Bertrand Russell's
MYSTICISM
AND LOGIC
______________
CHAPTER I
Mysticism and Logic
METAPHYSICS, or the attempt to conceive the world as a
whole by means of thought, has been developed, from the first, by the union and
conflict of two very different human impulses, the one urging men towards
mysticism, the other urging them towards science. Some men have achieved greatness through one
of these impulses alone, others through the other alone: in Hume, for example,
the scientific impulse reigns quite unchecked, while in Blake a strong
hostility to science coexists with profound mystic insight. But the greatest men who have been
philosophers have felt the need both of science and of mysticism: the attempt
to harmonize the two was what made their life, and what always must, for all
its arduous uncertainty, make philosophy, to some minds, a greater thing than
either science or religion.
Before
attempting an explicit characterization of the scientific and the mystical
impulses, I will illustrate them by examples from two philosophers whose
greatness lies in the very intimate blending which they achieved. The two philosophers I mean are Heraclitus and Plato.
Heraclitus, as everyone knows, was a believer in universal
flux: time builds and destroys all things.
From the few fragments that remain, it is not easy to discover how he
arrived at his opinions, but there are some sayings that strongly suggest
scientific observation as the source.
'The things
that can be seen, heard, and learned,' he says, 'are what I prize the
most.' This is the language of the empiricist,
to whom observation is the sole guarantee of truth. 'The sun is new every day,' is another
fragment; and this opinion, in spite of its paradoxical character, is obviously
inspired by scientific reflection, and no doubt seemed to him to obviate the
difficulty of understanding how the sun can work its way underground from west
to east during the night. Actual
observation must also have suggested to him his central doctrine, that Fire is
the one permanent substance, of which all visible things are passing
phases. In combustion we see things
change utterly, while their flame and heat rise up into the air and vanish.
'This
world, which is the same for all,' he says, 'no one of the gods or men has
made; but it was ever, is now, and ever shall be, an ever-living Fire, with
measures kindling, and measures going out.'
'The
transformations of Fire are, first of all, sea; and half of the sea is earth,
half whirlwind.'
This
theory, though no longer one which science can accept, is nevertheless
scientific in spirit. Science, too,
might have inspired the famous saying to which Plato alludes: 'You cannot step
twice into the same rivers; for fresh waters are ever flowing in upon
you.' But we find also another statement
among the extant fragments: 'We step and do not step into the same rivers; we
are and are not'.
The
comparison of this statement, which is mystical, with the one quoted by Plato,
which is scientific, shows how intimately the two tendencies are blended in the
system of Heraclitus.
Mysticism is, in essence, little more than a certain intensity and depth
of feeling in regard to what is believed about the universe; and this kind of
feeling leads Heraclitus, on the basis of his
science, to strangely poignant sayings concerning life and the world, such as:
'Time is a
child playing draughts, the kingly power is a
child's.'
It is
poetic imagination, not science, which presents Time as despotic lord of the
world, with all the irresponsible frivolity of a child. It is mysticism, too, which leads Heraclitus to assert the identity of opposites: 'Good and
ill are one,' he says; and again: 'To God all things are fair and good and
right, but men hold some things wrong and some right.'
Much of
mysticism underlies the ethics of Heraclitus. It is true that a scientific determinism
alone might have inspired the statement: 'Man's character is his fate;' but
only a mystic would have said:
'Every
beast is driven to the pasture with blows;' and again:
'It is hard
to fight with one's heart's desire.
Whatever it wishes to get, it purchases at the cost of soul;' and again:
'Wisdom is one thing. It is to know the thought by which all things are steered through all things.' [All the above quotations are from Burnet's Early Greek Philosophy (2nd ed., 1908), pp. 146-156.]
Examples
might be multiplied, but those that have been given are enough to show the
character of the man: the facts of science, as they appeared to him, fed the
flame in his soul, and in its light he saw into the depths of the world by the
reflection of his own dancing swiftly penetrating fire. In such a nature we see the true union of the
mystic and the man of science - the highest eminence, as I think, that it is
possible to achieve in the world of thought.
In Plato,
the same twofold impulse exists, though the mystic impulse is distinctly the
stronger of the two, and secures ultimate victory whenever the conflict is
sharp. His description of the cave is
the classical statement of belief in a knowledge and reality truer and more
real than that of the senses:
'Imagine [Republic, 514, translated by Davies and Vaughan] a number of men living in an underground cavernous chamber, with an entrance open to the light, extending along the entire length of the cavern, in which they have been confined, from their childhood, with their legs and necks so shackled that they are obliged to sit still and look straight forwards, because their chains render it impossible for them to turn their heads round: and imagine a bright fire burning some way off, above and behind them, and an elevated roadway passing between the fire and the prisoners, with a low wall built along it, like the screens which conjurors put up in front of their audience, and above which they exhibit their wonders.
I have, he replied.
Also figure to yourself a number of persons walking behind this wall, and carrying with them statues of men, and images of other animals, wrought in wood and stone and all kinds of materials, together with various other articles, which overtop the wall; and, as you might expect, let some of the passers-by be talking, and others silent.
You are describing a strange scene, and strange prisoners.
They resemble us, I replied.
Now consider what would happen if the course of nature brought them a release from their fetters, and a remedy for their foolishness, in the following manner. Let us suppose that one of them has been released, and compelled suddenly to stand up, and turn his neck round and walk with open eyes towards the light; and let us suppose that he goes through all these actions with pain, and that the dazzling splendour renders him incapable of discerning those objects of which he used formerly to see the shadows. What answer should you expect him to make, if someone were to tell him that in those days he was watching foolish phantoms, but that now he is somewhat nearer to reality, and is turned towards things more real, and sees more correctly; above all, if he were to point out to him the several objects that are passing by, and question him, and compel him to answer what they are? Should you not expect him to be puzzled, and to regard his old visions as truer than the objects now forced upon his notice?
Yes, much truer....
Hence, I suppose, habit will be necessary to enable him to perceive objects in that upper world. At first he will be most successful in distinguishing shadows; then he will discern the reflections of men and other things in water, and afterwards the realities; and after this he will raise his eyes to encounter the light of the moon and stars, finding it less difficult to study the heavenly bodies and the heaven itself by night, than the sun and the sun's light by day.
Doubtless.
Last of all, I imagine, he will be able to observe and contemplate the nature of the sun, not as it appears in water or on alien ground, but as it is in itself in its own territory.
Of course.
His next step will be to draw the conclusion, that the sun is the author of the seasons and the years, and the guardian of all things in the visible world, and in a manner the cause of all those things which he and his companions used to see.
Obviously, this will be his next step....
Now this imaginary case, my dear Glaucon, you must apply in all its parts to our former statements, by comparing the region which the eye reveals, to the prison house, and the light of the fire therein to the power of the sun: and if, by the upward ascent and the contemplation of the upper world, you understand the mounting of the soul into the intellectual region, you will hit the tendency of my own surmises, since you desire to be told what they are; though, indeed, God only knows whether they are correct. But, be that as it may, the view which I take of the subject is to the following effect. In the world of knowledge, the essential Form of Good is the limit of our enquiries, and can barely be perceived; but, when perceived, we cannot help concluding that it is in every case the source of all that is bright and beautiful, - in the visible world giving birth to light and its master, and in the intellectual world dispensing, immediately and with full authority, truth and reason; - and that whosoever would act wisely, either in private or in public, must set this Form of Good before his eyes.'
But in this
passage, as throughout most of Plato's teaching, there is an identification of
the good with the truly real, which became embodied in the philosophical
tradition, and is still largely operative in our own day. In thus allowing a legislative function tot
he good, Plato produced a divorce between philosophy and science, from which,
in my opinion, both have suffered ever since and are still suffering. The man of science, whatever his hopes may
be, must lay them aside while he studies nature; and the philosopher, if he is
to achieve truth must do the same.
Ethical considerations can only legitimately appear when the truth has
been ascertained: they can and should appear as determining our feeling towards
the truth, and our manner of ordering our lives in view of the truth, but not
as themselves dictating what the truth is to be.
There are
passages in Plato - among those which illustrate the scientific side of his
mind - where he seems clearly aware of this.
The most noteworthy is the one in which Socrates, as a young man, is
explaining the theory of ideas to Parmenides.
After
Socrates has explained that there is an idea of the good, but not of such
things as hair and mud and dirt, Parmenides advises him 'not to despise even
the meanest things', and this advice shows the genuine scientific temper. It is with this impartial temper that the
mystic's apparent insight into a higher reality and a hidden good has to be
combined if philosophy is to realise its greatest possibilities. And it is failure in this respect that has
made so much of idealistic philosophy thin, lifeless, and insubstantial. It is only in marriage with the world that
our ideals can bear fruit: divorced from it, they remain barren. But marriage with the world is not to be
achieved by an ideal which shrinks from fact, or demands in advance that the
world shall conform to its desires.
Parmenides
himself is the source of a peculiarly interesting strain of mysticism which
pervades Plato's thought - the mysticism which may be called 'logical' because
it is embodied in theories on logic.
This form of mysticism, which appears, so far as the West is concerned,
to have originated with Parmenides, dominates the reasonings
of all the great mystical metaphysicians from his day to that of Hegel and his
modern disciples. Reality, he says, is
uncreated, indestructible, unchanging, indivisible; it is 'immovable in the
bonds of mighty chains, without beginning and without end; since coming into
being and passing away have been driven afar, and true belief has cast them
away'. The fundamental principle of his
inquiry is stated in a sentence which would not be out of place in Hegel: 'Thou
canst not know what is not - that is impossible - nor utter
it; for it is the same thing that can be thought and that can be.' And again: 'It needs must be that what can be
thought and spoken of is; for it is possible for it to be, and it is not
possible for what is nothing to be.' The
impossibility of change follows from this principle; for what is past can be
spoken of, and therefore, by the principle, still is.
Mystical
philosophy, in all ages and in all parts of the world, is characterized by
certain beliefs which are illustrated by the doctrines we have been
considering.
There is,
first, the belief in insight as against discursive analytic knowledge: the
belief in a way of wisdom, sudden, penetrating, coercive, which is contrasted
with the slow and fallible study of outward appearance by science relying
wholly upon the senses. All who are
capable of absorption in an inward passion must have experienced at times the
strange feeling of unreality in common objects, the loss of contact with daily
things, in which the solidity of the outer world is lost, and the soul seems,
in utter loneliness, to bring forth, out of its own depths, the mad dance of
fantastic phantoms which have hitherto appeared independently real and
living. This is the negative side of the
mystic's initiation: the doubt concerning common knowledge, preparing the way
for the reception of what seems a higher wisdom. Many men to whom this negative experience is
familiar do not pass beyond it, but for the mystic it is merely the gateway to
an ampler world.
The mystic
insight begins with the sense of a mystery unveiled, of a hidden wisdom now suddenly
become certain beyond the possibility of a doubt. The sense of certainty and revelation comes
earlier than any definite belief. The
definite beliefs at which mystics arrive are the result of reflection upon the
inarticulate experience gained in the moment of insight. Often, beliefs which have no real connection
with this moment become subsequently attracted into the central nucleus; thus
in addition to the convictions which all mystics share, we find, in many of
them, other convictions of a more local and temporary character, which no doubt
become amalgamated with what was essentially mystical in virtue of their
subjective certainty. We may ignore such
inessential accretions, and confine ourselves to the beliefs which all mystics
share.
The first
and most direct outcome of the moment of illumination is belief in the
possibility of a way of knowledge which may be called revelation or insight or
intuition, as contrasted with sense, reason, and analysis, which are regarded
as blind guides leading to the morass of illusion. Closely connected with this belief is the
conception of a Reality behind the world of appearance and utterly different
from it. This Reality is regarded with
an admiration often amounting to worship; it is felt to be always and everywhere
close at hand, thinly veiled by the shows of sense, ready, for the receptive
mind, to shine in its glory even through the apparent folly and wickedness of
Man. The poet, the artist, and the lover
are seekers after that glory: the haunting beauty that they pursue is the faint
reflection of its sun. But the mystic
lives in the full light of the vision: what others dimly seek he knows, with a
knowledge beside which all other knowledge is ignorance.
The second
characteristic of mysticism is its belief in unity, and its refusal to admit
opposition or division anywhere. We
found Heraclitus saying 'good and ill are one'; and
again he says, 'the way up and the way down is one and the same'. The same attitude appears in the simultaneous
assertion of contradictory propositions, such as: 'We step and do not step into
the same rivers; we are and are not.'
The assertion of Parmenides, that reality is one and indivisible, comes
from the same impulse towards unity. In
Plato, this impulse is less prominent, being held in check by his theory of
ideas; but it reappears, so far as his logic permits, in the doctrine of the
primacy of the Good.
A third
mark of almost all mystical metaphysics is the denial of the reality of
Time. This is an outcome of the denial of
division; if all is one, the distinction of past and future must be
illusory. We have seen this doctrine
prominent in Parmenides; and among moderns it is fundamental in the systems of
Spinoza and Hegel.
The last of
the doctrines of mysticism which we have to consider is its belief that all
evil is mere appearance, an illusion produced by the divisions and oppositions
of the analytic intellect. Mysticism
does not maintain that such things as cruelty, for example, are good, but it
denies that they are real: they belong to that lower world of phantoms from
which we are to be liberated by the insight of the vision. Sometimes - for example in Hegel, and at
least verbally in Spinoza - not only evil, but good also, is regarded as
illusory, though nevertheless the emotional attitude towards what is held to be
Reality is such as would naturally be associated with the belief that Reality
is good. What is, in all cases,
ethically characteristic of mysticism is absence of indignation or protest,
acceptance with joy, disbelief in the ultimate truth of the division into two
hostile camps, the good and the bad.
This attitude is a direct outcome of the nature of the mystical
experience: with its sense of unity is associated a feeling of infinite
peace. Indeed it may be suspected that
the feeling of peace produce, as feelings do in dreams, the whole system of
associated beliefs which make up the body of mystic doctrine. But this is a difficult question, and one on
which it cannot be hoped that mankind will reach agreement.
Four
questions thus arise in considering the truth or falsehood of mysticism,
namely:
I. Are
there two ways of knowing which may be called respectively reason and
intuition? And if so, is either to be
preferred to the other?
II. Is all plurality
and division illusory?
III.
Is time unreal?
IV.
What kind of reality belongs to good and evil?
On all four
of these questions, while fully developed mysticism seems to me mistaken, I yet
believe that, by sufficient restraint, there is an element of wisdom to be
learned from the mystical way of feeling, which does not seem to be attainable
in any other manner. If this is the
truth, mysticism is to be commended as an attitude towards life, not as a creed
about the world. The metaphysical creed,
I shall maintain, is a mistaken outcome of the emotion, although this emotion,
as colouring and informing all other thoughts and feelings, is the inspirer of
whatever is best in Man. Even the
cautious and patient investigation of truth by science, which seems the very
antithesis of the mystic's swift certainty, may be fostered and nourished by
that very spirit of reverence in which mysticism lives and moves.
I. REASON AND INTUITION
[This section, and also one or two pages
in later sections, have been printed in a course of
Of the
reality or unreality of the mystic's world I know nothing. I have no wish to deny it, nor
even to declare that the insight which reveals it is not a genuine
insight. What I do wish to maintain -
and it is here that the scientific attitude becomes imperative - is that
insight, untested and unsupported, is an insufficient guarantee of truth, in
spite of the fact that much of the most important truth is first suggested by
its means. It is common to speak of an
opposition between instinct and reason; in the eighteenth century, the
opposition was drawn in favour of reason, but under the influence of Rousseau
and the romantic movement instinct was given the preference, first by those who
rebelled against artificial forms of government and thought, and then, as the
purely rationalistic defence of traditional theology became increasingly
difficult, by all who felt in science a menace to creeds which they associated
with a spiritual outlook on life and the world.
Bergson, under the name of 'intuition', has
raised instinct to the position of sole arbiter of metaphysical truth. But in fact the opposition of instinct and
reason is mainly illusory. Instinct,
intuition or insight is what first leads to the beliefs which subsequently
reason confirms or confutes; but the confirmation, where it is possible,
consists, in the last analysis, of agreement with other beliefs no less
instinctive. Reason is a harmonizing,
controlling force rather than a creative one.
Even in the most purely logical realm, it is insight that first arrives
at what is new.
Where
instinct and reason do sometimes conflict is in regard to single beliefs, held
instinctively, and held with such determination that no degree of inconsistency
with other beliefs leads to their abandonment.
Instinct, like all human faculties, is liable to error. Those in whom reason is weak are often
unwilling to admit this as regards themselves, though all admit it in regard to
others. Where instinct is least liable
to error is in practical matters as to which right judgement is a help to survival:
friendship and hostility in others, for instance, are often felt with
extraordinary discrimination through very careful disguises. But even in such matters a wrong impression
may be given by reserve or flattery; and in matters less directly practical,
such as philosophy deals with, very strong instinctive beliefs are sometimes
wholly mistaken, as we may come to know through their perceived inconsistency
with other equally strong beliefs. It is
such considerations that necessitate the harmonizing mediation of reason, which
tests our beliefs by their mutual compatibility, and examines, in doubtful
cases, the possible sources of error on the one side and on the other. In this there is no opposition to instinct as
a whole, but only to blind reliance upon some one interesting aspect of
instinct to the exclusion of other more commonplace but not less trustworthy
aspects. It is such one-sidedness, not
instinct itself, that reason aims at correcting.
There more
or less trite maxims may be illustrated by application to Bergson's
advocacy of 'intuition' as against 'intellect'.
There are, he says, 'two profoundly different ways of knowing a
thing. The first implies that we move
around the object: the second that we enter into it. The first depends on the point of view at
which we are placed and on the symbols by which we express ourselves. The second neither depends on a point of view
nor relies on any symbol. The first kind
of knowledge may be said to stop at the relative; the second, in those
cases where it is possible, to attain the absolute.' [Introduction
to Metaphysics, p.1] The second of these,
which is intuition, is, he says, 'the kind of intellectual sympathy by
which one places oneself within an object in order to coincide with what is unique
in it and therefore inexpressible' (p.6).
In illustration, he mentions self-knowledge: 'there is one reality, at
least, which we all seize from within, by intuition and not by simple analysis. It is our own personality in its flowing
through time - our self which endures' (p. 8).
The rest of Bergson's philosophy consists in
reporting, through the imperfect medium of words, the knowledge gained by
intuition, and the consequence complete condemnation of all the pretended
knowledge derive from science and common sense.
This
procedure, since it takes sides in a conflict of instinctive beliefs, stands in
need of justification by proving the greater trustworthiness of the beliefs on
one side than of those on the other. Bergson attempts this justification in two ways, first by
explaining that intellect is a purely practical faculty to secure biological
success, secondly by mentioning remarkable feats of instinct in animals and by
pointing out characteristics of the world which, though intuition can apprehend
them, are baffling to intellect as he interprets it.
Of Bergson's theory that intellect is a purely practical
faculty, developed in the struggle for survival, and not a source of true
beliefs, we may say, first, that it is only through intellect that we know of
the struggle for survival and of the biological ancestry of man: if the
intellect is misleading, the whole of this merely inferred history is
presumably untrue. If, on the other
hand, we agree with him in thinking that evolution took place as Darwin
believed, then it is not only intellect, but all our faculties, that have been
developed under the stress of practical utility. Intuition is seen at its best where it is
directly useful, for example in regard to other people's characters and dispositions. Bergson apparently
holds that capacity for this kind of knowledge is less explicable by the
struggle for existence than, for example, capacity for pure mathematics. Yet the savage deceived by false friendship
is likely to pay for his mistake with his life; whereas even in the most
civilized societies men are not put to death for mathematical
incompetence. All the most striking of
his instances of intuition in animals have a very direct survival value. The fact is, of course, that both intuition and
intellect have been developed because they are useful, and that, speaking
broadly, they are useful when they give truth and become harmful when they give
falsehood. Intellect, in civilized man,
like artistic capacity, has occasionally been developed beyond the point where
it is useful to the individual; intuition, on the other hand, seems on the
whole to diminish as civilization increases.
It is greater, as a rule, in children than in adults, in the uneducated
than in the educated. Probably in dogs it
exceeds anything to be found in human beings.
