extent of being delivered in the form of a
tedious monotone.
In this respect, the written word is
usually less good than the spoken one.
For although the writer should have informed his writings with an
appropriate use of spirit and thereby granted them a certain recognizable
colouring and timbre, it remains for the reader to assimilate the written word
into his own spirit, including of course the condition of his spirit at the
time, and if possible instantaneously translate it into the spirit it was
intended to convey - a thing that isn't always very easy to do and, to cite
personal experience, something that isn't always done!
Thus, on account of this complicated
process of spiritual translation, the written word is often misconstrued and
the writer misunderstood. But with the
spoken word, where intellect and spirit are usually in harmony and therefore
can be simultaneously comprehended, there is no need for spiritual
translation. So all it is necessary for
the listener to do is to assimilate it and then react appropriately - a fact,
it seems to me, which testifies to the eternal superiority of the spoken over
the written word!
INTERPLANETARY
EQUILIBRIUM: Throughout the history of civilized man people have often posed
the question 'Why is there life on earth?' and endeavoured to answer it in a
variety of ways, some religious, others scientific. The different viewpoints appertaining to the
reasons for life on this planet, and man's relationship to whichever of the
heavenly bodies he has hitherto been aware of, have ensured that, with each
succeeding generation, the question is posed and answered in a different way
or, at any rate, in a manner considered most suitable to the understanding of
the people of the time.
At present it is the scientific viewpoint
which prevails over the religious one where the interpretation of this
perennial mystery is concerned, and so it is to science, in its manifold
guises, that a majority of people look for a solution to those problems which
have vexed the greatest minds of the past.
True, unlike religion, science does not and cannot lay claim to
omniscience in these matters. But with
its largely empirical if not hypothetical basis, it does at least suffice to
draw one's attention to possibilities which religion, grounded on a 'rock of
faith', would categorically deny, and thus facilitate the way for further and
more detailed inquiry. And so the
question 'Why is there life on earth?', considered scientifically, demands an
answer that will appeal to the contemporary mind in terms it will understand
rather than in any previous or outdated terms.
Admittedly, I am not a scientist.
But, as a philosophical writer, I can at least draw conclusions and
formulate hypotheses roughly compatible with a scientific outlook. Hence the most obvious answer to the
difficult question we have posed is: 'Simply because life on earth was made
possible.'
Of the major planets currently known to
man in the Solar System, it is a general assumption that the earth is the only
one with any form of intelligent life and, in all probability, any life at
all. We no longer believe in Martians or
the possibility of autonomous life on Mars, and with our growing interest in
the more distant planets we are fast coming to the conclusion that life of
whatever kind would be even less likely to exist on them. And so if the earth is the only
life-sustaining planet, it may well puzzle some people what the other planets
are for, why, in fact, they exist at all.
My own theory of this is, I think, a
fairly plausible one - plausible, that is, for those who suffer from a need to
justify the prevailing cosmic order-of-things in this part of the Galaxy. Whether or not the other planets exist
primarily to serve the earth, it seems that their existence, willy-nilly, guarantees the
life-sustaining power of the earth simply by keeping it in a position, relative
to themselves, where life is made possible, but where the absence of one or
more planets from the prevailing order of things would so alter its orbital
distance from the sun as to render life on it utterly impossible or, at the
very least, extremely improbable.
Therefore we must assume that there exists an interplanetary equilibrium
which renders no planet superfluous, but keeps them interdependent in the
interests of a given planetary system.
Life is made possible on the earth because its distance from the sun -
in part established by the gravitational pull of each individual planet - gives
rise to the formation of a life-sustaining atmosphere, an atmosphere which
could not exist on any planet positioned either closer to or farther away from
the sun. Thus life could only be made
impossible on the earth by something which destroyed the prevailing
interplanetary equilibrium, removing one or more of the planets and thereby
necessitating the establishment of a different equilibrium - one which would so
alter the earth's position vis-à-vis the sun as possibly to transform it into
the rough equivalent of Venus or Mars.
Now if, in consequence of the destruction
of Mercury, Venus was 'pulled in' to a much closer position to the sun, it is
highly probable that the earth would also be 'pulled in' to a much closer
position to it, and that Mars, which would also be drawn-in closer to the sun,
might duly find itself in a position where life was made possible there in
consequence of the formation, over a long period of time, of a different
atmosphere from what it now possesses.
Thus Mars would become the rough equivalent of the earth and,
willy-nilly, the earth the rough equivalent of Venus, where the maximum surface
temperature is believed to be somewhere in excess of 800°F, which is to say
about 3¾ times that of boiling point.