But those who see in these facts a recommendation of intuition ought to
return to running wild in the woods, dyeing themselves with woad
and living on hips and haws.
Let us next
examine whether intuition possesses any such infallibility as Bergson claims for it.
The best instance of it, according to him, is our acquaintance with ourselves; yet self-knowledge is proverbially rare and
difficult. Most men, for example, have
in their natures meannesses,
vanities and envies of which they are quite unconscious, though even their best
friends can perceive them without any difficulty. It is true that intuition has a
convincingness which is lacking to intellect: while it is present, it is almost
impossible to doubt its truth. But if it
should appear, on examination, to be at least as fallible as intellect, its
greater subjective certainty becomes a demerit, making it only the more
irresistibly deceptive. Apart from
self-knowledge, one of the most notable examples of intuition is the knowledge
people believe themselves to possess of those with whom they are in love: the
wall between different personalities seems to become transparent, and people
think they see into another soul as into their own. Yet deception in such cases is constantly
practised with success; and even where there is no intentional deception,
experience gradually proves, as a rule, that the supposed insight was illusory,
and that the slower, more groping methods of the intellect are in the long run
more reliable.
Bergson maintains that intellect can only deal with things
insofar as they resemble what has been experienced in the past, while intuition
has the power of apprehending the uniqueness and novelty that always belong to
each fresh moment. That there is
something unique and new at every moment, is certainly
true; it is also truth that this cannot be fully expressed by means of
intellectual concepts. Only direct
acquaintance can give knowledge of what is unique and new. But direct acquaintance of this kind is given
fully in sensation, and does not require, so far as I can see, any special
faculty of intuition for its apprehension.
It is neither intellect nor intuition, but sensation, that supplies new data;
but when the data are new in any remarkable manner, intellect is much more
capable of dealing with them than intuition would be. The hen with a brood of ducklings no doubt
has intuition which seems to place her inside them,
and not merely to know them analytically; but when the ducklings take to the
water, the whole apparent intuition is seen to be illusory, and the hen is left
helpless on the shore. Intuition, in
fact, is an aspect and development of instinct, and, like all instinct, is
admirable in those customary surroundings which have moulded the habits of the
animal in question, but totally incompetent as soon as the surroundings are
changed in a way which demands some non-habitual mode of action.
The
theoretical understanding of the world, which is the aim of philosophy, is not
a matter of great practical importance to animals, or to savages, or even to
most civilized men. It is hardly to be
supposed, therefore, that the rapid, rough and ready methods of instinct or
intuition will find in this field a favourable ground for their application. It is the other kinds of activity, which
bring out our kinship with remote generations of animal and semi-human ancestors, that show intuition at its best. In such matters as self-preservation and
love, intuition will act sometimes (though not always) with a swiftness and
precision which are astonishing to the critical intellect. But philosophy is not one of the pursuits
which illustrate our affinity with the past: it is a highly refined, highly
civilized pursuit, demanding, for its success, a certain
liberation from the life of instinct, and even, at times, a certain aloofness
from all mundane hopes and fears. It is
not in philosophy, therefore, that we can hope to see intuition at its best. On the contrary, since the true objects of
philosophy, and the habit of thought demanded for their apprehension, are
strange, unusual, and remote, it is here, more almost than anywhere else, that
intellect proves superior to intuition, and that quick unanalysed convictions
are least deserving of uncritical acceptance.
In
advocating the scientific restraint and balance, as against the self-assertion
of a confident reliance upon intuition, we are only urging, in the sphere of
knowledge, that largeness of contemplation, that impersonal disinterestedness,
and that freedom from practical preoccupations which have been inculcated by
all the great religions of the world.
Thus our conclusion, however it may conflict with the explicit beliefs
of many mystics, is, in essence, not contrary to the spirit which inspires
those beliefs, but rather the outcome of this very spirit as applied in the
realm of thought.
II. UNITY AND PLURALITY
One of the
most convincing aspects of the mystic illumination is the apparent revelation
of the oneness of all things, giving rise to pantheism in religion and to
monism in philosophy. An elaborate
logic, beginning with Parmenides, and culminating in Hegel and his followers,
has been gradually developed, to prove that the universe is one indivisible
Whole, and that what seems to be its parts, if considered as substantial and
self-existing, are mere illusion. The
concept of a Reality quite other than the world of appearance, a reality one,
indivisible, and unchanging, was introduced into Western philosophy by
Parmenides, not, nominally at least, for mystical or religious reasons, but on
the basis of a logical argument as to the impossibility of not-being, and most
subsequent metaphysical systems are the outcome of this fundamental idea.
The logic
used in defence of mysticism seems to be faulty as logic, and open to technical
criticisms, which I have explained elsewhere.
I shall not here repeat these criticisms, since they are lengthy and
difficult, but shall instead attempt an analysis of the state of mind from
which mystical logic has arisen.
Belief in a
reality quite different from what appears to the senses arises with
irresistible force in certain moods, which are the source of most mysticism,
and of most metaphysics. While such a
mood is dominant, the need of logic is not felt, and accordingly the more
thorough-going mystics do not employ logic, but appeal directly to the
immediate deliverance of their insight.
But such fully developed mysticism is rare in the West. When the intensity of emotional conviction
subsides, a man who is in the habit of reasoning will search for logical
grounds in favour of the belief which he finds in himself. But since the belief already exists, he will
be very hospitable to any ground that suggests itself. The paradoxes apparently proved by his logic
are really the paradoxes of mysticism, and are the goal which he feels his
logic must reach if it is to be in accordance with insight. The resulting logic has rendered most
philosophers incapable of giving any account of the world of science and daily
life. If they had been anxious to give
such an account, they would probably have discovered the errors of their logic;
but most of them were less anxious to understand the world of science and daily
life than to convict it of unreality in the interests of a super-sensible
'real' world.
It is in
this way that logic has been pursued by those of the great philosophers who
were mystics. But since they usually
took for granted the supposed insight of the mystic emotion, their logical
doctrines were presented with a certain dryness, and
were believed by their disciples to be quite independent of the sudden
illumination from which they sprang.
Nevertheless their origin clung to them, and they remained - to borrow a
useful word from Mr Santayana - 'malicious' in regard to the world of science
and common sense. It is only so that we
can account for the complacency with which philosophers have accepted the
inconsistency of their doctrines with all the common and scientific facts which
seem best established and most worthy of belief.
The logic of mysticism shows, as is natural, the defects which are
inherent in anything malicious.
The impulse to logic, not felt while the mystic mood is dominant, reasserts
itself as the mood fades, but with a desire to retain the vanishing insight, or
at least to prove that it was insight, and that what seems to contradict
it is illusion. The logic which thus
arises is not quite disinterested or candid, and is inspired by a certain
hatred of the daily world to which it is to be applied. Such an attitude naturally does not tend to
the best results. Everyone knows that to
read an author simply in order to refute him is not the way to understand him;
and to read the book of Nature with a conviction that it is all illusion is
just as unlikely to lead to understanding.
If our logic is to find the common world intelligible, it must not be
hostile, but must be inspired by a genuine acceptance such as is not usually to
be found among metaphysicians.
III. TIME
The
unreality of time is a cardinal doctrine of many metaphysical systems, often
nominally based, as already by Parmenides, upon logical arguments, but
originally derived, at any rate in the founders of new systems, from the
certainty which is born in the moment of mystic insight. As a Persian Sufi poet says:
'Past and future are what veil God from our sight.
Burn up both of them with fire! How long
Wilt thou be partitioned by these segments as a reed?'
[Whinfield's translation of the Masnavi (Trubner,
1887), p. 34]
The belief
that what is ultimately real must be immutable is a very common one: it gives
rise to the metaphysical notion of substance, and finds, even now, a wholly
illegitimate satisfaction in such scientific doctrines as the conservation of
energy and mass.
It is
difficult to disentangle the truth and the error in this view. The argument for the contention that time is
unreal and that the world of sense is illusory must, I think, be regarded as
fallacious. Nevertheless there is some
sense - easier to feel than to state - in which time in an unimportant and
superficial characteristic of reality.
Past and future must be acknowledged to be as real as the present, and a certain emancipation from slavery to time is essential to
philosophic thought. The importance of
time is rather practical than theoretical, rather in relation to our desires
than in relation to truth. A truer image
of the world, I think, is obtained by picturing things as entering into the
stream of time from an eternal world outside, than from a view which regards
time as the devouring tyrant of all that is.
Both in thought and in feeling, even though time be
real, to realize the unimportance of time is the gate of wisdom.
That this
is the case may be seen at once by asking ourselves why our feelings towards
the past are so different from our feelings towards the future. The reason for this difference is wholly
practical: our wishes can effect the future but not
the past, the future is to some extent subject to our power, while the past is
unalterably fixed. But every future will
some day be past: if we see the past truly now, it must, when it was still
future, have been just what we now see it to be, and what is now future must be
just what we shall see it to be when it has become past. The felt difference of quality between past
and future, therefore, is not an intrinsic difference, but only a difference in
relation to us: to impartial contemplation, it ceases to exist. And impartiality of contemplation is, in the
intellectual sphere, that very same virtue of disinterestedness which, in the
sphere of action, appears as justice and unselfishness. Whoever wishes to see the world truly, to
rise in thought above the tyranny of practical desires, must learn to overcome
the difference of attitude towards past and future, and to survey the whole
stream of time in one comprehensive vision.
The kind of
way in which, as it seems to me, time ought not to enter into our theoretic
philosophical thought, may be illustrated by the philosophy which has become
associated with the idea of evolution, and which is exemplified by Nietzsche,
pragmatism, and Bergson. This philosophy, on the basis of the
development which has led from the lowest forms of life up to man, sees in progress
the fundamental law of the universe, and thus admits the difference between earlier
and later into the very citadel of its contemplative outlook. With its past and future history of the
world, conjectural as it is, I do not wish to quarrel. But I think that, in the intoxication of a
quick success, much that is required for a true understanding of the universe
has been forgotten. Something of
Hellenism, something, too, of Oriental resignation, must be combined with his
hurrying Western self-assertion before it can emerge from the ardour of youth
into the mature wisdom of manhood. In
spite of its appeals to science, the true scientific philosophy, I think, is
something more arduous and more aloof, appealing to less mundane hopes, and
requiring a severer discipline for its successful practice.
Darwin's Origin
of Species persuaded the world that the difference between different
species of animals and plants is not the fixed immutable difference that it
appears to be. The doctrine of natural
kinds, which has rendered classification easy and definite, which was enshrined
in the Aristotelian tradition, and protected by its supposed necessity for
orthodox dogma, was suddenly swept away for ever out of the biological
world. The difference between man and
the lower animals, which to our human conceit appears enormous, was shown to be
a gradual achievement, involving intermediate beings who could not with
certainty be placed either within or without the human family. The sun and the planets had already been
shown by Laplace to be very probably derived from a
primitive more or less undifferentiated nebula.
Thus the old fixed landmarks became wavering and indistinct, and all
sharp outlines were blurred. Things and
species lost their boundaries, and none could say where they began or where
they ended.
But if
human conceit was staggered for a moment by its kinship with the ape, it soon
found a way to reassert itself, and that way is the 'philosophy' of
evolution. A process which led from the
amoeba to Man appeared to the philosophers to be obviously a progress - though
whether the amoeba would agree with this opinion is not known. Hence the cycle of chances which science had
shown to be the probable history of the past was welcomed as revealing a law of
development towards good in the universe - an evolution or unfolding of an idea
slowly embodying itself in the actual.
But such a view, though it might satisfy Spencer and those whom we may
call Hegelian evolutionists, could not be accepted as adequate by the more
whole-hearted votaries of change. An
ideal to which the world continuously approaches is, to these minds, to dead
and static to be inspiring. Not only the
aspiration, but the ideal too, must change and develop with the course of
evolution: there must be no fixed goal, but a continual fashioning of fresh
needs by the impulse which is life and which alone gives unity to the process.
Life, in
this philosophy, is a continuous stream, in which all divisions are artificial
and unreal. Separate things, beginnings
and endings, are mere convenient fictions: there is only smooth unbroken
transition. The beliefs of today may
count as true today, if they carry us along the stream; but tomorrow they will
be false, and must be replaced by new beliefs to meet the new situation. All our thinking consists of conventional
fictions, imaginary congealings of the stream:
reality flows on in spite of all our fictions, and though it can be lived, it
cannot be conceived in thought. Somehow,
without explicit statement, the assurance is slipped in that the future, though
we cannot foresee it, will be better than the past or the present: the reader
is like the child which expects a sweet because it has
been told to open its mouth and shut its eyes.
Logic, mathematics, physics disappear in this philosophy, because they
are too 'static'; what is real is no impulse and movement towards a goal which,
like the rainbow, recedes as we advance, and makes every place different when
it reaches it from what it appeared to be at a distance.
I do not
propose to enter upon a technical examination of this philosophy. I wish only to maintain that the motives and
interests which inspire it are so exclusively practical, and the problems with
which it deals are so special, that it can hardly be regarded as touching any
of the questions that, to my mind, constitute genuine philosophy.
The
predominant interest of evolutionism is in the question of human destiny, or at
least of the destiny of Life. It is more
interested in morality and happiness than in knowledge for its own sake. It must be admitted that the same may be said
of many other philosophies, and that a desire for the kind of knowledge which
philosophy can give is very rare. But if
philosophy is to attain truth, it is necessary first and foremost that philosophers should acquire the disinterested
intellectual curiosity which characterizes the genuine man of science. Knowledge concerning the future - which is
the kind of knowledge that must be sought if we are to know about human destiny
- is possible within certain narrow limits.
It is impossible to say how much the limits may be enlarged with the
progress of science. But what is evident
is that any proposition about the future belongs by its subject-matter to some
particular science, and is to be ascertained, if at all, by the methods of that
science. Philosophy is not a short cut
to the same kind of results as those of the other sciences: if it is to be a
genuine study, it must have a province of its own, and aim at results which the
other sciences can neither prove nor disprove.
Evolutionism,
in basing itself upon the notion of progress, which is change from the
worse to the better, allows the notion of time, as it seems to me, to become
its tyrant rather than its servant, and thereby loses that impartiality of
contemplation which is the source of all that is best in philosophic thought
and feeling. Metaphysicians, as we saw,
have frequently denied altogether the reality of time. I do not wish to do this; I wish only to
preserve the mental outlook which inspired the denial, the attitude which, in
thought, regards the past as having the same reality as the present and the
same importance as the future.
'Insofar,' says Spinoza, [Ethics, Bk. IV, Prop. LXII] 'as
the mind conceives a thing according to the dictate of reason, it will be
equally affected whether the idea is that of a future, past, or present thing.' It is this
'conceiving according to the dictate of reason' that I find lacking in the
philosophy which is based on evolution.
IV. GOOD AND EVIL
Mysticism
maintains that all evil is illusory, and sometimes maintains the same view as
regards good, but more often holds that all Reality is good. Both views are to be found in Heraclitus: 'Good and ill are one,'
he says, but again, 'To God all things are fair and good and right, but men
hold some things wrong and some right.'
A similar twofold position is to be found in Spinoza, but he uses the
word 'perfection' when he means to speak of the good that is not merely
human. 'By reality and perfection I mean
the same thing,' he says; [Ethics, Pt. II, Df. VI] but elsewhere
we find the definition: 'By good I shall mean that which we certainly
know to be useful to us.' [Ethics, Pt. IV, Df. I] Thus perfection
belongs to Reality in its own nature, but goodness is relative to ourselves and
our needs, and disappears in an impartial survey. Some such distinction, I think, is necessary
in order to understand the ethical outlook of mysticism: there is a lower
mundane kind of good and evil, which divides the world of appearance into what
seem to be conflicting parts; but there is also a higher, mystical kind of
good, which belongs to Reality and is not opposed by any correlative kind of
evil.
It is
difficult to give a logically tenable account of this position without
recognizing that good and evil are subjective, that what is good is merely that
towards which we have one kind of feeling, and what is evil is merely that
towards which we have another kind of feeling.
In our active life, where we have to exercise choice, and to prefer this
to that of two possible acts, it is necessary to have a distinction of good and
evil, or at least of better and worse.
But this distinction, like everything pertaining to action, belongs to
what mysticism regards as the world of illusion, if only because it is
essentially concerned with time. In our
contemplative life, where action is not called for, it is possible to be
impartial, and to overcome the ethical dualism which action requires. So long as we remain merely impartial,
we may be content to say that both the good and the evil of action are
illusions. But if, as we must do if we
have the mystic vision, we find the whole world worthy of love and worship, if
we see
'The earth, and every common sight ...
Apparell'd in celestial light,'
we shall say that there is a higher good than that of
action, and that this higher good belongs to the whole world as it is in
reality. In this way the twofold attitude
and the apparent vacillation of mysticism are explained and justified.
The
possibility of this universal love and joy in all that exists is of supreme
importance for the conduct and happiness of life, and gives inestimable value
to the mystic emotion, apart from any creeds which may be built upon it. But if we are not to be led into false
beliefs, it is necessary to realize exactly what the mystic emotion
reveals. It reveals a possibility of
human nature - a possibility of a nobler, happier, freer life than any that can
be otherwise achieved. But it does not
reveal anything about the non-human, or about the
nature of the universe in general. Good
and bad, and even the higher good that mysticism finds everywhere, are the
reflections of our own emotions on other things, not part of the substance of
things as they are in themselves. And
therefore an impartial contemplation, freed from all preoccupation with Self, will not judge things good or bad, although it is very
easily combined with that feeling of universal love which leads the mystic to
say that the whole world is good.
The
philosophy of evolution, through the notion of progress, is bound up with the
ethical dualism of the worse and the better, and is thus shut out, not only
from the kind of survey which discards good and evil altogether from its view,
but also from the mystical belief in the goodness of everything. In this way the distinction of good and evil,
like time, becomes a tyrant in this philosophy, and introduces into thought the
restless selectiveness of action. Good
and evil, like time, are, it would seem, not general or fundamental in the
world of thought, but late and highly specialized members of the intellectual
hierarchy.
Although,
as we saw, mysticism can be interpreted so as to agree with the view that good
and evil are not intellectually fundamental, it must be admitted that here we
are no longer in verbal agreement with most of the great philosophers and
religious teachers of the past. I
believe, however, that the elimination of ethical considerations from
philosophy is both scientifically necessary and - though this may seem a
paradox - an ethical advance. Both these
contentions must be briefly defended.
The hope of
satisfaction to our more human desires - the hope of demonstrating that the
world has this or that desirable ethical characteristic - is not one which, so
far as I can see, a scientific philosophy can do anything whatever to
satisfy. The difference between a good
world and a bad one is a difference in the particular characteristics of the
particular things that exist in these worlds: it is not a sufficiently abstract
difference to come within the province of philosophy. Love and hate, for example, are ethical
opposites, but to philosophy they are closely analogous attitudes towards
objects. The general form and structure
of those attitudes towards objects which constitute mental phenomena is a
problem for philosophy, but the difference between love and hate is not a difference
of form or structure, and therefore belongs rather to the special science of
psychology than to philosophy. Thus the
ethical interests which have often inspired
philosophers must remain in the background: some kind of ethical interest may
inspire the whole study, but none must obtrude in the detail or be expected in
the special results which are sought.
If this
view seems at first sight disappointing, we must remind ourselves that a
similar change has been found necessary in all the other sciences. The physicist or chemist is not now required
to prove the ethical importance of his ions or atoms; the biologist is not
expected to prove the utility of the plants or animals which he dissects. In pre-scientific ages this was not the case. Astronomy, for example, was studied because
men believed in astrology: it was thought that the movements of the planets had
the most direct and important bearing upon the lives of human beings. Presumably, when this belief decayed and the
disinterested study of astronomy began, many who had found astrology
absorbingly interesting decided that astronomy had too little human interest to
be worthy of study. Physics, as it
appears in Plato's Timaeus for example, is full of
ethical notions: it is an essential part of its purpose to show that the earth
is worthy of admiration. The modern
physicist, on the contrary, though he has no wish to deny that the earth is
admirable, is not concerned, as physicist, with its ethical attributes: he is
merely concerned to find out facts, not to consider whether they are good or
bad. In psychology, the scientific
attitude is even more recent and more difficult than in the physical sciences:
it is natural to consider that human nature is either good or bad, and to
suppose that the difference between good and bad, so all-important in practice,
must be important in theory also. It is
only during the last century that an ethically neutral psychology has grown up;
and here too, ethical neutrality has been essential to scientific success.