However, the difference of mass, volume, density, etc., between the
various planets would undoubtedly affect their relative positions in the Solar
System if such a change were to occur, so we cannot be certain that Mars would
necessarily take up a position exactly corresponding to the one currently held
by the earth. But an approximation there
could well be, and if this approximation of Mars to the earth was such that the
formation of a life-sustaining atmosphere became possible, then there would
almost certainly be life-forms on Mars after a number of millennia.
But in returning from such 'far out'
speculation to the Solar System as it now stands, we cannot be sure to what
extent the prevailing interplanetary equilibrium is governed by the sun and to
what extent it is also governed by the nearest foreign stars in the Galaxy (as
indeed the Galaxy and perhaps even the Universe as a whole). It is, at any rate, unlikely that the Solar
System is a self-contained and totally-isolated unit which exists independently
of the rest of the Galaxy, of which the sun is but a comparatively minor
star. My own theory is that the
equilibrium of the Solar System is predominantly governed by the sun but not
exclusively so. Likewise, if the core of
this planet is molten hot and becomes progressively cooler and harder towards
the surface, my own theory as to the mechanism underlining this equilibrium is
that there are other planets that also possess a molten core which exists, like
the earth's, in an antithetically magnetic relationship to the sun, but which
is prevented from being sucked-in to it by the magnetic influences being
gravitated by certain other stars in the Galaxy which to a certain extent
counteract the sun's magnetic influence and thus produce the tension necessary
to maintaining the orbital variations of the individual planets. Of course, I have to admit that all this is
purely speculative. For as far as a
comprehensive knowledge of the Galaxy and the workings thereof are concerned, we
are still in our infancy, not even having acquired a comprehensive knowledge of
the Solar System!
However, as to the question 'Why is there
life on earth?', I think the fact of its position vis-à-vis the sun must be
taken as the most credible answer, so that our attitude towards the other
planets should encompass an awareness of their function as a means,
effectively, to keeping a life-sustaining atmosphere in existence.
MAGNETIC
RECIPROCITIES: If, to expand on the above hypothesis of interplanetary
equilibrium, we assume that our planet exists in a magnetically antithetical
relationship to the sun, which is literally hundreds of times bigger than the
earth, then it is difficult for us not to assume the core of the former to be
radically different from the core of the latter, so that the innermost parts of
the respective bodies signify a kind of north/south pole antithesis which makes
possible a magnetic reciprocity between them.
At present we know next-to-nothing about the innermost regions of
planets and stars, although it has long been a general hypothesis that the core
of the former is likely to be different from the core of the latter. Planets, it is assumed, have a hard core
while stars have a soft one, and, at face value, this does seem to be the most
sensible theory.
However, my own theory is at present
inclined to the contrary assumption - namely that planets have a comparatively
soft core and stars, by contrast, a hard one, so that the external reality of
both kinds of phenomena may be presumed to exist in an antithetical
relationship to their internal reality.
Thus the earth would seem to be burning up inside, in its innermost
core, while the sun's innermost core is producing the energy and providing the
material upon which the outer parts burn.
The sun would therefore be burning with a positive energy, i.e. one
generated from its innermost core, and the earth, by contrast, with a negative
energy, or one dependent upon the materials lying closest to hand, upon which
it sustains itself. Thus a magnetic
reciprocity would be established between them, by dint of the nature of their
respective types of energy.
Furthermore it would seem that if, by
circling the sun, the earth exists in an antithetical relationship to it, then
the moon, which circles the earth, must of necessity exist in a like
relationship to the earth, and one, moreover, which presupposes a natural
affinity with the sun. Here again my
hypothesis begs to differ from the general assumption relating to the nature of
the moon vis-à-vis the sun. For instead
of being antithetical to the sun, I would argue that the moon is a kind of dead
sun, a weak and negative sun of the night which shines with a borrowed light
(from the earth), and the hard core of which forms a positive antithesis to the
earth's soft one. Now just as I argue
that the earth is largely prevented from being sucked-in to the sun by the
competitive magnetic forces being exerted by various other stars in the Galaxy,
many of which are far greater than the sun and may be presumed to be in
perpetual struggle with one another for mastery over particular planets, so it
is logical for me to contend that the moon is prevented from being sucked-in to
the earth by the competitive magnetic forces being exerted by various other
planets in the Solar System, which likewise struggle with one another for
mastery over particular moons and, by attracting the earth's moon to
themselves, keep it in motion around the earth.