In
philosophy, hitherto, ethical neutrality has been seldom sought and hardly ever
achieved. Men have remembered their
wishes, and have judged philosophies in relation to their wishes. Driven from the particular sciences, the
belief that the notions of good and evil must afford a key to the understanding
of the world has sought a refuge in philosophy.
But even from this last refuge, if philosophy is not to remain a set of
pleasing dreams, this belief must be driven forth. It is a commonplace that happiness is not
best achieved by those who seek it directly; and it would seem that the same is
true of the good. In thought, at any
rate, those who forget good and evil and seek only to know the facts are more
likely to achieve good that those who view the world through the distorting
medium of their own desires.
We are thus
brought back to our seeming paradox, that a philosophy which does not seek to
impose upon the world its own conceptions of good and evil is not only more
likely to achieve truth, but is also the outcome of a higher ethical standpoint
than one which, like evolutionism and most traditional systems, is perpetually
appraising the universe and seeking to find in it an embodiment of present
ideals. In religion, and in every deeply
serious view of the world and of human destiny, there is an element of
submission, a realization of the limits of human power, which is somewhat
lacking in the modern world, with its quick material successes and its insolent
belief in the boundless possibilities of progress. 'He that loveth his
life shall lose it;' and there is danger lest, through a too confident love of
life, life itself should lose much of what gives it its highest worth. The submission which religion inculcates in
action is essentially the same in spirit as that which science teaches in thought;
and the ethical neutrality by which its victories have been achieved is the
outcome of that submission.
The good
which it concerns us to remember is the good which it lies in our power to
create - the good in our own lives and in our attitude towards the world. Insistence on belief in an external
realization of the good is a form of self-assertion, which, while it cannot
secure the external good which it desires, can seriously impair the inward good
which lies within our power, and destroy that reverence towards fact which
constitutes both what is valuable in humility and what is fruitful in the
scientific temper.
Human
beings cannot, of course, wholly transcend human nature; something subjective,
if only the interest that determines the direction of our attention, must
remain in all our thought. But
scientific philosophy comes nearer to objectivity than any other human pursuit,
and gives us, therefore, the closest constant and the most intimate relation
with the outer world that it is possible to achieve. To the primitive mind, everything is either
friendly or hostile; but experience has shown that friendliness and hostility
are not the conceptions by which the world is to be understood. Scientific philosophy thus represents, though
as yet only in a nascent condition, a higher form of thought than any
pre-scientific belief or imagination, and, like every approach to
self-transcendence, it brings with it a rich reward in increase of scope and
breadth and comprehension. Evolutionism,
in spite of its appeals to particular scientific facts, fails to be a truly
scientific philosophy because of its slavery to time, its ethical
preoccupations, and its predominant interest in our mundane concerns and
destiny. A truly scientific philosophy
will be more humble, more piecemeal, more arduous, offering less glitter of
outward mirage to flatter fallacious hopes, but more indifferent to fate, and
more capable of accepting the world without the tyrannous imposition of our
human and temporary demands.
CHAPTER II
The Place of
Science in a Liberal Education
I
SCIENCE, to the ordinary reader of newspapers, is
represented by a varying selection of sensational triumphs, such as wireless
telegraphy and aeroplanes, radio-activity and the marvels of modern alchemy. It is not of this aspect of science that I
wish to speak. Science, in this aspect,
consists of detached up-to-date fragments, interesting only until they are
replaced by something newer and more up-to-date, displaying nothing of the
systems of patiently constructed knowledge out of which, almost as a casual
incident, have come the practically useful results which interest the man in
the street. The increased command over
the forces of nature which is derived from science is undoubtedly an amply sufficient
reason for encouraging scientific research, but this reason has been so often
urged and is so easily appreciated that other reasons, to my mind quite as
important, are apt to be overlooked. It
is with these other reasons, especially with the intrinsic value of a
scientific habit of mind in forming our outlook on the world,
that I shall be concerned in what follows.
The
instance of wireless telegraphy will serve to illustrate the difference between
the two points of view. Almost all the
serious intellectual labour required for the possibility of this invention is
due to three men - Faraday, Maxwell, and Hertz.
In alternating layers of experiment and theory these three men built up
the modern theory of electromagnetism, and demonstrated the identity of light
with electromagnetic waves. The system
which they discovered is one of profound intellectual interest, bringing
together and unifying an endless variety of apparently detached phenomena, and
displaying a cumulative mental power which cannot but afford delight to every
generous spirit. The mechanical details
which remained to be adjusted in order to utilize their discoveries for a
practical system of telegraphy demanded, no doubt, very considerable ingenuity,
but had that broad sweep and that universality which could give them intrinsic
interest as an object of disinterested contemplation.
From the
point of view of training the mind, of giving that well-informed, impersonal
outlook which constitutes culture in the good sense of this much misused word,
it seems to be generally held indisputable that a literary education is
superior to one based on science. Even
the warmest advocates of science are apt to rest their claims on the contention
that culture ought to be sacrificed to utility.
Those men of science who respect culture, when they associate with men
learned in the classics, are apt to admit, not merely politely, but sincerely,
a certain inferiority on their side, compensated doubtless by the services
which science renders to humanity, but nonetheless real. And so long as this attitude exists among men
of science, it tends to verify itself: the intrinsically valuable aspects of
science tend to be sacrificed to the merely useful,
and little attempt is made to preserve that leisurely, systematic survey by
which the finer quality of mind is formed and nourished.
But even if
there be, in present fact, any such inferiority as is supposed in the
educational value of science, this is, I believe, not the fault of science
itself, but the fault of the spirit in which science is taught. If its full possibilities were realized by
those who teach it, I believe that its capacity for producing those habits of
mind which constitute the highest mental excellence would be at least as great
as that of literature, and more particularly of Greek and Latin
literature. In saying this I have no
wish whatever to disparage a classical education. I have not myself enjoyed its benefits, and
my knowledge of Greek and Latin authors is derived almost wholly from translations. But I am firmly persuaded that the Greeks
fully deserve all the admiration that is bestowed upon them, and that it is a
very great and serious loss to be unacquainted with their writings. It is not by attacking them, but by drawing
attention to neglected excellences in science, that I wish to conduct my
argument.
One defect,
however, does seem inherent in a purely classical education - namely, a too
exclusive emphasis on the past. By the
study of what is absolutely ended and can never be renewed, a habit of
criticism towards the present and the future is engendered. The qualities in which the present excels are
qualities to which the study of the past does not direct attention, and to
which, therefore, the student of Greek civilization may easily become
blind. In what is new and growing there
is apt to be something crude, insolent, even a little vulgar, which is shocking
to the man of sensitive taste; quivering from the rough contact, he retires to
the trim gardens of a polished past, forgetting that they were reclaimed from
the wilderness by men as rough and earth-soiled as those from whom he shrinks
in his own day. The habit of being
unable to recognize merit until it is dead is too apt to be the result of a
purely bookish life, and a culture based wholly on the past will seldom be able
to pierce through everyday surroundings to the essential splendour of
contemporary things, or to the hope of still greater splendour in the future.
'My eyes saw not the men of old;
And now their age away has rolled.
I weep - to think I shall not see
The heroes of posterity.'
So says the Chinese poet; but such impartiality is
rare in the more pugnacious atmosphere of the West, where the champions of past
and future fight a never-ending battle, instead of combining to seek out the
merits of both.
This
considerations, which militates not only against the exclusive study of the
classics, but against every form of culture which has become static,
traditional, and academic, leads inevitably to the fundamental question: What
is the true end of education? But before
attempting to answer this question it will be well to define the sense in which
we are to use the word 'education'. For
this purpose I shall distinguish the sense in which I mean to use it from two
others, both perfectly legitimate, the one broader and the other narrower than
the sense in which I mean to use the word.
In the
broader sense, education will include not only what we learn through instruction,
but all that we learn through personal experience - the formation of character
through the education of life. Of this
aspect of education, vitally important as it is, I will say nothing, since its
consideration would introduce topics quite foreign to the question with which
we are concerned.
In the
narrower sense, education may be confined to instruction, the imparting of
definite information on various subjects, because such information, in and for
itself, is useful in daily life.
Elementary education - reading, writing, and arithmetic - is almost
wholly of this kind. But instruction,
necessary as it is, does not per se constitute education in the sense in
which I wish to consider it.
Education,
in the sense in which I mean it, may be defined as the formation, by means
of instruction, of certain mental habits and a certain outlook on the life and
the world. It remains to ask
ourselves, what mental habits, and what sort of outlook, can be hoped for as
the result of instruction? When we have
answered this question we can attempt to decide what science has to contribute
to the formation of the habits and outlook which we desire.
Our whole
life is built about a certain number - not a very small number - of primary
instincts and impulses. Only in what is
in some way connected with these instincts and impulses appears to us desirable
or important; there is no faculty, whether 'reason' or 'virtue' or whatever it
may be called, that can take our active life and our hopes and fears outside
the region controlled by these first movers of all desire. Each of them is like a queen bee, aided by a
hive of workers gathering honey; but when the queen is gone the workers
languish and die, and the cells remain empty of their expected sweetness. So with each primary impulse in civilized
man: it is surrounded and protected by a busy swarm of attendant derivative
desires, which store up in its service whatever honey the surrounding world
affords. But if the queen-impulse dies,
the death-dealing influence, though retarded a little by habit, spreads slowly
through all the subsidiary impulses, and a whole tract of life becomes
inexplicably colourless. What was
formerly full of zest, and so obviously worth doing that it raised no
questions, had now grown dreary and purposeless: with a sense of disillusion we
inquire the meaning of life, and decide, perhaps, that all is vanity. The search for an outside meaning that can compel
an inner response must always be disappointed: all 'meaning' must be at bottom
related to our primary desires, and when they are extinct no miracle can
restore to the world the value which they reflected upon it.
The purpose
of education, therefore, cannot be to create any primary impulse which is
lacking in the uneducated; the purpose can only be to enlarge the scope of
those that human nature provides, by increasing the number and variety of
attendant thoughts, and by showing where the most permanent satisfaction is to
be found. Under the impulse of a
Calvinistic horror of the 'natural man', this obvious truth has been too often
misconceived in the training of the young; 'nature' has been falsely regarded
as excluding all that is best in what is natural, and the endeavour to teach
virtue has led to the production of stunted and contorted hypocrites instead of
full-grown human beings. From such
mistakes in education a better psychology or a kinder heart is beginning to
preserve the present generation; we need, therefore, waste no more words on the
theory that the purpose of education is to thwart or eradicate nature.
But
although nature must supply the initial force of desire, nature is not, in the
civilized man, the spasmodic, fragmentary, and yet violent set of impulses that
it is in the savage. Each impulse has
its constitutional ministry of thought and knowledge and reflection, through
which possible conflicts of impulses are foreseen, and
temporary impulses are controlled by the unifying impulse which may be called
wisdom. In this way education destroys
the crudity of instinct, and increases through knowledge the wealth and variety
of the individual's contacts with the outside world, making him no longer an
isolated fighting unit, but a citizen of the universe, embracing distant
countries, remote regions of space, and vast stretches of past and future
within the circle of his interests. It
is this simultaneous softening in the insistence of desire and enlargement of
its scope that is the chief moral end of education.
Closely
connected with this moral end is the more purely intellectual aim of education,
the endeavour to make us see and imagine the world in an objective manner, as
far as possible as it is in itself, and not merely through the distorting
medium of personal desire. The complete
attainment of such an objective view is no doubt an ideal, indefinitely
approachable, but not actually and fully realizable. Education, considered as a process of forming
our mental habits and our outlook on the world, is to be judged successful in
proportion as its outcome approximates to this ideal; in proportion, that is to
say, as it gives us a true view of our place in society, of the relation of the
whole human society to its non-human environment, and of the nature of the
non-human world as it is in itself apart from our desires and interests. If this standard is admitted, we can return
to the consideration of science, inquiring how far science contributes to such
an aim, and whether it is in any respect superior to its rivals in educational
practice.
II
Two
opposite and at first sight conflicting merits belong to science as against
literature and art. The one, which is
not inherently necessary, but is certainly true at the present day, is
hopefulness as to the future of human achievement, and in particular as to the
useful work that may be accomplished by any intelligent student. This merit and the cheerful outlook which it
engenders prevent what might otherwise be the depressing effect of another
aspect of science, to my mind also a merit, and perhaps its greatest merit - I
mean the irrelevance of human passions and of the whole subjective apparatus
where scientific truth is concerned.
Each of these reasons for preferring the study of science requires some
amplification. Let us begin with the
first.
In the
study of literature or art our attention is perpetually riveted upon the past:
the men of Greece or of the Renaissance did better than any men do now; the
triumphs of the former age, so far from facilitating fresh triumphs in our own
age, actually increase the difficulty of fresh triumphs by rendering
originality harder of attainment; not only is artistic achievement not
cumulative, but it seems even to depend upon a certain freshness and naiveté
of impulse and vision which civilization tends to destroy. Hence comes, to those who have been nourished
on the literary and artistic productions of former ages, a certain peevishness
and undue fastidiousness towards the present, from which there seems no escape
except into the deliberate vandalism which ignores tradition and in the search after
originality achieves only the eccentric.
But in such vandalism there is none of the simplicity and spontaneity
out of which great art springs: theory is still the canker in its core, and
insincerity destroys the advantages of a merely pretended ignorance.
The despair
thus arising from an education which suggests no pre-eminent mental activity
except that of artistic creation is wholly absent from an education which gives
the knowledge of scientific method. The
discovery of scientific method, except in pure mathematics, is a thing of
yesterday; speaking broadly, we may say that it dates from Galileo. Yet already it has transformed the world, and
its success proceeds with ever-accelerating velocity. In science men have discovered an activity of
the very highest value in which they are no longer, as in art, dependent for
progress upon the appearance of continually greater genius, for in science the
successors stand upon the shoulders of their predecessors; where one man of
supreme genius has invented a method, a thousand lesser men apply it. No transcendent ability is required in order
to make useful discoveries in science; the edifice of science needs its masons,
bricklayers and common labourers as well as its foremen, master-builders and
architects. In art nothing worth doing
can be done without genius; in science even a very moderate capacity can
contribute to a supreme achievement.
In science
the man of real genius is the man who invents a new method. The notable discoveries are often made by his
successors, who can apply the method with fresh vigour, unimpaired by the
previous labour of perfecting it; but the mental calibre of the thought
required for their work, however brilliant, is not so great as that required by
the first inventor of the method. There
are in science immense numbers of different methods, appropriate to different
classes of problems; but over and over them all, there is something not easily
definable, which may be called the method of science. It was formerly customary to identify this
with the inductive method, and to associate it with the name of Bacon. But the true inductive method was not
discovered by Bacon, and the true method of science is something which includes
deduction as much as induction, logic and mathematics as much as botany and
geology. I shall not attempt the
difficult task of stating what the scientific method is, but I will try to
indicate the temper of mind out of which the scientific method grows, which is
the second of the two merits that were mentioned above as belonging to
scientific education.
The kernel
of the scientific outlook is a thing so simple, so obvious, so
seemingly trivial, that the mention of it may almost excite derision. The kernel of the scientific outlook is the
refusal to regard our own desires, tastes and interests as affording a key to
the understanding of the world. Stated
thus baldly, this may seem no more than a trite truism. But to remember it consistently in matters
arousing our passionate partisanship is by no means easy, especially where the
available evidence is uncertain and inconclusive. A few illustrations will make this clear.
Aristotle,
I understand, considered that the stars must move in circles because the circle
is the most perfect curve. In the
absence of evidence to the contrary, he allowed himself to decide a question of
fact by an appeal to aesthetico-moral
considerations. In such a case it is at
once obvious to us that this appeal was unjustifiable. We know now how to ascertain as a fact the
way in which the heavenly bodies move, and we know that they do not move in
circles, or even in accurate ellipses, or in any other kind of simply
describable curve. This may be painful
to a certain hankering after simplicity of pattern in the universe, but we know
that in astronomy such feelings are irrelevant.
Easy as this knowledge seems now, we owe it to the courage and insight
of the first inventors of scientific method, and more especially of Galileo.
We may take
as another illustration Malthus's doctrine of population. This illustration is all the better for the
fact that his actual doctrine is now known to be largely erroneous. It is not his conclusions that are valuable,
but the temper and method of his inquiry.
As everyone knows, it was to him that Darwin owed an essential part of
his theory of natural selection, and this was only possible because Malthus's outlook was truly scientific. His great merit lies in considering man not
as the object of praise or blame, but as part of nature, a thing with a certain
characteristic behaviour from which certain consequences must follow. If the behaviour is not quite what Malthus supposed, if the consequences are not quite what he
inferred, that may falsify his conclusions, but does not impair the value of
his method. The objections which were
made when his doctrines were new - that it was horrible and depressing, that
people ought not to act as he said they did, and so on - were all such as
implied an unscientific attitude of mind; as against all of them, his calm determination
to treat man as a natural phenomenon marks an important advance over the
reformers of the eighteenth century and the Revolution.
Under the
influence of Darwinism the scientific attitude towards man has now become
fairly common, and is to some people quite natural, though to most it is still
a difficult and artificial contortion.
There is, however, one study which is as yet almost wholly untouched by
the scientific spirit - I mean the study of philosophy. Philosophers and the public
image that the scientific spirit must pervade pages that bristle with allusions
to ions, germ plasmas, and the eyes of shellfish. But as the devil can quote Scripture, so the
philosopher can quote science. The
scientific spirit is not an affair of quotation, of externally acquired
information, any more than manners are an affair of the etiquette book. The scientific attitude of mind involves a
sweeping away of all other desires in the interests of the desire to know - it
involves suppression of hopes and fears, loves and hates, and the whole
subjective emotional life, until we become subdued to the material, able to see
it frankly, without preconceptions, without bias, without any wish except to
see it as it is, and without any belief that what it is must be determined by
some relation, positive or negative, to what we should like it to be, or to
what we can easily imagine it to be.
Now in
philosophy this attitude of mind has not as yet been achieved. A certain self-absorption, not personal, but
human, has marked almost all attempts to conceive the universe as a whole. Mind, or some aspect of it - thought or will
or sentience - has been regarded as the pattern after which the universe is to
be conceived, for no better reason, at bottom, than that such a universe would
not seem strange, any would give us the cosy feeling that every place is like
home. To conceive the universe as
essentially progressive or essentially deteriorating, for example, is to give
to our hopes and fears a cosmic importance which may, of course, be
justified, but which we have as yet no reason to suppose justified. Until we have learnt to think of it in
ethically neutral terms, we have not arrived at a scientific attitude in
philosophy; and until we have arrived at such an attitude, it is hardly to be
hoped that philosophy will achieve any solid results.
I have
spoken so far largely of the negative aspect of the scientific spirit, but it
is from the positive aspect that its value is derived. The instinct of constructiveness, which is
one of the chief incentives to artistic creation, can find in scientific
systems a satisfaction more massive than any epic poem. Disinterested curiosity, which is the source
of almost all intellectual effort, finds with astonished delight that science
can unveil secrets which might well have seemed for ever undiscoverable. The desire for a larger life and wider
interests, for an escape from private circumstances, and even from the whole
recurring human cycle of birth and death, is fulfilled by the impersonal cosmic
outlook of science as by nothing else.
To all these must be added, as contributing to the happiness of the man
of science, the admiration of splendid achievement, and the consciousness of
inestimable utility to the human race. A
life devoted to science is therefore a happy life, and its happiness is derived
from the very best sources that are open to dwellers on this troubled and
passionate planet.
CHAPTER III
A Free Man's Worship
[Reprinted from the Independent Review, December, 1903.]
TO Dr Faustus in his study Mephistopheles told the
history of the Creation, saying:
'The
endless praises of the choirs of angels had begun to grow wearisome; for, after
all, did He not deserve their praise?
Had He not given them endless joy?
Would it not be more amusing to obtain undeserved praise, to be
worshipped by beings whom He tortured? He smiled inwardly, and resolved that the
great drama should be performed.
'For
countless ages the hot nebula whirled aimlessly through space. At length it began to take shape, the central
mass threw off planets, the planets cooled, boiling seas and burning mountains
heaved and tossed, from black masses of cloud hot sheets of rain deluged the
barely solid crust. And now the first
germ of life grew in the depths of the ocean, and developed rapidly in the
fructifying warmth into vast forest trees, huge ferns springing from the damp
mould, sea monsters breeding, fighting, devouring, and passing away. And from the monsters, as the play unfolded
itself, Man was born, with the power of thought, the knowledge of good and
evil, and the cruel thirst for worship.
And Man saw that all is passing in this mad, monstrous world, that all
is struggling to snatch, at any cost, a few brief moments of life before
Death's inexorable decree. And Man said:
"There is a hidden purpose, could we but fathom it, and the purpose is
good; for we must reverence something and in the visible world there is nothing
worthy of reverence." And Man stood
aside from the struggle, resolving that God intended harmony to come out of
chaos by human efforts. And when he
followed the instincts which God had transmitted to him from his ancestry of
beasts of prey, he called it Sin, and asked God to forgive him. But he doubted whether he could be justly forgiven,
until he invented a divine Plan by which God's wrath was to have been
appeased. And seeing the present was
bad, he made it yet worse, that thereby the future might be better. And he gave God thanks for the strength that
enabled him to forgo even the joys that were possible. And God smiled; and when he saw that Man had
become perfect in renunciation and worship, he sent another sun through the
sky, which crashed into Man's sun; and all returned again to nebula
'"Yes,"
he murmured, "it was a good play; I will have it performed again."'
Such, in
outline, but even more purposeless, more void of meaning, is the world which
Science presents for our belief. Amid
such a world, if anywhere, our ideals henceforward must find a home. That Man is the product of causes which had
no prevision of the end they were achieving; that his origin, his growth, his
hopes and fears, his loves and his beliefs, are but the outcome of accidental
collocations of atoms; that no fire, no heroism, no intensity of thought and
feeling, can preserve an individual life beyond the grave; that all the labours
of the ages, all the devotion, all the inspiration, all the noonday brightness
of human genius, are destined to extinction in the vast death of the solar
system, and that the whole temple of Man's achievement must inevitably be
buried beneath the debris of a universe in ruins - all these things, if not
quite beyond dispute, are yet so nearly certain, that no philosophy which
rejects them can hope to stand. Only
within the scaffolding of these truths, only on the firm foundation of
unyielding despair, can the soul's habitation henceforth be safely built.
How, in
such an alien and inhuman world, can so powerless a creature as Man preserve
his aspirations untarnished? A strange
mystery it is that Nature, omnipotent but blind, in the revolutions of her
secular hurryings through the abysses of space, has
brought forth at last a child, subject still to her power, but gifted with
sight, with knowledge of good and evil, with the capacity of judging all the
works of his unthinking Mother. In spite
of Death, the mark and seal of the parental control, Man is yet free, during
his brief years, to examine, to criticize, to know, and in imagination to
create. To him alone, in the world with
which he is acquainted, this freedom belongs; and in this lies
his superiority to the restless forces that control his outward life.
The savage,
like ourselves, feels the oppression of his impotence before the powers of
Nature; but having in himself nothing that he respects more than Power, he is
willing to prostrate himself before his gods, without inquiring whether they
are worthy of his worship. Pathetic and
very terrible is the long history of cruelty and torture, of degradation and
human sacrifice, endured in the hope of placating the jealous gods: surely, the
trembling believer thinks, when what is most precious has been freely given,
their lust for blood must be appeased, and more will not be required. The religion of Moloch
- as such creeds may be generically called - is in essence the cringing
submission of the slave, who dare not, even in his heart, allow the thought
that his master deserves no adulation.
Since the independence of ideals is not yet acknowledged, Power may be
freely worshipped, and receive an unlimited respect, despite its wanton
infliction of pain.
But
gradually, as morality grows bolder, the claim of the ideal world begins to be
felt; and worship, if it is not to cease, must be given to gods of another kind
than those created by the savage. Some,
though they feel the demands of the ideal, will still consciously reject them,
still urging that naked Power is worthy of worship. Such is the answer inculcated in God's answer
to Job out of the whirlwind: the divine power and knowledge are paraded, but of
the divine goodness there is no hint.
Such also is the attitude of those who, in our own day, base their
morality upon the struggle for survival, maintaining that the survivors are
necessarily the fittest. But others, not
content with an answer so repugnant to the moral sense, will adopt the position
which we have become accustomed to regard as specially
religious, maintaining that, in some hidden manner, the world of fact is really
harmonious with the world of ideals.
Thus Man creates God, all-powerful and all-good, the mystic unity of
what is and what should be.
But the
world of fact, after all, is not good; and, in submitting our judgement to it,
there is an element of slavishness from which our thoughts must be purged. For in all things it is well to exalt the
dignity of Man, by freeing him as far as possible from the tyranny of non-human
Power. When we have realized that Power
is largely bad, that man, with his knowledge of good and evil, is but a
helpless atom in a world which has no such knowledge, the choice is again
presented to us: Shall we worship Force, or shall we worship Goodness? Shall our God exist and be evil, or shall he
be recognized as the creation of our own conscience?
The answer
to this question is very momentous, and affects profoundly our whole
morality. The worship of Force, to which
Carlyle and Nietzsche and the creed of Militarism have accustomed us, is the
result of failure to maintain our own ideals against a hostile universe: it is
itself a prostrate submission to evil, a sacrifice of our best to Moloch. If strength
indeed is to be respected, let us respect rather the strength of those who
refuse that false 'recognition of facts' which fails to recognize that facts
are often bad. Let us admit that, in the
world we know, there are many things that would be better otherwise, and that
the ideals to which we do and must adhere are not realized in the realm of
matter. Let us preserve our respect for
truth, for beauty, for the ideal of perfection which life does not permit us to
attain, though none of these things meet with the approval of the unconscious
universe. If Power is bad, as it seems
to be, let us reject it from our hearts.
In this lies Man's true freedom: in determination to worship only the
God created by our own love of the good, to respect only the heaven which
inspires the insight of our best moments.
In action, in desire, we must submit perpetually to the tyranny of
outside forces; but in thought, in aspiration, we are free, free from our
fellow-men, free from the petty planet on which our bodies impotently crawl,
free even, while we live, from the tyranny of death. Let us learn, then, that energy of faith
which enables us to live constantly in the vision of the good; and let us
descend, in action, into the world of fact, with that vision always before us.
When first
the opposition of fact and ideal grows fully visible, a spirit of fiery revolt,
of fierce hatred of the gods, seems necessary to the assertion of freedom. To defy with Promethean constancy a hostile
universe, to keep its evil always in view, always actively hated, to refuse no
pain that the malice of Power can invent, appears to be the duty of all who
will not bow before the inevitable. But
indignation is still a bondage, for it compels our
thoughts to be occupied with an evil world; and in the fierceness of desire
from which rebellion springs there is a kind of self-assertion which it is
necessary for the wise to overcome.
Indignation is a submission of our thoughts, but not of our desires; the
Stoic freedom in which wisdom consists is found in the submission of our
desires, but not of our thoughts. From
the submission of our desires springs the virtue of resignation; from the freedom
of our thoughts springs the whole of art and philosophy, and the vision of
beauty by which, at last, we half reconquer the
reluctant world. But the vision of
beauty is possible only to unfettered contemplation,
to thoughts not weighted by the load of eager wishes; and thus Freedom comes
only to those who no longer ask of life that it shall yield them any of those
personal goods that are subject to the mutations of Time.
Although
the necessity of renunciation is evidence of the existence of evil, yet
Christianity, in preaching it, has shown a wisdom exceeding that of the
Promethean philosophy of rebellion. It
must be admitted that, of the things we desire, some, though they prove
impossible, are yet real goods; others, however, as ardently longed for, do not
form part of a fully purified ideal. The
belief that what must be renounced is bad, though sometimes false, is far less
often false than untamed passion supposes; and the creed of religion, by
providing a reason for proving that it is never false, has been the means of
purifying our hopes by the discovery of many austere truths.
But there
is in resignation a further good element: even real goods, when they are
unattainable, ought not to be fretfully desired. To every man comes, sooner or later, the
great renunciation. For the young, there
is nothing unattainable; a good thing desired with the whole force of a
passionate will, and yet impossible, is to them not credible. Yet, by death, by illness, by poverty, or by
the voice of duty, we must learn, each one of us, that the world was not made
for us, and that, however beautiful may be the things we crave, Fate may
nevertheless forbid them. It is the part
of courage, when misfortune comes, to bear without repining
the ruin of our hopes, to turn away our thoughts from vain regrets. This degree of submission to Power is not
only just and right: it is the very gate of wisdom.
But passive
renunciation is not the whole of wisdom; for not by renunciation alone can we
build a temple for the worship of our own ideals. Haunting foreshadowings
of the temple appear in the realm of imagination, in music, in architecture, in
the untroubled kingdom of reason, and in the golden sunset magic of lyrics,
where beauty shines and glows, remote from the failures and disenchantments of
the world of fact. In the contemplation
of these things the vision of heaven will shape itself in our hearts, giving at
once a touchstone to judge the world about us, and an inspiration by which to
fashion to our needs whatever is not incapable of serving as a stone in the sacred
temple.
Except for
those rare spirits that are born without sin, there is a cavern of darkness to
be traversed before that temple can be entered.
The gate of the cavern is despair, and its floor is paved with the
gravestones of abandoned hopes. There Self must die; there the eagerness, the greed of untamed
desire must be slain, for only so can the soul be freed from the empire of
Fate. But out of the cavern the Gate of
Renunciation leads again to the daylight of wisdom, by whose radiance a new
insight, a new joy, a new tenderness, shine forth to gladden the pilgrim's
heart.
When,
without the bitterness of impotent rebellion, we have learnt both to resign
ourselves to the outward rule of Fate and to recognize that the non-human world
is unworthy of our worship, it becomes possible at last so to transform and
refashion the unconscious universe, so to transmute it in the crucible of
imagination, that a new image of shining gold replaces the old idol of
clay. In all the multiform facts of the
world - in the visual shapes of trees and mountains and clouds, in the events
of the life of man, even in the very omnipotence of Death - the insight of
creative idealism can find the reflection of a beauty which its own thoughts
first made. In this way mind asserts its
subtle mastery over the thoughtless forces of Nature. The more evil the material with which it
deals, the more thwarting to untrained desire, the greater is its achievement
in inducing the reluctant rock to yield up its hidden treasures, the prouder its
victory in compelling the opposing forces to swell the pageant of its
triumph. Of all the arts, Tragedy is the
proudest, the most triumphant; for it builds its shining citadel in the very
centre of the enemy's country, on the very summit of his highest mountain; from
its impregnable watch towers, his camps and arsenals, his columns and forts,
are all revealed; within its walls the free life continues, while the legions
of Death and Pain and Despair, and all the servile captains of tyrant Fate,
afford the burghers of that dauntless city new spectacles of beauty. Happy those sacred
ramparts, thrice happy the dwellers on that all-seeing eminence. Honour to those brave
warriors who, through countless ages of warfare, have preserved for us the
priceless heritage of liberty, and have kept undefiled by sacrilegious invaders
the home of the unsubdued.
But the
beauty of Tragedy does not make visible a quality which, in more or less
obvious shapes, is present always and everywhere in life. In the spectacle of Death, in the endurance
of intolerable pain, and in the irrevocableness of a vanished past, there is a
sacredness, an overpowering awe, a feeling of the vastness, the depth, the
inexhaustible mystery of existence, in which, as by some strange marriage of pain,
the sufferer is bound to the world by bonds of sorrow. In these moments of insight, we lose all
eagerness of temporary desire, all struggling and striving for petty ends, all
care for the little trivial things that, to a superficial view, make up the
common life of day by day; we see, surrounding the narrow raft illumined by the
flickering light of human comradeship, the
dark ocean on whose rolling waves we toss for a brief hour; from the
great night without, a chill blast breaks in upon our refuge; all the
loneliness of humanity amid hostile forces is concentrated upon the individual
soul, which must struggle alone, with what of courage it can command, against
the whole weight of a universe that cares nothing for its hopes and fears. Victory, in this struggle with the powers of
darkness, is the true baptism into the glorious company of heroes, the true
initiation into the overmastering beauty of human existence. From that awful encounter of the soul with
the outer world, enunciation, wisdom, and charity are born; and with their
birth a new life begins. To take into
the inmost shrine of the soul the irresistible forces whose puppets we seem to
be - Death and change, the irrevocableness of the past, and the powerlessness
of man before the blind hurry of the universe from vanity to vanity - to feel
these things and know them is to conquer them.
This is the
reason why the Past has such magical power.
The beauty of its motionless and silent pictures is like the enchanted
purity of late autumn, when the leaves, though one
breath would make them fall, still glow against the sky in golden glory. The Past does not change or strive; like
The life of
Man, viewed outwardly, is but a small thing in comparison with the forces of
Nature. The slave is doomed to worship
Time and Fate and Death, because they are greater than anything he finds in
himself, and because all his thoughts are of things which they devour. But, great as they are, to think of them
greatly, to feel their passionless splendour, is greater still. And such thought makes us free men; we no
longer bow before the inevitable in Oriental subjection, but we absorb it, and
make it a part of ourselves. To abandon
the struggle for private happiness, to expel all eagerness of temporary desire,
to burn with passion for eternal things - this is emancipation, and this is the
free man's worship. And this liberation
is effected by a contemplation of Fate; for Fate
itself is subdued by the mind which leaves nothing to be purged by the
purifying fire of Time.
United with
his fellow-men by the strongest of all ties, the tie of a common doom, the free
man finds that a new vision is with him always, shedding over every daily task the
light of love. The life of Man is a long
march through the night, surrounded by invisible foes, tortured by weariness
and pain, towards a goal that few can hope to reach, and where none may tarry
long. One by one, as they march, our
comrades vanish from our sight, seized by the silent orders of omnipotent
Death. Very brief is the time in which
we can help them, in which their happiness or misery is decided. Be it ours to shed sunshine on their path, to
lighten their sorrows by the balm of sympathy, to give them the pure joy of a
never-ending affection, to strengthen failing courage, to instil faith in hours
of despair. Let us not weigh in grudging
scales their merits and demerits, but let us think only of their need - of the
sorrows, the difficulties, perhaps the blindnesses,
that make the misery of their lives; let us remember that they are
fellow-sufferers in the same darkness, actors in the same tragedy with ourselves. And so,
when their day is over, when their good and their evil have become eternal by
the immorality of the past, be it ours to feel that, where they suffered, where
they failed, no deed of ours was the cause; but wherever a spark of the divine
fire kindled in their hearts, we were ready with encouragement, with sympathy,
with brave words in which high courage glowed.
Brief and
powerless is Man's life; on him and all his race the
slow, sure doom falls pitiless and dark.
Blind to good and evil, reckless of destruction, omnipotent matter rolls
on its relentless way; for Man, condemned today to lose his dearest, tomorrow
himself to pass through the gate of darkness, it remains only to cherish, ere
yet the blow falls, the lofty thoughts that ennoble his little day; disdaining
the coward terrors of the slave of Fate, to worship at the shrine that his own
hands have built; undismayed by the empire of chance, to preserve a mind free
from the wanton tyranny that rules his outward life; proudly defiant of the
irresistible forces that tolerate, for a moment, his knowledge and his
condemnation, to sustain alone, a weary but unyielding Atlas, the world that
his own ideals have fashioned despite the trampling march of unconscious power.
CHAPTER IV
The Study of
Mathematics
IN regard to every form of human activity it is
necessary that the question should be asked from time to time, What is its purpose and ideal? In what way does it contribute to the beauty
of human existence? As in respect of
those pursuits which contribute only remotely, by providing the mechanism of
life, it is well to be reminded that not the mere fact of living is to be
desired, but the art of living in the contemplation of great things. Still more in regard to those avocations
which have no end outside ourselves, which are to be justified, if at all, as
actually adding to the sum of the world's permanent possessions, it is
necessary to keep alive a knowledge of their aims, a clear prefiguring vision
of the temple in which creative imagination is to be embodied.
The
fulfilment of this need, in what concerns the studies forming the material upon
which custom has decided to train the youthful mind, is indeed sadly remote -
so remote as to make the mere statement of such a claim appear
preposterous. Great men, fully alive to
the beauty of the contemplations to whose service their lives are devoted,
desiring that others may share in their joys, persuade mankind to impart to the
successive generations the mechanical knowledge without which it is impossible
to cross the threshold. Dry pedants
possess themselves of the privilege of instilling this knowledge: they forget
that it is to serve but as a key to open the doors of the temple; though they
spend their lives on the steps leading up to those sacred doors, they turn
their backs upon the temple so resolutely that its very existence is forgotten,
and the eager youth, who would press forward to be initiated to its domes and
arches, is bidden to turn back and count the steps.
Mathematics, perhaps more even than the study of
Mathematics,
rightly viewed, possesses not only truth, but supreme beauty - a beauty cold
and austere, like that of sculpture, without appeal to any part of our weaker
nature, without the gorgeous trappings of painting or music, yet sublimely
pure, and capable of a stern perfection such as only the greatest art can
show. The true spirit of delight, the
exaltation, the sense of being more than man, which is the touchstone of the
highest excellence, is to be found in mathematics as surely as in poetry. What is best in mathematics deserves not
merely to be learnt as a task, but to be assimilated as a part of daily thought,
and brought again and again before the mind with ever-renewed
encouragement. Real life is, to most
men, a long second-best, a perpetual compromise between the ideal and the
possible; but the world of pure reason knows no compromise, no practical limitations,
no barrier to the creative activity embodying in splendid edifices the
passionate aspiration after the perfect from which all great work springs. Remote from human passions, remote even from
the pitiful facts of nature, the generations have gradually created an ordered
cosmos, where pure thought can dwell as in its natural home, and where one, at
least, of our nobler impulses can escape from the dreary exile of the actual
world.
So little,
however, have mathematicians aimed at beauty, that hardly anything in their
work has had this conscious purpose. Much, owing to irrepressible instincts, which
were better than avowed beliefs, has been moulded by an unconscious taste; but
much also has been spoilt by false notions of what was fitting. The characteristic excellence of mathematics
is only to be found where the reasoning is rigidly logical: the rules of logic
are to mathematics what those of structure are to architecture. In the most beautiful work, a chain of
argument is presented in which every link is important on its own account, in
which there is an air of ease and lucidity throughout, and the premises achieve
more than would have been thought possible, by means which appear natural and
inevitable. Literature embodies what is
general in particular circumstances whose universal significance shines through
their individual dress; but mathematics endeavours to present whatever is most
general in its purity, without any irrelevant trappings.
How should
the teaching of mathematics be conducted so as to communicate to the learner as
much as possible of this high ideal?
Here experience must, in a great measure, be our guide; but some maxims
may result from our consideration of the ultimate purpose to be achieved.
One of the
chief ends served by mathematics, when rightly taught, is to awaken the
learner's belief in reason, his confidence in the truth of what has been
demonstrated, and in the value of demonstration. This purpose is not served by existing instruction;
but it is easy to see ways in which it might be served. At present, in what concerns arithmetic, the
boy or girl is given a set of rules, which present themselves as neither true
nor false, but as merely the will of the teacher, the way in which, for some
unfathomable reason, the teacher prefers to have the game played. To some degree, in a study of such definite
practical utility, this is no doubt unavoidable; but as soon as possible, the
reasons of rules should be set forth by whatever means most readily appeal to
the childish mind. In geometry, instead
of the tedious apparatus of fallacious proofs for obvious truisms which
constitutes the beginning of Euclid, the learner should be allowed at first to
assume the truth of everything obvious, and should be instructed in the
demonstrations of theorems which are at once startling and easily verifiable by
actual drawing, such as those in which it is shown that three or more lines
meet in a point. In this way belief is
generated; it is seen that reasoning may lead to startling conclusions, which
nevertheless the facts will verify; and thus the instinctive distrust of
whatever is abstract or rational is gradually overcome. Where theorems are difficult, they should be
first taught as exercises in geometrical drawing, until the figure has become
thoroughly familiar; it will then be an agreeable advance to be taught the
logical connections of the various lines or circles that occur. It is desirable also that the figure
illustrating a theorem should be drawn in all possible cases and shapes, that
so the abstract relations with which geometry is concerned may of themselves
emerge as the residue of similarity amid such great apparent diversity. In this way the abstract demonstrations
should form but a small part of the instruction, and should be given when, by
familiarity with concrete illustrations, they have come to be felt as the
natural embodiment of visible fact. In
this early stage proofs should not be given with pedantic fullness; definitely
fallacious methods, such as that of superposition, should be rigidly excluded
from the first, but where, without such methods, the proof would be very
difficult, the result should be rendered acceptable by arguments and
illustrations which are explicitly contrasted with demonstrations.