From this hypothesis it should follow
that, just as the largest stars in the Galaxy will have the most number of
circling planets, so the largest planets in the Solar System will have the most
number of circling moons - a contention which can, in fact, be confirmed by an
investigation of the relative number of moons attaching to each of the
planets. Jupiter, the
largest planet, has twelve moons, three more than Saturn, which is the next
largest. Then comes Uranus with
its five moons,
Consequently, there can be little doubt
that planets struggle with one another for moons and possess a number of moons
in accordance with their capacity to support them. Likewise, it should follow that stars
struggle with one another for planets and possess planets in accordance with their
supportive capacity. Hence the largest
stars should possess either the largest or the most number of planets and thus
form the greatest solar systems, the greatest of all presumably being
positioned midway between the innermost and outermost stars of the Galaxy, i.e.
in a galactic position corresponding to the solar-system positions of the
largest planets, rather than actually nearest to the governing star. For it is likely that the actual nucleus of
the Galaxy, about which we know absolutely nothing, possesses a star, or ruling
body, of such magnitude as to govern not merely a solar system peculiar to
itself but, additionally, the courses of the 100,000 million-odd stars which
revolve around it in the fulfilment of their respective 'cosmic years'.
Thus we find ourselves confronted by the possibility
of a three-way system of reciprocal magnetic influence. We have the central star of the Galaxy which,
whatever its actual nature, dictates the paths of individual stars; we have the
stars, which dictate the paths of individual planets; and finally we have the
planets, which dictate the paths of individual moons. A sun, we have assumed, forms the main
positive influence in a given solar system, the planets, drawn into circulation
around that sun, being comparatively negative.
However, the planets 'take revenge', so to speak, upon their sun by
dictating the paths that moons are to take around them
in a given solar system. For we must
assume that, although the planets are largely negative in relation to their
moons, their negativity is nevertheless far more powerful than the weak positivity of the moons' hard core. Now just as a large magnet with a south pole
will draw a smaller north-pole magnet towards itself, so the planets are able
to govern the orbits of individual moons.
As an afterthought, I should like to point
out the similarity of these cosmic speculations with those of
Now this is not to say that force and mass
was incorrect or a misconception of what literally took place in the
Universe. But it was bound to be
challenged sooner or later by a standpoint that scorned the brute facts of the
matter in favour of a convenient fiction which would enable man, from that time
onwards, to perceive the workings of the Universe through a mystical veil, as
it were, in deference to transcendental criteria and a refusal, in consequence,
to recognize brute reality.
Such an anti-imperialist and
anti-autocratic concept as curved space surely has much to recommend it to the
future! But intellectual honesty compels
me to say that
UNIVERSE OR
UNIVERSES: If the moon revolves around the earth and the earth revolves around
the sun and that in turn revolves around the centre of the Galaxy, then it
seems feasible to contend that the centre of the Galaxy revolves around the
centre of the Universe and that maybe even the centre of the Universe revolves
around something greater than itself, and so on, in a process without end. The concept of multiple universes could then
present itself to our comprehension as a continuous manifestation of greater
and greater degrees of revolution around a central something which is always one
step ahead, so to speak, of that which revolves around it.
However, the logic of this does entail a
serious flaw. Why, you may wonder, doesn't something smaller than
the moon revolve around the moon, and something smaller than the something
which should therefore revolve around the moon revolve around it, and so
on? Clearly, if there is a downwards
limit as to what revolves around what, the moon having nothing revolving around
it in the manner of planetary revolution around the sun, then it seems highly
probable that there must also be an upwards limit which is established if not
at that point where suns revolve around the centre of their particular galaxy,
then almost certainly at that point where the centres of galaxies revolve around
the centre of the Universe. If the
Universe is still understood to imply the totality of existing galaxies, then
the concept of multiple universes is still beyond our comprehension and
possibly no more than a figment of the imagination.
But if multiple universes do exist,
then the Western concept of a unitary universe is smashed to pieces, the
totality of galaxies becoming merely a phenomenon appertaining to a tiny area
of total space in which other universes - or immense galactic clusters - exist
as logical entities at virtually incalculable distances from one another, and
revolve in toto around a body
or bodies greater than themselves.
Probably the concept of multiple universes
derives, in any case, from a more evolved point-of-view which can accommodate
the notion of alternative atomicities and thereby
avoid being limited to just one monadic absolute such as would correspond, in
theological terms, to the Father at the expense not only of the Son but of the
Holy Spirit as well, and which would accordingly limit us to a force/mass
autocracy in traditional subservience to a unitary cosmos.