In the
beginning of algebra, even the most intelligent child finds, as a rule, very
great difficulty. The use of letters is
a mystery, which seems to have no purpose except mystification. It is almost impossible, at first, not to
think that every letter stands for some particular number, if only the teacher
would reveal what number it stands for.
The fact is, that in algebra the mind is first
taught to consider general truths, truths which are not asserted to hold only
of this or that particular thing, but of any one of a whole group of
things. It is in the power of
understanding and discovering such truths that the mastery of the intellect
over the whole world of things actual and possible resides; and ability to deal
with the general as such is one of the gifts that a mathematical education
should bestow. But how little, as a
rule, is the teacher of algebra able to explain the chasm which divides it from
arithmetic, and how little is the learner assisted in
his groping efforts at comprehension!
Usually the method that has been adopted in arithmetic is continued:
rules are set forth, with no adequate explanation of their grounds; the pupil
learns to use the rules blindly, and presently, when he is able to obtain the
answer that the teacher desires, he feels that he has mastered the difficulties
of the subject. But of inner
comprehension of the processes employed he has probably acquired almost
nothing.
When
algebra has been learnt, all goes smoothly until we reach those studies in
which the notion of infinity is employed - the infinitesimal calculus and the
whole of higher mathematics. The
solution of the difficulties which formerly surrounded the mathematical
infinite is probably the greatest achievement of which our own age has to
boast. Since the beginnings of Greek
thought these difficulties have been known; in every age the finest intellects
have vainly endeavoured to answer the apparently unanswerable questions that
had been asked by Zeno the Eleatic. At last Georg
Cantor has found the answer, and has conquered for the intellect a new and vast
province which had been given over to Chaos and old Night. It was assumed as self-evident, until Cantor
and Dedekind established the opposite, that if, from
any collection of things, some were taken away, the
number of things left must always be less than the original number of
things. This assumption, as a matter of
fact, holds only of finite collections; and the rejection of it, where the
infinite is concerned, has been shown to remove all the difficulties that had
hitherto baffled human reason in this matter, and to render possible the
creation of an exact science of the infinite.
This stupendous fact ought to produce a revolution in the higher
teaching of mathematics; it has itself added immeasurably to the educational
value of the subject, and it has at last given the means of treating with
logical precision many studies which, until lately, were wrapped in fallacy and
obscurity. By those who were educated on
the old lines, the new work is considered to be appallingly difficult,
abstruse, and obscure; and it must be confessed that the discoverer, as is so
often the case, has hardly himself emerged from the mists which the light of
his intellect is dispelling. But
inherently, the new doctrine of the infinite, to all candid and inquiring
minds, has facilitated the mastery of higher mathematics; for hitherto, it has
been necessary to learn, by a long process of sophistication, to give assent to
arguments which, on first acquaintance, were rightly judged to be confused and
erroneous. So far from producing a
fearless belief in reason, a bold rejection of whatever failed to fulfil the
strictest requirements of logic, a mathematical training, during the past two
centuries, encouraged the belief that many things, which a rigid inquiry would
reject as fallacious, must yet be accepted because they work in what the
mathematician calls 'practice'. By this
means, a timid, compromising spirit, or else a sacerdotal belief in mysteries
not intelligible to the profane, has been bred where reason alone should have
ruled. All this it is now time to sweep
away; let those who wish to penetrate into the arcana
of mathematics be taught at once the true theory in all its logical purity, and
in the concatenation established by the very essence of the entities concerned.
If we are
considering mathematics as an end in itself, and not
as a technical training for engineers, it is very desirable to preserve the
purity and strictness of its reasoning.
Accordingly those who have attained a sufficient familiarity with its
easier portions should be led backward from propositions to which they have
assented as self-evident to more and more fundamental principles from which
what had previously appeared as premises can be deduced. They should be taught - what the theory of
infinity very aptly illustrates - that many propositions seem self-evident to
the untrained mind which, nevertheless, a nearer scrutiny shows to be
false. By this means they will be led to
a sceptical inquiry into first principles, an examination of the foundations
upon which the whole edifice of reasoning is built, or, to take perhaps a more
fitting metaphor, the great trunk from which the spreading branches
spring. At this stage, it is well to study
afresh the elementary portions of mathematics, asking no longer merely whether
a given proposition is true, but also how it grows out of the central
principles of logic. Questions of this
nature can now be answered with a precision and certainty which was formerly
quite impossible; and in the chains of reasoning that the answer requires the
unity of all mathematical studies at last unfolds itself.
In the
great majority of mathematical textbooks there is a total lack of unity in
method and of systematic development of a central theme. Propositions of very diverse kinds are proved
by whatever means are thought most easily intelligible, and much space is
devoted to mere curiosities which in no way contribute to the main
argument. But in the greatest works,
unity and inevitability are felt as in the unfolding of a drama; in the
premises a subject is proposed for consideration, and in every subsequent step
some definite advance is made towards mastery of its nature. The love of system, of interconnection, which
is perhaps the inmost essence of the intellectual impulse, can find free play
in mathematics as nowhere else. The
learner who feels this impulse must not be repelled by an array of meaningless
examples or distracted by amusing oddities, but must be encouraged to dwell
upon central principles, to become familiar with the structure of the various
subjects which are put before him, to travel easily over the steps of the more
important deductions. In this way a good
tone of mind is cultivated, and selective attention is taught to dwell by preference
upon what is weighty and essential.
When the
separate studies into which mathematics is divided have each been viewed as a
logical whole, as a natural growth from the propositions which constitute their
principles, the learner will be able to understand the fundamental science
which unifies and systematizes the whole of deductive reasoning. This is symbolic logic - a study which,
though it owes its inception to Aristotle, is yet, in its wider developments, a
product, almost wholly, of the nineteenth century, and is indeed, in the
present day, still growing with great rapidity.
The true method of discovery in symbolic logic, and probably also the
best method for introducing the study to a learner acquainted with other parts
of mathematics, is the analysis of actual examples of deductive reasoning, with
a view to the discovery of the principles employed. These principles, for the most part, are so
embedded in our ratiocinative instincts, that they
are employed quite unconsciously, and can be dragged to light only by much
patient effort. But when at last they
have been found, they are seen to be few in number, and to be the sole source
of everything in pure mathematics. The
discovery that all mathematics follows inevitably from a small collection of
fundamental laws is one which immeasurably enhances the intellectual beauty of
the whole; to those who have been oppressed by the fragmentary and incomplete
nature of most existing chains of deduction this discovery comes with all the
overwhelming force of a revelation; like a palace emerging from the autumn mist
as the traveller ascends an Italian hillside, the stately storeys of the
mathematical edifice appear in their due order and proportion, with a new
perfection in every part.
Until
symbolic logic had acquired its present development, the principles upon which
mathematics depends were always supposed to be philosophical, and discoverable
only by the uncertain, unprogressive methods hitherto
employed by philosophers. So long as
this was thought, mathematics seemed to be not autonomous, but dependent upon a
study which had quite other methods than its own. Moreover, since the nature of the postulate
from which arithmetic, analysis, and geometry are to be deduced was wrapped in
all the traditional obscurities of metaphysical discussion, the edifice built
upon such dubious foundations began to be viewed as no better than a castle in
the air. In this respect, the discovery
that the true principles are as much a part of mathematics as any of their consequences
has very greatly increased the intellectual satisfaction to be obtained. This satisfaction ought not to be refused to
learners capable of enjoying it, for it is of a kind to increase our respect
for human powers and our knowledge of the beauties belonging to the abstract
world.
Philosophers
have commonly held that the laws of logic, which underlie mathematics, are laws
of thought, laws regulating the operations of our minds. By this opinion the true dignity of reason is
very greatly lowered: it ceases to be an investigation into the very heart and
immutable essence of all things actual and possible, becoming, instead, an
inquiry into something more or less human and subject to our limitations. The contemplation of what is non-human, the
discovery that our minds are capable of dealing with material not created by
them, above all, the realization that beauty belongs to the outer world as to
the inner, are the chief means of overcoming the terrible sense of impotence,
of weakness, of exile amid hostile powers, which is too apt to result from
acknowledging the all-but omnipotence of alien forces. To reconcile us, by the exhibition of its
awful beauty, to the reign of Fate - which is merely the literary personification
of these forces - is the task of tragedy.
But mathematics takes us still further from what is human, into the
region of absolute necessity, to which not only the actual world, but every
possible world, must conform; and even here it builds a habitation, or rather
finds a habitation eternally standing, where our ideals are fully satisfied and
our best hopes are not thwarted. It is
only when we thoroughly understand the entire independence of ourselves, which
belongs to this world that reason finds, that we can
adequately realize the profound importance of its beauty.
Not only is
mathematics independent of us and our thoughts, but in another sense we and the
whole universe of existing things are independent of mathematics. The apprehension of this purely ideal
character is indispensable, if we are to understand rightly the place of
mathematics as one among the arts. If
was formerly supposed that pure reason could decide, in some respects, as to
the nature of the actual world: geometry, at least, was thought to deal with
the space in which we live. But we now
know that pure mathematics can never pronounce upon questions of actual
existence: the world of reason, in a sense, controls the world of fact, but it
is not at any point creative of fact, and in the application of its results to
the world in time and space, its certainty and precision are lost among
approximations and working hypotheses.
The objects considered by mathematics have, in the past, been mainly of
a kind suggested by phenomena; but from such restrictions the abstract imagination
should be wholly free. A reciprocal
liberty must thus be accorded: reason cannot dictate to the world of facts, but
the facts cannot restrict reasons' privilege of dealing with whatever objects
its love of beauty may cause to seem worthy of consideration. Here, as elsewhere, we build up our own
ideals out of the fragments to be found in the world; and in the end it is hard
to say whether the result is creation or a discovery.
It is very
desirable, in instruction, not merely to persuade the student of the accuracy
if important theorems, but to persuade him in the way which itself has, of all
possible ways, the most beauty. The true
interest of a demonstration is not, as traditional modes of exposition suggest,
concentrated wholly in the result; where this does occur, it must be viewed as
a defect, to be remedied, if possible, by so generalizing the steps of the
proof that each becomes important in and for itself. An argument which serves only to prove a conclusion
is like a story subordinated to some moral which it is meant to teach: for
aesthetic perfection no part of the whole should be merely a means. A certain practical spirit, a desire for
rapid progress, for conquest of new realms, is responsible for the undue
emphasis upon results which prevails in mathematical instruction. The better way is to propose some theme for
consideration - in geometry, a figure having important properties; in analysis,
a function of which the study is illuminating, and so on. Whenever proofs depend upon some only of the
marks by which we define the object to be studied, these marks should be
isolated and investigated on their own account.
For it is a defect, in an argument, to employ more premises than the
conclusion demands: what mathematicians call elegance results from employing
only the essential principles in virtue of which the thesis is true. It is a merit in Euclid that he advances as
far as he is able to go without employing the axiom of parallels - not, as is
often said, because this axiom is inherently objectionable, but because, in
mathematics, every new axiom diminishes the generality of the resulting
theorems, and the greatest possible generality is before all things to be
sought.
Of the effects
of mathematics outside its own sphere more has been written than on the subject
of its own proper ideal. The effect upon
philosophy has, in the past, been most notable, but most varied; in the
seventeenth century, idealism and rationalism, in the eighteenth, materialism
and sensationalism, seemed equally its offspring. Of the effect which it is likely to have in
the future it would be very rash to say much; but in one respect a good result
appears probable. Against that kind of
scepticism which abandons the pursuit of ideals because the road is arduous and
the goal not certainly attained, mathematics, within its own sphere, is a
complete answer. Too often it is said
that there is no absolute truth, but only opinion and private judgement; that
each of us is conditioned, in his view of the world, by his own peculiarities,
his own taste and bias; that there is no external kingdom of truth to which, by
patience and discipline, we may at last obtain admittance, but only truth for
me, for you, for every separate person.
By this habit of mind one of the chief ends of human effort is denied,
and the supreme virtue of candour, of fearless acknowledgement of what is,
disappears from our moral vision. Of
such scepticism mathematics is a perpetual reproof; for its edifice of truths
stands unshakeable and inexpungable to all the
weapons of doubting cynicism.
The effects
of mathematics upon practical life, though they should not be regarded as the
motive of our studies, may be used to answer a doubt to which the solitary
student must always be liable. In a
world so full of evil and suffering, retirement into the cloister of
contemplation, to the enjoyment of delights which, however noble, must always
be for the few only, cannot but appear as a selfish refusal to share the burden
imposed upon others by accidents in which justice plays no part. Have any of us the right, we ask, to withdraw
from present evils, to leave our fellow-men unaided, while we live a life
which, though arduous and austere, is yet plainly good in its own nature? When these questions arise, the true answer
is, no doubt, that some must keep alive the sacred fire, some must preserve, in
every generation, the haunting vision which shadows forth the goal of so much
striving. But when, as must sometimes
occur, this answer seems too cold, when we are almost maddened by the spectacle
of sorrows to which we bring no help, then we may
reflect that indirectly the mathematician often does more for human happiness
than any of his more practically active contemporaries. The history of science abundantly proves that
a body of abstract propositions - even if, as in the case of conic sections, it
remains two thousand years without effect upon daily life - may yet, at any
moment, be used to cause a revolution in the habitual thoughts and occupations
of every citizen. The use of steam and
electricity - to take striking instances - is rendered possible only by
mathematics. In the results of abstract
thought the world possesses a capital of which the employment in enriching the
common round has no hitherto discoverable limits. Nor does experience give any means of
deciding what parts of mathematics will be found useful. Utility, therefore, can be only a consolation
in moments of discouragement, not a guide in directing our studies.
For the
health of the moral life, for ennobling the tone of an age or a nation, the austerer virtues have a strange power, exceeding the power
of those not informed and purified by thought.
Of these austerer virtues the love of truth is
the chief, and in mathematics, more than elsewhere, the love of truth may find
encouragement for waning faith. Every
great study is not only an end in itself, but also a means of creating and
sustaining a lofty habit of mind; and this purpose should be kept always in
view throughout the teaching and learning of mathematics.
CHAPTER V
Mathematics and the
Metaphysicians
THE nineteenth century, which prided itself upon the
invention of steam and evolution, might have derived a more legitimate title
the fame from the discovery of pure mathematics. This science, like most others, was baptized
long before it was born; and thus we find writers before the nineteenth century
alluding to what they called pure mathematics.
But if they had been asked what this subject was, they would only have
been able to say that it consisted of Arithmetic, Algebra, Geometry, and so
on. As to what these studies had in
common, and as to what distinguished them from applied mathematics, our
ancestors were completely in the dark.
Pure
mathematics was discovered by Boole, in a work which
he called the Laws of Thought (1854).
This work abounds in asseverations that it is not mathematical, the fact
being that Boole was too modest to suppose his book
the first ever written on mathematics.
He was also mistaken in supposing that he was dealing with the laws of
thought: the question how people actually think was quite irrelevant to him,
and if his book had really contained the laws of thought, it was curious that
no-one should ever have thought in such a way before. His book was in fact concerned with formal
logic, and this is the same thing as mathematics.
Pure
mathematics consists entirely of assertions to the effect that, if such and
such a proposition is true of anything, then such and such another
proposition is true of that thing. It is
essential not to discuss whether the first proposition is really true, and not
to mention what the anything is, of which it is supposed to be true. Both these points would apply to applied
mathematics. We start, in pure
mathematics, from certain rules of inference, by which we can infer that if
one proposition is true, then so is some other proposition. These rules of inference constitute the major
part of the principles of formal logic.
We then take any hypothesis that seems amusing, and deduce its
consequences. If our hypothesis
is about anything, and not about some one or more particular things,
then our deductions constitute mathematics.
Thus mathematics may be defined as the subject in which
we never know what we are talking about, nor whether what we are saying is
true. People who have been puzzled by
the beginnings of mathematics will, I hope, find comfort in this definition,
and will probably agree that it is accurate.
As one of
the chief triumphs of modern mathematics consists in having discovered what
mathematics really is, a few more words on the subject may not be amiss. It is common to start any branch of
mathematics - for instance, Geometry - with a certain number of primitive
ideas, supposed incapable of definition, and a certain number of primitive
propositions or axioms, supposed incapable of proof. Now the fact is that, though there are indefinables and indemonstrables
in every branch of applied mathematics, there are none in pure mathematics
except such as belong to general logic.
Logic, broadly speaking, is distinguished by the fact that its
propositions can be put into a form in which they apply to anything whatever. All pure mathematics - Arithmetic, Analysis,
and Geometry - is built up by combinations oft the primitive ideas of logic, and its propositions are deduced from the general
axioms of logic, such as the syllogism and the other rules of inference. And this is no longer a dream or an
aspiration. On the contrary, over the
greater and more difficult part of the domain of mathematics, it has been
already accomplished; in the few remaining cases, there is no special
difficulty, and it is now being rapidly achieved. Philosophers have disputed for ages whether
such deduction was possible; mathematicians have sat down and made the
deduction. For the philosophers there is
now nothing left but graceful acknowledgements.
The subject
of formal logic, which has thus at last shown itself
to be identical with mathematics, was, as everyone knows, invented by
Aristotle, and formed the chief study (other than theology) of the Middle
Ages. But Aristotle never got beyond the
syllogism, which is a very small part of the subject, and the schoolmen never
got beyond Aristotle. If any proof were
required of our superiority to the medieval doctors, it might be found in
this. Throughout the Middle
Ages, almost all the best intellects devoted themselves to formal logic,
whereas in the nineteenth century only an infinitesimal proportion of the
world's thought went into this subject.
Nevertheless, in each decade since 1850 more has been done to advance
the subject than in the whole period from Aristotle to Leibniz. People have discovered how to make reasoning
symbolic, as it is in Algebra, so that deductions are effected by mathematical
rules. They have discovered many rules
besides the syllogism, and a new branch of logic, called the Logic of
Relatives, [The subject is due in the main to Mr C. S. Peirce.] has been invented to
deal with topics that wholly surpassed the powers of the old logic, though they
form the chief contents of mathematics.
It is not
easy for the lay mind to realize the importance of symbolism in discussing the
foundations of mathematics, and the explanation may perhaps seem strangely
paradoxical. The fact is that symbolism
is useful because it makes things difficult.
(This is not true of the advanced parts of mathematics, but only of the
beginnings.) What we wish to know is, what can be deduced from what. Now, in the beginnings, everything is
self-evident; and it is very hard to see whether one self-evident proposition
follows from another or not. Obviousness
is always the enemy of correctness.
Hence we invent some new and difficult symbolism, in which nothing seems
obvious. Then we set up certain rules
for operating on the symbols, and the whole thing becomes mechanical. In this way we find out what must be taken as
premise and what can be demonstrated or defined. For instance, the whole of Arithmetic and
Algebra has been shown to require three indefinable notions and five
indemonstrable propositions. But without
a symbolism it would have been very hard to find this out. It is so obvious that two and two are four, that we can hardly make ourselves sufficiently
sceptical to doubt whether it can be proved.
And the same holds in other cases where self-evident things are to be
proved.
But the
proof of self-evident propositions may seem, to the uninitiated, a somewhat
frivolous occupation. To this we might
reply that it is often by no means self-evident that one obvious proposition
follows from another obvious proposition; so that we are really discovering new
truths when we prove what is evident by a method which is not evident. But a more interesting retort is, that since people have tried to prove obvious
propositions, they have found that many of them are false. Self-evidence is often a mere
will-o'-the-wisp, which is sure to lead us astray is we take it as our guide. For instance, nothing is plainer than that a
whole always has more terms than a part, or that a number is increased by
adding one to it. But these propositions
are now known to be usually false. Most
numbers are infinite, and if a number is infinite you may add ones to it as
long as you like without disturbing it in the least. One of the merits of a proof is that it
instils a certain doubt as to the result proved; and when what is obvious can
be proved in some cases, but not in others, it becomes possible to suppose that
in these other cases it is false.
The great
master of the art of formal reasoning, among the men of our own day, is an
Italian, Professor Peano, of the University of Turin.
[I ought to have added Frege, but his writings were
unknown to me when this article was written. - Note added in 1917.] He has reduced the greater part of mathematics (and
he or his followers will, in time, have reduced the whole) to strict symbolic
form, in which there are no words at all.
In the ordinary mathematical books, there are
no doubt fewer words than most readers would wish. Still, little phrases occur, such as therefore,
let us assume, consider, or hence it follows. All these, however, are a concession, and are
swept away by Professor Peano. For instance, if we wish to learn the whole
of Arithmetic, Algebra, the Calculus, and indeed all that is usually called
pure mathematics (except Geometry), we must start with a dictionary of three
words. One symbol stands for zero,
another for number, and a third for next after. What these ideas means, it is necessary to
know if you wish to become an arithmetician.
But after symbols have been invented for these three ideas, not another
word is required in the whole development.
All future symbols are symbolically explained by means of these
three. Even these three can be explained
by means of the notions of relation and class; but this requires
the Logic of Relations, which Professor Peano has
never taken up. It must be admitted that
what a mathematician has to know to begin with is not much. There are at most a dozen notions out of
which all the notions in all pure mathematics (including Geometry) are
compounded. Professor Peano, who is assisted by a very able school of young
Italian disciples, has shown how this may be done; and although the method
which he invented is capable of being carried a good deal further than he has
carried it, the honour of the pioneer must belong to him.
Two hundred
years ago, Leibniz foresaw the science which Peano
has perfected, and endeavoured to create it.
He was prevented from succeeding by respect for the authority of
Aristotle, whom he could not believe guilty of definite, formal fallacies; but
the subject which he desired to create now exists, in spite of the patronizing
contempt with which his schemes have been treated by all superior persons. From this 'Universal Characteristic', as he
called it, he hoped for a solution of all problems, and an end to all
disputes. 'If controversies were to
arise,' he says, 'there would be no more need of disputation between two
philosophers than between two accountants.
For it would suffice to take their pens in their
hands, to sit down to their desks, and to say to each other (with a friend as
witness, if they liked), "Let us calculate."' This optimism has now appeared to be somewhat
excessive; there still are problems whose solution is
doubtful, and disputes which calculation cannot decide. But over an enormous field of what was
formerly controversial, Leibniz's dream has become sober fact. In the whole philosophy of mathematics, which
used to be at least as full of doubt as any other part of philosophy, order and
certainty have replaced the confusion and hesitation which formerly
reigned. Philosophers, of course, have
not yet discovered this fact, and continue to write on such subjects in the old
way. But mathematicians, at least in
Italy, have now the power of treating the principles of mathematics in an exact
and masterly manner, by means of which the certainty of mathematics extends
also to mathematical philosophy. Hence
many of the topics which used to be placed among the great mysteries - for
example, the natures of infinity, of continuity, of space, time and motion -
are now no longer in any degree open to doubt or discussion. Those who wish to know the nature of these
things need only read the works of such men as Peano
or Georg Cantor; they will there find exact and
indubitable expositions of all these quondam mysteries.
In this
capricious world, nothing is more capricious than posthumous fame. One of the most notable examples of
posterity's lack of judgement is the Eleatic
Zeno. This man, who may be regarded as
the founder of the philosophy of infinity, appears in Plato's Parmenides in the
privileged position of instructor to Socrates.
He invented four arguments, all immeasurably subtle and profound, to
prove that motion is impossible, that Achilles can never overtake the tortoise,
and that an arrow in flight is really at rest.
After being refuted by Aristotle, and by every subsequent philosopher from
that day to our own, these arguments were reinstated, and made the basis of a
mathematical renaissance, by a German professor, who probably never dreamed of
any connection between himself and Zeno. Weierstrass,
[Professor of Mathematics in the University of Berlin. He died in 1897.] by
strictly banishing from mathematics the use of infinitesimals, has at last
shown that we live in an unchanging world, and that the arrow in its flight is
truly at rest. Zeno's only error lay in
inferring (if he did infer) that, because there is no such thing as a state of
change, therefore the world is in the same state at any one time as at any
other. This is a consequence which by no
means follows; and in this respect, the German mathematician is more
constructive than the ingenious Greek. Weierstrass has been able, by embodying his views in
mathematics, where familiarity with truth eliminates the vulgar prejudices of
common sense, to invest Zeno's paradoxes with the respectable air of
platitudes; and if the result is less delightful to the lover of reason than
Zeno's bold defiance, it is at any rate more calculated to appease the mass of
academic mankind.
Zeno was
concerned, as a matter of fact, with three problems, each presented by motion,
but each more abstract than motion, and capable of a purely arithmetical
treatment. These are the problems of the
infinitesimal, the infinite, and continuity.
To state clearly the difficulties involved, was to accomplish perhaps
the hardest part of the philosopher's task.
This was done by Zeno. From him
to our own day, the finest intellects of each generation in turn attacked the
problems, but achieved, broadly speaking, nothing. In our own time, however, three men - Weierstrass, Dedekind, and Cantor
- have not merely advanced the three problems, but have completely solved
them. The solutions, for those
acquainted with mathematics, are so clear as to leave no longer the slightest
doubt or difficulty. This achievement is
probably the greatest of which our age has to boast; and I know of no age
(except perhaps the golden age of Greece) which has a more convincing proof to
offer of the transcendent genius of its great men. Of the three problems, that
of the infinitesimal was solved by Weierstrass; the
solution of the other two was begun by Dedekind, and
definitively accomplished by Cantor.
The
infinitesimal played formerly a great part in mathematics. It was introduced by the Greeks, who regarded
a circle as differing infinitesimally from a polygon with a very large number
of very small equal sides. It gradually
grew in importance, until, when Leibniz invented the Infinitesimal Calculus, it seemed to become the fundamental notion of all
higher mathematics. Carlyle tells, in
his Friederick the Great, how Leibniz
used to discourse to Queen Sophia Charlotte of Prussia concerning the
infinitely little, and how she would reply that on that subject she needed no
instruction - the behaviour of courtiers had made her thoroughly familiar with
it. But philosophers and mathematicians
- who for the most part had less acquaintance with courts - continued to
discuss this topic, though without making any advance. The Calculus required continuity, and
continuity was supposed to require the infinitely little; but nobody could
discover what the infinitely little might be.
It was plainly not quite zero, because a sufficiently large number of
infinitesimals, added together, were seen to make up a finite whole. But nobody could point out any fraction which
was not zero, and yet not finite. Thus there
was a deadlock. But at last Weierstrass discovered that the infinitesimal was not
needed at all, and that everything could be accomplished without it. Thus there was no longer any need to suppose
that there was such a thing. Nowadays,
therefore, mathematicians are more dignified than Leibniz: instead of talking
about the infinitely small, they talk about the infinitely great - a subject
which, however appropriate to monarchs, seems, unfortunately, to interest them
even less than the infinitely little interested the monarchs to whom Leibniz
discoursed.
The
banishment of the infinitesimal has all sorts of odd consequences, to which one
has to become gradually accustomed. For
example, there is no such thing as the next moment. The interval between one moment and the next
would have to be infinitesimal, since, if we take two moments with a finite
interval between them, there are always other moments in the interval. Thus if there are to be no infinitesimals, no
two moments are quite consecutive, but there are always other moments between
any two. Hence there must be an infinite
number of moments between any two; because if there were a finite number one
would be nearest the first of the two moments, and
therefore next to it. This might be
thought to be a difficulty; but, as a matter of fact, it is here that the
philosophy of the infinite comes in, and makes all straight.
The same
sort of thing happens in space. If any
piece of matter be cut in two, and then each part be halved, and so on, the
bits will become smaller and smaller, and can theoretically be made as small as
we please. However small they may be,
they can still be cut up and made smaller still. But they will always have some finite
size, however small they may be. We
never reach the infinitesimal in this way, and no finite number of divisions
will bring us to points. Nevertheless
there are points, only these are not to be reached by successive
divisions. Here again, the philosophy of
the infinite shows us how this is possible, and why points are not
infinitesimal lengths.
As regards
motion and change, we get similarly curious results. People used to think that when a thing
changes, it must be in a state of change, and that when a thing moves, it is in
a state of motion. This is now known to
be a mistake. When a body moves, all
that can be said is that it is in one place at one time and in another at
another. We must not say that it will be
in a neighbouring place at the next instant, since there is no next
instant. Philosophers often tell us that
when a body is in motion, it changes its position within the instant. To this view Zeno long ago made the fatal
retort that every body always is where it is; but a retort so simply and brief
was not of the kind to which philosophers are accustomed to give weight, and
they have continued down to our own day to repeat the same phrases which roused
the Eleatic's destructive ardour. It was only recently that it became possible
to explain motion in detail in accordance with Zeno's platitude, and in
opposition to the philosopher's paradox.
We may now at last indulge the comfortable belief that a body in motion
is just as truly where it is as a body at rest.
Motion consists merely in the fact that bodies are sometimes in one
place and sometimes in another, and that they are at intermediate places at
intermediate times. Only those who have
waded through the quagmire of philosophic speculation on this subject can
realize what a liberation from antique prejudices is
involved in this simple and straightforward commonplace.
The
philosophy of the infinitesimal, as we have just seen, is mainly negative. People used to believe in it, and now they
have found out their mistake. The
philosophy of the infinite, on the other hand, is wholly positive. It was formerly supposed that infinite numbers, and the mathematical infinite generally, were
self-contradictory. But as it was
obvious that there were infinities - for example, the number of numbers - the
contradictions of infinity seemed unavoidable, and philosophy seemed to have
wandered into a cul-de-sac. This
difficulty led to Kant's antinomies, and hence, more or less indirectly, to
much of Hegel's dialectic method. Almost all current philosophy is upset by the
fact (of which very few philosophers are as yet aware) that all the ancient and
respectable contradictions in the notion of the infinite have been once for all
disposed of. The method by which this
has been done is most interesting and instructive. In the first place, though people had talked
glibly about infinity ever since the beginnings of Greek thought, nobody had
ever thought of asking, What is infinity? If any philosopher had been asked for a
definition of infinity, he might have produced some unintelligible rigmarole,
but he would certainly not have been able to give a definition that had any
meaning at all. Twenty years ago,
roughly speaking, Dedekind and Cantor asked this
question, and, what is more remarkable, they answered it. They found, that is to say, a perfectly
precise definition of an infinite number or an infinite collection of things.
This was the first and perhaps the greatest step. It then remained to examine the supposed
contradictions in this notion. Here
Cantor proceeded in the only proper way.
He took pairs of contradictory propositions, in which both sides of the
contradiction would be usually regarded as demonstrable, and he strictly
examined the supposed proofs. He found
that all proofs adverse to infinity involved a certain principle, at first
sight obviously true, but destructive, in its consequences, of almost all
mathematics. The proofs favourable to
infinity, on the other hand, involved no principle that had evil
consequences. It thus appeared that
common sense had allowed itself to be taken in by a specious maxim, and that,
when once this maxim was rejected, all went well.
The maxim
in question is, that if one collection is part of another, the one which is a
part has fewer terms than the one of which it is a part. This maxim is true of finite numbers. For example, Englishmen are only some among
Europeans, and there are fewer Englishmen than Europeans. But when we come to infinite numbers, this is
no longer true. This breakdown of the
maxim gives us the precise definition of infinity. A collection of terms is infinite when it
contains as parts other collections which have just as many terms as it
has. If you can take away some of the
terms of a collection, without diminishing the number of terms, then there are
an infinite number of terms in the collection.
For example, there are just as many even numbers as there are numbers altogether, since every number can be
doubled. This may be seen by putting odd
and even numbers together in one row and even numbers alone in a row below:-
1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ad infinitum.
2, 4, 6, 8, 10, ad infinitum.
There are obviously just as many numbers in the row
below as in the row above, because there is one below for each row above. This property, which was formerly thought to
be a contradiction, is now transformed into a harmless definition of infinity,
and shows, in the above case, that the number of finite numbers is infinite.
But the
uninitiated may wonder how it is possible to deal with a number which cannot be
counted. It is impossible to count up all
the numbers, one by one, because, however many we may count, there are always
more to follow. The fact is that
counting is a very vulgar and elementary way of finding out how many terms are
in a collection. And in any case,
counting gives us what mathematicians call the ordinal numbers of our
terms; that is to say, it arranges our terms in an order or series, and its
result tells us what type of series results from this arrangement. In other words, it is impossible to count
things without counting some first and others afterwards, so that counting
always has to do with order. Now when
there are only a finite number of terms, we can count them in any order we
like; but when there are an infinite number, what corresponds to counting will
give us quite different results according to the way in which we carry out the
operation. Thus the ordinal number,
which results from what, in a general sense, may be called counting, depends
not only upon how many terms we have, but also (where the number of terms is
infinite) upon the way in which the terms are arranged.
The
fundamental infinite numbers are not ordinal, but are what is called cardinal. They are not obtained by putting our terms in
order and counting them, but by a different method, which tells us, to begin
with, whether two collections have the same number of terms, or, if not, which
is the greater. [Although some infinite numbers are greater than some
others, it cannot be proved that of any two infinite numbers one must be the
greater. - Note added in 1917.] It does not tell
us, in the way in which counting does, what number of terms a collection
has; but if we define a number as the number of terms in such and such a
collection, then this method enables us to discover whether some other
collection that may be mentioned has more or fewer terms. An illustration will show how this is
done. If there existed some country in
which, for one reason or another, it was impossible to take a census, but in
which it was known that every man had a wife and every woman a husband, then
(provided polygamy was not a national institution) we should know, without
counting, that there were exactly as many men as there were women in that
country, neither more nor less. This
method can be applied generally. If
there is some relation which, like marriage, connects
the things in one collection each with one of the things in another collection,
and vice versa, then the two collections have the same number of terms. This was the way in which we found that there
are as many even numbers as there are numbers.
Every number can be doubled, and every even number can be halved, and
each process gives just one number corresponding to the one that is doubled or
halved. And in this way we can find any
number of collections each of which has just as many terms as there are finite
numbers. If every term of a collection
can be hooked on to a number, and all the finite numbers are used once, and
only once, in the process, then our collection must have just as many terms as
there are finite numbers. This is the
general method by which the numbers of infinite collections are defined.
But it must not be supposed that all infinite numbers are equal. On the contrary, there are infinitely more infinite numbers than finite ones. There are more ways of arranging the finite numbers in different types of series than there are finite numbers. There are probably more points in space and more moments in time than there are finite numbers. There are exactly as many fractions as whole numbers, although there are an infinite number of fractions between any two whole numbers. But there are more irrational numbers than there are whole numbers or fractions. There are probably exactly as many points in space as there are irrational numbers, and exactly as many points on a line a millionth of an inch long as in the whole of infinite space. There is a greatest of all infinite numbers, which is the number of things altogether, of every sort and kind. It is obvious that there cannot be a greater number than this, because, if everything has been taken, there is nothing left to add. Cantor has a proof that there is no greatest number, and if this proof were valid, the contradictions of infinity would reappear in a sublimated form. But in this one point, the master has been guilty of a very subtle fallacy, which I hope to explain in some future work. [Cantor was not guilty of a fallacy on this point. His proof that there is no greatest number is valid. The solution of the puzzle is complicated and depends upon the theory of types, which is explained in Principia Mathematica, Vol. 1 (Camb. Univ. Press, 1910). - Note added in 1917.]
We can now
understand why Zeno believed that Achilles cannot overtake the tortoise and why
as a matter of fact he can overtake it.
We shall see that all the people who disagreed with Zeno had no right to
do so, because they all accepted premises from which his conclusion
followed. The argument is this: Let
Achilles and the tortoise start along a road at the same time, the tortoise (as
is only fair) being allowed a handicap.
Let Achilles go twice as fast as the tortoise, or ten times or a hundred
times as fast. Then he will never reach
the tortoise. For at every moment the
tortoise is somewhere and Achilles is somewhere; and neither is ever twice in
the same place while the race is going on.
Thus the tortoise goes to just as many places as Achilles does, because
each is in one place at one moment, and in another at
any other moment. But if Achilles were
to catch up with the tortoise, the places where the tortoise would have been
would be only part of the places where the Achilles would have been. Here, we must suppose, Zeno appealed to the
maxim that the whole has more terms than the part. [This must not be
regarded as a historically correct account of what Zeno actually had in
mind. It is a new argument for his
conclusion, not the argument which influenced him. On this point, see e.g. C.D. Broad, 'Note on
Achilles and the Tortoise', Mind, N.S. Vol. XXII, pp. 318-19. Much valuable work on the interpretation of
Zeno has been done since this article was written. - Note added in 1917.] Thus is
Achilles were to overtake the tortoise, he would have been in more places than
the tortoise; but we saw that he must, in any period, be in exactly as many
places as the tortoise. Hence we infer
that he can never catch the tortoise.
This argument is strictly correct, if we allow the axiom that the whole
has more terms than the part. As the
conclusion is absurd, the axiom must be rejected, and then all goes well. But there is no good word to be said for the
philosophers of the past two thousand years and more, who have all allowed the
axiom and denied the conclusion.
The
retention of this axiom leads to absolute contradictions, while its rejection
leads only to oddities. Some of these
oddities, it must be confessed, are very odd.
One of them, which I call the paradox of Tristram
Shandy, is the converse of the Achilles, and shows
that the tortoise, if you give him time, will go just as far as Achilles. Tristram Shandy, as we know, employed two years in chronicling the
first two days of his life, and lamented that, at this rate, material would
accumulate faster than he could deal with it, so that, as years went by, he
would be farther and farther from the end of his history. Now I maintain that, if he had lived for
ever, and had not wearied of his task, then, even if his life had continued as
eventfully as it began, no part of his biography would have remained
unwritten. For consider: the hundredth
day will be described in the hundredth year, the thousandth in the thousandth
year, and so on. Whatever day we may
choose as so far on that he cannot hope to reach it, that day will be described
in the corresponding year. Thus any day
that may be mentioned will be written up sooner or later, and therefore no part
of the biography will remain permanently unwritten. This paradoxical but perfectly true
proposition depends upon the fact that the number of days in all time is no
greater than the number of years.
Thus on the
subject of infinity it is impossible to avoid conclusions which at first sight
appear paradoxical, and this is the reason why so many philosophers have
supposed that there were inherent contradictions in the infinite. But a little practice enables one to grasp
the true principles of Cantor's doctrine, and to acquire new and better
instincts as tot he true and the false.
The oddities then become no odder than the people at the antipodes, who
used to be thought impossible because they would find it so inconvenient to
stand on their heads.
The
solution of the problems concerning infinity has enabled Cantor to solve also
the problems of continuity. Of this, as
of infinity, he has given a perfectly precise definition, and has shown that there
are no contradictions in the notion so defined.
But this subject is so technical that it is impossible to give any
account of it here.
The notion
of continuity depends upon that of order, since continuity is merely a
particular type of order. Mathematics
has, in modern times, brought order into greater and greater prominence. In former days, it was supposed (and
philosophers are still apt to suppose) that quantity was the fundamental notion
of mathematics. But nowadays, quantity
is banished altogether, except from one little corner of Geometry, while order
more and more reigns supreme. The
investigation of different kinds of series and their relations is now a very
large part of mathematics, and it has been found that this investigation can be
conducted without any reference to quantity, and, for the most part, without
any reference to number. All types of
series are capable of formal definition, and their properties can be deduced
from the principles of symbolic logic by means of the Algebra of Relatives. The notion of a limit, which is fundamental
in the greater part of higher mathematics, used to be defined by means of
quantity, as a term to which the terms of some series approximate as nearly as
we please. But nowadays the limit is
defined quite differently, and the series which it limits may not approximate
to it at all. This improvement also is
due to Cantor, and it is one which has revolutionized mathematics. Only order is now relevant to limits. Thus, for instance, the smallest of the infinite
integers is the limit of the finite integers, though all finite integers are at
an infinite distance from it. The study
of different types of series is a general subject of which the study of ordinal
numbers (mentioned above) is a special and very interesting branch. But the unavoidable technicalities of this
subject render it impossible to explain to any but professed mathematicians.