BETWEEN
GOOD AND EVIL: The inorganic may be beneath good and evil but nothing organic
is. It is especially in man that the
concepts of good and evil attain to their greatest clarity, that what is felt
to be either the one or the other is given verbal definition and understood in
the context to which it pertains.
Everything organic beneath man, from the higher animals to the lower
forms of plant life, is also subject to varying degrees and kinds of good and
evil, though their respective experiences are merely felt rather than defined
as being specifically good or evil. It
is only with the inorganic, with the blind forces of wind, rain, hail, snow,
heat, etc., that good and evil have no meaning, and therefore cease to apply.
Hence a violent thunderstorm is no more
evil in itself than a fine midsummer's day is inherently good. A violent thunderstorm may be interpreted as
evil by a dog that hides under the bed or by a man who runs for shelter
somewhere other than under the branches of a tree, but it is only such in
relation to the organic, especially to the higher forms of organic life. And the same, of course, applies to a fine
midsummer's day with a brilliantly clear sky and the sun shining down onto the
bodies of holiday-makers enjoying themselves on a sandy beach. They may interpret the favourable conditions
as being good, but the fact remains that such conditions are only 'good' in
relation to themselves as sentient beings.
For beneath the realm of the sentient, good and evil have no
applicability.
The good may be defined as that which
accompanies or engenders positive feelings, thereby making one conscious of
being happy or hopeful. The evil, by contrast, as that which accompanies or engenders
negative feelings, thereby making one conscious of being sad or fearful. A fine midsummer's day may well engender
positive feelings in one's mind in consequence of its favourable conditions and
thereupon be interpreted as a good, a veritable blessing. Thus anything that makes one feel either
pleased with oneself or pleased with life in general comes within the realm of
'the good' by dint of the positivity it
engenders. However, in the case of a
thunder storm it will be found that the noise of thunder, flashes of lightning,
torrents of rain, bleak clouds, etc., engender negative feelings in one's mind
and are thereupon instinctively interpreted as evil. Anything that makes one's hair stand on end
comes within the realm of 'the evil' by dint of the negativity it engenders,
the worst experiences being those which engender the most negativity.
If one had a scale for both positive and
negative feelings ranging, for example, from 1-10 in each direction, one could
ascertain the extent of 'the good' or of 'the evil' being experienced by simply
taking note of one's feelings at the time.
We do not, of course, have an exact means of doing this, but if we
remember that good and evil are inextricably bound-up with our feelings, then
we can always acquire an approximate indication as to where we stand in
relation to them at any given time. The
greatest good will be manifested in feelings of bliss,
the greatest evil in feelings of sheer agony or dejection. The degree of pleasure one experiences in any
given context stands in direct proportion to the extent of 'the good', the
degree of pain, by contrast, in direct proportion to the extent of 'the evil'.
It is foolish to pretend that one should
live solely in 'the good', or that evil is something which should be eradicated
from the world in the interests of life.
On the contrary, so long as there is life, good and evil must co-exist
in its interests. One cannot experience
pleasure if one knows nothing of pain, one cannot live
in 'the good' unless one is regularly accustomed to also living in 'the
evil'. Strange as it may seem, every
time one experiences evil, i.e. negative feelings, whether engendered by a
nightmare, thunderstorm, quarrel, fall, rebuff, cold, stomach ache, toothache,
contempt, hatred, anger, worry, derision, etc., one is unconsciously earning
one's subsequent good, i.e. positive feelings, whether engendered by a kiss,
beautiful dream, glass of wine, pleasant walk, favourite music, pride,
complacency, love, respect, admiration, etc.
The interdependence of good and evil is
indisputable and cannot be torn apart.
One can, of course, deceive oneself as much as one likes. One can call one's evil experiences good and
reject the theory that good and evil are inextricably bound-up with the nature
of one's feelings. But even then one
will be as subject to their influences as anyone else and be unable to do
anything to alter them. The nightmares
will continue regardless, and so, too, will the physical maladies which
regularly beset one. If life was
entirely evil, we could condemn it. But
the fact that it is also given to good, which is ultimately dependent upon 'the
evil' for its authenticity, its place in life, obliges us to accept life's
overall logic for what it is, and thus resign ourselves to living it. We may condemn life under pressure of
unfavourable circumstances, but we are just as likely to extol it when
circumstances become favourable. That is the
human condition, and that is what we have to face!