Geometry,
like Arithmetic, has been subsumed, in recent times, under the general study of
order. It was formerly supposed that
Geometry was the study of the nature of the space in which we live, and
accordingly it was urged, by those who held that what exists can only be known
empirically, that Geometry should really be regarded as belonging to applied
mathematics. But it has gradually
appeared, by the increase of non-Euclidean systems, that Geometry throws no
more light upon the nature of space than Arithmetic throws upon the population
of the United States. Geometry is a whole
collection of deductive sciences based on a corresponding collection of sets of
axioms. One set of axioms is Euclid's;
other equally good sets of axioms lead to other results. Whether Euclid's axioms are true, is a
question as to which the pure mathematician is indifferent; and, what is more,
it is a question which it is theoretically impossible to answer with certainty
in the affirmative. It might possibly be
shown, by very careful measurements, that Euclid's axioms are false; but no
measurements could ever assure us (owing to the errors of observation) that
they are exactly true. Thus the geometer
leaves to the man of science to decide, as best he may, what axioms are most
nearly true in the actual world. The geometer
takes any set of axioms that seem interesting, and deduces their consequences. What defines Geometry, in this sense, is that
the axioms must give rise to a series of more than one dimension. And it is thus that Geometry becomes a
department in the study of order.
In
Geometry, as in other parts of mathematics, Peano and
his disciples have done work of the very greatest merit as regards
principles. Formerly, it was held by
philosophers and mathematicians alike that the proofs in Geometry depended on
the figure; nowadays, this is known to be false. In the best books there are no figures at
all. The reasoning proceeds by the
strict rules of formal logic from a set of axioms laid
down to begin with. If a figure is used,
all sorts of things seem obviously to follow, which no formal reasoning can
prove from the explicit axioms, and which, as a matter of fact, are only
accepted because they are obvious. By
banishing the figure, it becomes possible to discover all the axioms
that are needed; and in this way all sorts of possibilities, which would have
otherwise remained undetected, are brought to light.
One great
advance, from the point of view of correctness, has been made by introducing
points as they are required, and not starting, as was formerly done, by
assuming the whole of space. This method
is due partly to Peano, partly to another Italian
named Fano. To
those unaccustomed to it, it has an air of somewhat wilful pedantry. In this way, we begin with the following
axioms: (1) There is a class of entities called points. (2) There is at least one point. (3) If a be a
point, there is at least one other point besides a. Then we bring in the straight line joining
two points, and begin again with (4), namely, on the straight line joining a and b, there is at least one other point
besides a and b. (5) There
is at least one point not on the line ab. And so we go on, till we have the means of
obtaining as many points as we require.
But the word space, as Peano humorously
remarks, is one for which Geometry has no use at all.
The rigid
methods employed by modern geometers have deposed Euclid from his pinnacle of
correctness. It was thought, until
recent times, that, as Sir Henry Savile remarked in
1621, there were only two blemishes in Euclid, the theory of parallels and the
theory of proportion. It is now known
that these are almost the only points in which Euclid is free from
blemish. Countless errors are involved
in his first eight propositions. That is
to say, not only is it doubtful whether his axioms are true, which is a
comparatively trivial matter, but it is certain that his propositions do not
follow from the axioms which he enunciates.
A vastly greater number of axioms, which Euclid unconsciously employs,
are required for the proof of his propositions.
Even in the first proposition of all, where he constructs an equilateral
triangle on a given base, he uses two circles which are assumed to
intersect. But no explicit axiom assures
us that they do so, and in some kinds of spaces they do not always intersect. It is quite doubtful whether one space
belongs to one of these kinds or not.
Thus Euclid fails entirely to prove his point in the very first
proposition. As he is certainly not an
easy author, and is terribly long-winded, he has no longer any but an
historical interest. Under these
circumstances, it is nothing less than a scandal that he should still be taught
to boys in England. [Since the above was written, he has ceased to be
used as a textbook. But I fear many of
the books now used are so bad that the change is no great improvement. - Note
added in 1917.] A book should have either
intelligibility or correctness; to combine the two is impossible, but to lack
both is to be unworthy of such a place as Euclid has occupied in education.
The most
remarkable result of modern methods in mathematics is the importance of
symbolic logic and of rigid formalism.
Mathematicians, under the influence of Weierstrass,
have shown in modern times a care for accuracy, and an aversion to slipshod
reasoning, such as had not been known among them previously since the time of
the Greeks. The great inventions of the
seventeenth century - Analytical Geometry and the Infinitesimal Calculus - were
so fruitful in new results that mathematicians had neither time nor inclination
to examine their foundations.
Philosophers, who should have taken up the task, had too little
mathematical ability to invent the new branches of mathematics which have now
been found necessary for any adequate discussion. Thus mathematicians were only awakened from
their 'dogmatic slumbers' when Weierstrass and his
followers showed that many of their most cherished propositions are in general
false. Macaulay, contrasting the
certainty of mathematics with the uncertainty of philosophy, asks who ever
heard of a reaction against
The proof that all pure mathematics, including Geometry, is nothing but formal logic, is a fatal blow to the Kantian philosophy. Kant, rightly perceiving that Euclid's propositions could not be deduced from Euclid's axioms without the help of the figures, invented a theory of knowledge to account for this fact; and it accounted so successfully that, when the fact is shown to be a mere defect in Euclid, and not a result of the nature of geometrical reasoning, Kant's theory also has to be abandoned. The whole doctrine of a priori intuitions, by which Kant explained the possibility of pure mathematics, is wholly inapplicable to mathematics in its present form. The Aristotelian doctrines of the schoolmen come nearer in spirit to the doctrines which modern mathematics inspire; but the schoolmen were hampered by the fact that their formal logic was very defective, and that the philosophical logic based upon the syllogism showed a corresponding narrowness. What is now required is to give the greatest possible development to mathematical logic, to allow to the full the importance of relations, and then to found upon this secure basis a new philosophical logic, which may hope to borrow some of the exactitude and certainty of its mathematical foundation. If this can be successfully accomplished, there is every reason to hope that the near future will be as great an epoch in pure philosophy as the immediate past has been in the principles of mathematics. Great triumphs inspire great hopes; and pure thought may achieve, within our generation, such results as will place our time, in this respect, on a level with the greatest age of Greece. [The greatest age of Greece was brought to an end by the Peloponnesian War. - Note added in 1917.]
CHAPTER VI
On Scientific Method in Philosophy
[The Herbert Spencer
lecture, Oxford, 1914.]
WHEN we try to ascertain the motives which have led
men to the investigation of philosophical questions, we find that, broadly speaking,
they can be divided into two groups, often antagonistic, and leading to very
divergent systems. These two groups of
motives are, on the one hand, those derived from religion and ethics, and, on
the other hand, those derived from science.
Plato, Spinoza, and Hegel may be taken as typical of the philosophers
who interests are mainly religious and ethical, while Leibniz, Locke, and Hume
may be taken as representatives of the scientific wing. In Aristotle, Descartes, Berkeley, and Kant
we find both groups of motives strongly present.
Herbert
Spencer, in whose honour we are assembled today, would naturally be classed
among scientific philosophers: it was mainly from science that he drew his
data, his formulation of problems, and his conception of method. But his strong religious sense in obvious in
much of his writing, and his ethical preoccupations are what make him value the
conception of evolution - that conception in which, as a whole generation has
believed, science and morals are to be united in fruitful and indissoluble
marriage.
It is my
belief that the ethical and religious motives, in spite of the splendidly
imaginative systems to which they have given rise, have been on the whole a
hindrance to the progress of philosophy, and ought now to be consciously thrust
aside by those who wish to discover philosophical truth. Science, originally, was entangled in similar
motives, and was thereby hindered in its advances. It is, I maintain, from science, rather than
from ethics and religion, that philosophy should draw its inspiration.
But there
are two different ways in which a philosophy may seek to base itself upon
science. It may emphasize the most
general results of science, and seek to give even greater generality and
unity to these results. Or it may study
the methods of science, and seek to apply these methods, with the
necessary adaptations, to its own peculiar province. Much philosophy inspired by science has gone
astray through preoccupation with the results momentarily supposed to
have been achieved. It is not results,
but methods, that can be transferred with profit from the sphere of the
special sciences to the sphere of philosophy.
What I wish to bring to your notice is the possibility and importance of
applying to philosophical problems certain broad principles of method which
have been found successful in the study of scientific questions.
The
opposition between a philosophy guided by scientific method and a philosophy
dominated by religious and ethical ideas may be illustrated by two notions
which are very prevalent in the works of philosophers, namely the notion of the
universe, and the notion of good and evil. A philosopher is expected to tell us
something about the nature of the universe as a whole, and to give grounds for
either optimism or pessimism. Both these
expectations seem to me mistaken. I
believe the conception of 'the universe' to be, as its etymology indicates, a
mere relic of pre-Copernican astronomy: and I believe the question of optimism
and pessimism to be one which the philosopher will regard as outside his scope,
except, possibly, to the extent of maintaining that it is insoluble.
In the days
before Copernicus, the conception of the 'universe' was defensible on
scientific grounds: the diurnal revolution of the heavenly bodies bound them
together as all parts of one system, of which the earth was the centre. Round this apparent scientific fact, many
human desires rallied: the wish to believe Man important in the scheme of
things, the theoretical desire for a comprehensive understanding of the Whole,
the hope that the course of nature might be guided by some sympathy with our
wishes. In this way, an ethically
inspired system of metaphysics grew up, whose anthropocentrism was apparently
warranted by the geocentrism of astronomy. When Copernicus swept away the astronomical
basis of this system of thought, it had grown so familiar, and had associated
itself so intimately with men's aspirations, that it survived with scarcely diminished
force - survived even Kant's 'Copernican revolution', and is still now the
unconscious premise of most metaphysical systems.
The oneness
of the world is an almost undiscussed postulate of
most metaphysics. 'Reality is not merely
one and self-consistent, but is a system of reciprocally determinate parts'
[Bosanquet, Logic, ii. p. 211.] - such a statement would pass almost unnoticed as a
mere truism. Yet I believe that it
embodies a failure to effect thoroughly the 'Copernican revolution', and that
the apparent oneness of the world is merely the oneness of what is seen by a
single spectator or apprehended by a single mind. The Critical Philosophy, although it intended
to emphasize the subjective element in many apparent characteristics of the
world, yet, by regarding the world in itself as unknowable, so concentrated
attention upon the subjective representation that its subjectivity was soon
forgotten. Having recognized the
categories as the work of the mind, it was paralysed by its own recognition,
and abandoned in despair the attempt to undo the work of subjective
falsification. In part, no doubt, its
despair was well founded, but not, I think, in any absolute or ultimate
sense. Still less was it a ground for rejoicing, or for supposing that the nescience
to which it ought to have given rise could be legitimately exchanged for a
metaphysical dogmatism.
I
As regards
our present question, namely, the question of the unity of the world, the right
method, as I think, has been indicated by William James. [Some
Problems of Philosophy, p. 124.] 'Let us now
turn our backs upon ineffable or unintelligible ways of accounting for the
world's oneness, and inquire whether, instead of being a principle, the
"oneness" affirmed may not merely be a name like
"substance", descriptive of the fact that certain specific and
verifiable connections are found among the parts of the experiential
flux.... We can easily conceive of things that shall have no connection
whatever with each other. We may assume
them to inhabit different times and spaces, as the dreams of different persons
do even now. They may be so unlike and
incommensurable, and so inert towards one another, as never to jostle or
interfere. Even now there may actually
be whole universes so disparate from ours that we who know ours have no means
of perceiving that they exist. We
conceive their diversity, however; and by that fact the whole lot of them form
what is known in logic as "a universe of discourse". To form a universe of discourse argues, as
this example shows, no further kind of connection. The importance attached by certain monistic
writers to the fact that any chaos may become a universe by merely being named,
is to me incomprehensible.' We are thus
left with two kinds of unity in the experienced world; the one what we may call
the epistemological unity, due merely to the fact that my experienced world is
what one experience selects from the sum total of existence; the other
that tentative and partial unity exhibited in the prevalence of scientific laws
in those portions of the world which science has hitherto mastered. Now a generalization based upon either of
these kinds of unity would be fallacious.
That the things which we experience have the common property of being
experienced by us is a truism from which obviously nothing of importance can be
deducible: it is clearly fallacious to draw from the fact that whatever we
experience is experienced the conclusion that therefore everything must be
experienced. The generalization of the
second kind of unity, namely, that derived from scientific
laws, would be equally fallacious, though the fallacy is a trifle less
elementary. In order to explain it let
us consider for a moment what is called the reign of law. People often speak as though it were a
remarkable fact that the physical world is subject to invariable laws. In fact, however, it is not easy to see how
such a world could fail to obey general laws.
Taking any arbitrary set of points in space, there is a function of the
time corresponding to these points, i.e. expressing the motion of a particle
which traverses these points: this function may be regarded as a general law to
which the behaviour of such a particle is subject. Taking all such functions for all the
particles in the universe, there will be theoretically some one formula
embracing them all, and this formula may be regarded as the single and supreme
law of the spatio-temporal world. Thus what is surprising in physics is not the
existence of general laws, but their extreme simplicity. It is not the uniformity of nature that
should surprise us, for, by sufficient analytic ingenuity, any conceivable
course of nature might be shown to exhibit uniformity. What should surprise us is the fact that the
uniformity is simple enough for us to be able to discover it. But it is just this characteristic of
simplicity in the laws of nature hitherto discovered which it would be
fallacious to generalize, for it is obvious that simplicity has been a part
cause of their discovery, and can, therefore, give no ground for the supposition
that other undiscovered laws are equally simple.
The
fallacies to which these two kinds of unity have given rise suggest a caution
as regards all use in philosophy of general results that science is
supposed to have achieved. In the first
place, in generalizing these results beyond past experience, it is necessary to
examine very carefully whether there is not some reason making it more probable
that these results should hold of all that has been experienced than that they
should hold of things universally. The
sum total of what is experienced by mankind is a selection from the sum total
of what exists, and any general character exhibited by this selection may be
due to the manner of selecting rather than due to the general character of that
from which experience selects. In the
second place, the most general results of science are the least certain and the
most liable to be upset by subsequent research.
In utilizing these results as the basis of philosophy, we sacrifice the
most valuable and remarkable characteristic of scientific method, namely, that,
although almost everything in science is found sooner or later to require some
correction, yet this correction is almost always such as to leave untouched, or
only slightly modified, the greater part of the results which have been deduced
from the premise subsequently discovered to be faulty. The prudent man of science acquires a certain
instinct as to the kind of uses which may be made of present scientific beliefs
without incurring the danger of complete and utter refutation from the
modifications likely to be introduced by subsequent discoveries. Unfortunately the use of scientific
generalizations of a sweeping kind as the basis of philosophy is just that kind
of use which an instinct of scientific caution would avoid, since, as a rule,
it would only lead to true results if the generalization upon which it is based
stood in no need of correction.
We may
illustrate these general considerations by means of two examples, namely, the
conservation of energy and the principle of evolution.
(1) Let us begin with the conservation of energy, or, as Herbert Spencer used to call it, the persistence of force. He says: [First Principles (1862), Part II, beginning of chap. viii.]
'Before
taking a first step in the rational interpretation of Evolution, it is needful
to recognize, not only the facts that Matter is indestructible and Motion
continuous, but also the fact that Force persists. An attempt to assign the causes of
Evolution would manifestly be absurd if that agency to which the metamorphosis
in general and in detail is due, could either come into existence or cease to
exist. The succession of phenomena would
in such case be altogether arbitrary, and deductive
Science impossible.'
This
paragraph illustrates the kind of way in which the philosopher is tempted to
give an air of absoluteness and necessity to empirical generalizations, of
which only the approximate truth in the regions hitherto investigated can be
guaranteed by the unaided methods of science.
It is very often said that the persistence of something or other is a
necessary presupposition of all scientific investigation, and this
presupposition is then thought to be exemplified in some quantity which physics
declares to be constant. There are here,
as it seems to me, three distinct errors.
First, the detailed scientific investigation of nature does not presuppose
any such general laws as its results are found to verify. Apart from particular observations, science
need presuppose nothing except the general principles of logic, and these
principles are not laws of nature, for they are merely hypothetical, and apply
not only to the actual world but to whatever is possible. The second error consists in the
identification of a constant quality with a persistent entity. Energy is a certain function of a physical
system, but is not a thing or substance persisting throughout the changes of
the system. The same is true of mass, in
spite of the fact that mass has often been defined as quantity of matter. The whole conception, of quantity, involving,
as it does, numerical measurement based largely upon conventions, is far more
artificial, far more an embodiment of mathematical convenience, than is
commonly believed by those who philosophize on physics. Thus even if (which I cannot for a moment
admit) the persistence of some entity were among the necessary postulates of
science, it would be a sheer error to infer from this the constancy of any
physical quantity, or the a priori necessity of any such constancy which
may be empirically discovered. In the
third place, it has become more and more evident with the progress of physics
that large generalizations, such as the conservation of energy or mass, are far
from certain and are very likely only approximate. Mass, which used to be regarded as the most
indubitable of physical quantities, is now generally believed to vary according
to velocity, and to be, in fact, a vector quantity which at a given moment is different
in different directions. The detailed
conclusions deduced from the supposed constancy of mass for such motions as
used to be studied in physics will remain very nearly exact, and therefore over
the field of the older investigations very little modification of the older
results is required. Butt as soon as
such a principle as the conservation of mass or of energy is erected into a
universal a priori law, the slightest failure in absolute exactness is
fatal, and the whole philosophic structure raised upon this foundation is
necessarily ruined. The prudent
philosopher, therefore, though he may with advantage study the methods of
physics, will be very chary of basing anything upon what happen at the moment
to be the most general results apparently obtained by those methods.
(2) The philosophy of evolution, which was to be
our second example, illustrates the same tendency to hasty generalization, and
also another sort, namely, the undue preoccupation with ethical notions. There are two kinds of evolutionist philosophy,
of which both Hegel and Spencer represent the older and less radical kind,
while Pragmatism and Bergson represent the more
modern and revolutionary variety. But
both these sorts of evolutionism have in common the emphasis on progress,
that is, upon a continual change from the worse to the better, or from the
simpler to the more complex. It would be
unfair to attribute to Hegel any scientific motive or foundation,
but all the other evolutionists, including Hegel's modern disciples, have
derived their impetus very largely from the history of biological
development. To a philosophy which
derives a law of universal progress from this history there are two
objections. First, that this history
itself is concerned with a very small selection of facts confined to an
infinitesimal fragment of space and time, and even on scientific grounds
probably not an average sample of events in the world at large. For we know that decay as well as growth is a
normal occurrence in the world. An
extra-terrestrial philosopher, who had watched a single youth up to the age of
twenty-one and had never come across any other human being, might conclude that
it is the nature of human beings to grow continually taller and wiser in an
indefinite progress towards perfection; and this generalization would be just
as well founded as the generalization which evolutionists base upon the
previous history of this planet. Apart,
however, from this scientific objection to evolutionism, there is another,
derived from the undue admixture of ethical notions in the very idea of
progress from which evolutionism derives its charm. Organic life, we are told, has developed
gradually from the protozoon to the philosopher, and this development, we are
assured, is indubitably an advance.
Unfortunately it is the philosopher, not the protozoon, who gives us
this assurance, and we can have no security that the impartial outsider would
agree with the philosopher's self-complacent assumption. This point has been illustrated by the
philosopher Chuang Tzu in the following instructive
anecdote:
'The Grand
Augur, in his ceremonial robes, approached the shambles and thus addressed the
pigs: "How can you object to die? I
shall fatten you for three months. I
shall discipline myself for ten days and fast for three. I shall strew fine grass, and place you
bodily upon a carved sacrificial dish.
Does not this satisfy you?"
Then,
speaking from the pigs' point of view, he continued: "It is better,
perhaps, after all, to live on bran and escape the shambles...."
"But
then", added he, speaking from his own point of view, "to enjoy
honour when alive one would readily die on a war-shield or in the headsman's
basket."
So he
rejected the pigs' point of view and adopted his own point of view. In what sense, then, was he different from
the pigs?'
I much fear
that the evolutionists too often resemble the Grand Augur and the pigs.
The ethical
element which has been prominent in many of the most famous systems of
philosophy is, in my opinion, one of the most serious obstacles to the victory
of scientific method in the investigation of philosophical questions. Human ethical notions, as Chuang
Tzu perceived, are essentially anthropocentric, and involve, when used in
metaphysics, an attempt, however veiled, to legislate for the universe on the
basis of the present desires of men. In
this way they interfere with that receptivity to fact which is the essence of
the scientific attitude towards the world.
To regard ethical notions as a key to the understanding of the world is
essentially pre-Copernican. It is to
make man, with the hopes and ideals which he happens to have at the present
moment, the centre of the universe and the interpreter of its supposed aims and
purposes. Ethical metaphysics is
fundamentally an attempt, however disguised, to give legislative force to our
own wishes. This may, of course, be
questioned, but I think that it is confirmed by a consideration of the way in
which ethical notions arise. Ethics is
essentially a product of the gregarious instinct, that is to say, of the
instinct to cooperate with those who are to form our own group against those
who belong to other groups. Those who
belong to our own group are good; those who belong to hostile groups are
wicked. The ends which are pursued by
our own group are desirable ends, the ends pursued by
hostile groups are nefarious. The
subjectivity of this situation is not apparent to the gregarious animal, which
feels that the general principles of justice are on the side of its own herd. When the animal has arrived at the dignity of
the metaphysician, it invents ethics as the embodiment of its belief in the
justice of its own herd. So the Grand
Augur invokes ethics as the justification of Augurs in their conflicts with
pigs. But, it may be said, this view of
ethics takes no account of such truly ethical notions as that of
self-sacrifice. This, however, would be
a mistake. The success of gregarious
animals in the struggle for existence depends upon cooperation within the herd,
and cooperation requires sacrifice, to some extent, of what would otherwise be
the interests of the individual. Hence arises a conflict of desires and instincts, since both
self-preservation and the preservation of the herd are biological ends to the
individual. Ethics is in origin the art
of recommending to others the sacrifices required for cooperation with
oneself. Hence, by reflection, it comes,
through the operation of social justice, to recommend sacrifices by oneself,
but all ethics, however refined, remains more or less subjective. Even vegetarians do not hesitate, for
example, to save the life of a man in a fever, although in doing so they
destroy the lives of many millions of microbes.
The view of the world taken by the philosophy derived from ethical
notions is thus never impartial and therefore never fully scientific. As compared with science, it fails to achieve
the imaginative liberation from self which is necessary to such understanding
of the world as man can hope to achieve, and the philosophy which it inspires
is always more or less parochial, more or less infected with the prejudices of
a time and a place.
I do not
deny the importance or value, within its own sphere, of the kind of philosophy
which is inspired by ethical notions.
The ethical work of Spinoza, for example, appears to me of the very
highest significance, but what is valuable in such work is not any metaphysical
theory as to the nature of the world to which it may give
rise, nor indeed anything which can be proved or disproved by
argument. What is valuable is the
indication of some new way of feeling towards life and the world, some way of
feeling by which our own existence can acquire more of the characteristics
which we must deeply desire. The value
of such work, however immeasurable it is, belongs with practice and not with
theory. Such theoretic importance as it
may possess is only in relation to human nature, not in relation to the world
at large. The scientific philosophy,
therefore, which aims only at understanding the world and not directly at any
other improvement of human life, cannot take account of ethical notions without
being turned aside from that submission to fact which is the essence of the
scientific temper.
II
If the
notion of the universe and the notion of good and evil are extruded from
scientific philosophy, it may be asked what specific problems remain for the
philosopher as opposed to the man of science?
It would be difficult to give a precise answer to this question, but
certain characteristics may be noted as distinguishing the province of
philosophy from that of the special sciences.
In the
first place a philosophical proposition must be general. It must not deal specially
with things on the surface of the earth, or with the solar system, or with any
other portion of space and time. It is
this need of generality which has led to the belief that philosophy deals with
the universe as a whole. I do not belief
that this belief is justified, but I do believe that a philosophical
proposition must be applicable to everything that exists or may exist. It might be supposed that this admission
would be scarcely distinguishable from the view which I wish to reject. This, however, would be an error, and an
important one. The traditional view
would make the universe itself the subject of various predicates which could
not be applied to any particular thing in the universe, and the ascription of
such peculiar predicates to the universe would be the special business of
philosophy. I maintain, on the contrary,
that there are no propositions of which the 'universe' is the subject; in other
words, that there is no such thing as the 'universe'. What I do maintain is that there are general
propositions which may be asserted of each individual thing, such as the
propositions of logic. This does not
involve that all the things there are from a whole which could be regarded as
another thing and be made the subject of predicates. It involves only the assertion that there are
properties which belong to each separate thing, not that there are properties
belonging to the whole of things collectively.
The philosophy which I wish to advocate may be called logical atomism or
absolute pluralism, because, while maintaining that there are many things, it
denies that there is a whole composed of those things. We shall see, therefore, that philosophical
propositions, instead of being concerned with the whole of things collectively,
are concerned with all things distributively; and not
only must they be concerned with all things, but they must be concerned with
such properties of all things as do not depend upon the accidental nature of
the things that there happen to be, but are true of any possible world,
independently of such facts as can only be discovered by our senses.
This brings
us to a second characteristic of philosophical propositions, namely, that they
must be a priori. A philosophical
proposition must be such as can be neither proved nor disproved by empirical
evidence. Too often we find in
philosophical books arguments based upon the course of history, or the
convolutions of the brain, or the eyes of shellfish. Special and accidental facts of this kind are
irrelevant to philosophy, which must make only such assertions as would be
equally true however the actual world were constituted.
We may sum
up these two characteristics of philosophical propositions by saying that philosophy
is the science of the possible. But
this statement unexplained is liable to be misleading, since it may be thought
that the possible is something other than the general, whereas in fact the two
are indistinguishable.
Philosophy,
if what has been said is correct, becomes indistinguishable from logic as that
word has now come to be used. The study
of logic consists, broadly speaking, of two not very sharply distinguished
portions. On the one hand it is
concerned with those general statements which can be made concerned everything
without mentioning any one thing or predicate or relation, such for example as
'if c is a member of the class a and every member of a is a member of b, then c is a member of the class b, whatever c, a, and b may be.' On the
other hand, it is concerned with the analysis and enumeration of logical forms,
i.e. with the kinds of propositions that may occur, with the various types of
facts, and with the classification of the constituents of facts. In this way logic provides an inventory of
possibilities, a repertory of abstractly tenable hypotheses.
It might be
thought that such a study would be too vague and too general to be of any very
great importance, and that, if its problems became at any point sufficiently
definite, they would be merged in the problems of some special science. It appears, however, that this is not the
case. In some problems, for example, the
analysis of space and time, the nature of perception, or the theory of
judgement, the discovery of the logical form of the facts involved is the
hardest part of the work and the part whose performance has been most lacking
hitherto. It is chiefly for want of the
right logical hypothesis that such problems have hitherto been treated in such
an unsatisfactory manner, and have given rise to those contradictions or
antinomies in which the enemies of reason among philosophers have at all times
delighted.
By
concentrating attention upon the investigation of logical forms, it becomes
possible at last for philosophy to deal with its problems piecemeal, and to
obtain, as the sciences do, such partial and probably not wholly correct
results as subsequent investigation can utilize even while it supplements and
improves them. Most philosophies
hitherto have been constructed all in one block, in such a way that, if they
were not wholly correct, they were wholly incorrect, and could not be used as a
basis for further investigations. It is
chiefly owing to this fact that philosophy, unlike science, has hitherto been unprogressive, because each original philosopher has had to
begin the work again from the beginning, without being able to accept anything
definite from the work of his predecessors.
A scientific philosophy such as I wish to recommend will be piecemeal
and tentative like other sciences; above all, it will be able to invent
hypotheses which, even if they are not wholly true, will yet remain fruitful
after the necessary corrections have been made.
This possibility of successive approximations to the truth is, more than
anything else, the source of the triumphs of science, and to transfer this
possibility to philosophy is to ensure a progress in method whose importance it
would be almost impossible to exaggerate.
The essence
of philosophy as thus conceived is analysis, not synthesis. To build up systems of the world, like Heine's German professor who knit together fragments of
life and made an intelligible system out of them, is not, I believe, any more
feasible than the discovery of the philosopher's stone. What is feasible is the understanding of
general forms, and the division of traditional problems into a number of
separate and less baffling questions.
'Divide and conquer' is the maxim of success here as elsewhere.
Let us
illustrate these somewhat general maxims by examining their application to the
philosophy of space, for it is only in application that the meaning or
importance of a method can be understood.
Suppose we are confronted with the problem of space as presented in
Kant's Transcendental Aesthetic, and suppose we wish to discover what are the
elements of the problem and what hope there is of obtaining a solution of
them. It will soon appear that three
entirely distinct problems, belonging to different studies, and requiring
different methods for their solution, have been confusedly combined in the
supposed single problem with which Kant is concerned. There is a problem of logic, a problem of
physics, and a problem of theory of knowledge.
Of these three, the problem of logic can be solved exactly and
perfectly; the problem of physics can probably be solved with as great a degree
of certainty and as great an approach to exactness as can be hoped in an
empirical region; the problem of theory of knowledge, however, remains very
obscure and very difficult to deal with.
Let us see how these three problems arise.
(1) The logical problem has arisen through the
suggestions of non-Euclidean geometry.
Given a body of geometrical propositions, it is not difficult to find a
minimum statement of the axioms from which this body of propositions can be
deduced. It is also not difficult, by
dropping or altering some of these axioms, to obtain a more general or a
different geometry, having, from the point of view of pure mathematics, the
same logical coherence and the same title to respect as the more familiar
Euclidean geometry. The Euclidean
geometry itself is true perhaps of actual space (though this is doubtful), but
certainly of an infinite number of purely arithmetical systems, each of which,
from the point of view of abstract logic, has an equal and indefeasible right
to the called a Euclidean space. Thus
space as an object of logical or mathematical study loses its uniqueness; not
only are there many kinds of spaces, but there are an infinity of examples of
each kind, though it is difficult to find any kind of which the space of
physics may be an example, and it is impossible to find any kind of which the
space of physics is certainly an example.
As an illustration of one possible logical system of geometry we may
consider all relations of three terms which are analogous in certain formal
respects to the relation 'between' as it appears to be in actual space. A space is then defined by means of one such
three-term relation. The points of the
space are all the terms which have this relation to something or other, and
their order in the space in question is determined by this relation. The points of one space are necessarily also
points of other spaces, since there are necessarily other three-term relations
having those same points for their field.
The space in fact is not determined by the class of its points, but by
the ordering three-term relation. When
enough abstract logical properties of such relations have been enumerated to
determine the resulting kind of geometry, say, for example, Euclidean geometry,
it becomes unnecessary for the pure geometer in his abstract capacity to
distinguish between the various relations which have all these properties. He considers the whole class of such
relations, not any single one among them.
Thus in studying a given kind of geometry the pure mathematician is
studying a certain class of relations defined by means of certain abstract
logical properties which take the place of what used to be called axioms. The nature of geometrical reasoning
therefore is purely deductive and purely logical; if any special
epistemological peculiarities are to be found in geometry, it must not be in
the reasoning, but in our knowledge concerning the axioms in some given space.
(2) The physical problem of space is both more
interesting and more difficult than the logical problem. The physical problem may be stated as
follows: to find in the physical world, or to construct from physical
materials, a space of one of the kinds enumerated by the logical treatment of
geometry. This problem derives its
difficulty from the attempt to accommodate to the roughness and vagueness of
the real world some system possessing the logical clearness and exactitude of
pure mathematics. That this can be done
with a certain degree of approximation is fairly evident. If I see three people A, B, and C
sitting in a row, I become aware of the fact which may be expressed by saying
that B is between A and C rather than that A is
between B and C, or C is between A and B. This relation of 'between' which is thus
perceived to hold has some of the abstract logical properties of those three-term
relations which, we saw, give rise to a geometry, but its properties fail to be
exact, and are not, as empirically given, amenable to the kind of treatment at
which geometry aims. In abstract
geometry we deal with points, straight lines, and planes; but the three people A,
B, and C whom I see sitting in a row are not exactly points, nor is
the row exactly a straight line.
Nevertheless physics, which formally assumes a space containing points,
straight lines, and planes, is found empirically to give results applicable to
the sensible world. It must therefore be
possible to find an interpretation of the points, straight lines, and planes of
physics in terms of physical data, or at any rate in terms of data together
with such hypothetical additions as seem least open to question. Since all data suffer from a lack of
mathematical precision through being of a certain size and somewhat vague in
outline, it is plain that if such a notion as that of a point is to find any
application to empirical material, the point must be neither a datum nor a
hypothetical addition to data, but a construction by means of data with
their hypothetical additions. It is
obvious that any hypothetical filling out of data is less dubious and
unsatisfactory when the additions are closely analogous to data than when they
are of a radically different sort. To
assume, for example, that objects which we see continue, after we have turned
away our eyes, to be more or less analogous to what they were while we were
looking, is a less violent assumption than to assume that such objects are
composed of an infinite number of mathematical points. Hence in the physical study of the geometry
of physical space, points must not be assumed ab
initio as they are in the logical treatment of geometry,
but must be constructed as systems composed of data and hypothetical analogues
of data. We are thus led naturally to
define a physical point as a certain class of those objects which are the
ultimate constituents of the physical world.
It will be the class of all those objects which, as one would naturally
say, contain the points. To
secure a definition giving this result, without previously assuming that
physical objects are composed of points, is an agreeable problem in
mathematical logic. The solution of this
problem and the perception of its importance are due to my friend Dr Whitehead. The
oddity of regarding a point as a class of physical entities wears off with
familiarity, and ought in any case not to be felt by those who maintain, as practically
everyone does, that points are mathematical fictions. The word 'fiction' is used glibly in such
connections by many men who seem not to feel the necessity of explaining how it
can come about that a fiction can be so useful in the study of the actual world
as the points of mathematical physics have been found to be. By our definition, which regards a point as a
class of physical objects, it is explained both how the use of points can lead
to important physical results, and how we can nevertheless avoid the assumption
that points are themselves entities in the physical world.
Many of the
mathematically convenient properties of abstract logical spaces cannot be
either known to belong or known not to belong to the space of physics. Such are all the properties connected with
continuity. For to
know that actual space has these properties would require an infinite exactness
of sense-perception. If actual space is continuous, there are nevertheless many possible
non-continuous spaces which will be empirically indistinguishable from it; and,
conversely, actual space may be non-continuous and yet empirically
indistinguishable from a possible continuous space. Continuity, therefore, though obtainable in
the a priori region of arithmetic, is not with certainty obtainable in
the space or time of the physical world: whether these are continuous or not
would seem to be a question not only unanswered but for ever unanswerable. From the point of view of philosophy,
however, the discovery that a question is unanswerable is as complete an answer
as any that could possibly be obtained.
And from the point of view of physics, where no empirical means of
distinction can be found, there can be no empirical objection to the
mathematically simplest assumption, which is that of continuity.
The subject
of the physical theory of space is a very large one, hitherto little
explored. It is associated with a
similar theory of time, and both have been forced upon the attention of
philosophically minded physicists by the discussions which have raged
concerning the theory of relativity.
(3) The problem with which Kant is concerned in
the Transcendental Aesthetic is primarily the epistemological problem: 'How do
we come to have knowledge of geometry a priori?' By the distinction between the logical and
physical problems of geometry, the bearing and scope of this question are
greatly altered. Our knowledge of pure
geometry is a priori but is wholly logical. Our knowledge of physical geometry is
synthetic, but is not a priori.
Our knowledge of pure geometry is hypothetical, and does not enable us
to assert, for example, that the axiom of parallels is true in the physical
world. Our knowledge of physical
geometry, while it does enable us to assert that this axiom is approximately
verified, does not, owing to the inevitable inexactitude
of observation, enable us to assert that it is verified exactly. Thus, with the separation which we have made
between pure geometry and the geometry of physics, the Kantian problem
collapses. To the question, 'How is
synthetic a priori knowledge possible?' we can now reply, at any rate so
far as geometry is concerned, 'It is not possible,' if 'synthetic' means 'not
deducible from logic alone.' Our
knowledge of geometry, like the rest of our knowledge, is derived partly from
logic, partly from sense, and the peculiar position which in Kant's day
geometry appeared to occupied is seen now to be a
delusion. There are still some
philosophers, it is true, who maintain that our knowledge of the axiom of
parallels, for example, is true of actual space, is not to be accounted for
empirically, but is as Kant maintained derived from an a priori
intuition. This position is not
logically refutable, but I think it loses all plausibility as soon as we
realize how complicated and derivative is the notion of
physical space. As we have seen,
the application of geometry to the physical world in no way demands that there
should really be points and straight lines among physical entities. The principle of economy, therefore, demands
that we should abstain from assuming the existence of points and straight
lines. As soon, however, as we accept
the view that points and straight lines are complicated constructions by means
of classes of physical entities, the hypothesis that we have an a priori
intuition enabling us to know what happens to straight lines when they are
produced indefinitely becomes extremely strained and harsh; nor do I think that
such an hypothesis would ever have arisen in the mind of a philosopher who had
grasped the nature of physical space.
Kant, under the influence of Newton, adopted, though with some
vacillation, the hypothesis of absolute space, and this hypothesis, though
logically unobjectionable, is removed by Occam's
razor, since absolute space is an unnecessary entity in the explanation of the
physical world. Although, therefore, we
cannot refute the Kantian theory of an a priori intuition, we can remove
its grounds one by one through an analysis of the problem. Thus, here as in many other philosophical
questions, the analytic method, while not capable of arriving at a
demonstrative result, is nevertheless capable of showing that all the positive
grounds in favour of a certain theory are fallacious and that a less unnatural theory
is capable of accounting for the facts.
Another
question by which the capacity of the analytic method can be shown is the
question of realism. Both those who
advocate and those who combat realism seem to me to be far from clear as to the
nature of the problem which they are discussing. If we ask: 'Are our objects of perception real
and are they independent of the percipient?' it must be supposed that we
attach some meaning to the words 'real' and 'independent', and yet, if either
side in the controversy of realism is asked to define these two words, their
answer is pretty sure to embody confusions such as logical analysis will
reveal.
Let us
begin with the word 'real'. There
certainly are objects of perception, and therefore, if the question whether
these objects are real is to be a substantial question, there must be in the
world two sorts of objects, namely, the real and the unreal, and yet the unreal
is supposed to be essentially what there is not. The question what properties must belong to
an object in order to make it real is one to which an adequate answer is seldom
if ever forthcoming. There is of course
the Hegelian answer, that the real is the self-consistent and that nothing is
self-consistent except the Whole; but this answer, true or false, is not
relevant in our present discussion, which moves on a lower plane and is
concerned with the status of objects of perception among other objects of equal
fragmentariness. Objects of perception
are contrasted, in the discussions concerning realism, rather with psychical
states on the one hand and matter on the other hand than with the all-inclusive
whole of things. The question we have
therefore to consider is the question as to what can be meant by assigning
'reality' to some but not all of the entities that make up the world. Two elements, I think, make up what is felt
rather than thought when the word 'reality' is used in this sense. A thing is real if it persists at times when
it is not perceived; or again, a thing is real when it is correlated with other
things in a way which experience has led us to expect. It will be seen that reality in either of
these senses is by no means necessary to a thing, and that in fact there might
be a whole world in which nothing was real in either of these senses. It might turn out that the objects of
perception failed of reality in one or both of these respects, without its
being in any way deducible that they are not parts of the external world with
which physics deals. Similar remarks
will apply to the word 'independent'.
Most of the associations of this word are bound up with ideas as to
causation which it is not now possible to maintain. A is independent of B when B
is not an indispensable part of the cause of A. But when it is recognized that causation is
nothing more than correlation, and that there are correlations of simultaneity
as well as of succession, it becomes evident that there is no uniqueness in a
series of causal antecedents of a given event, but that, at any point where
there is a correlation of simultaneity, we can pass from one line of
antecedents to another in order to obtain a new series of causal
antecedents. It will be necessary to
specify the causal law according to which the antecedents are to be
considered. I received a letter the
other day from a correspondent who had been puzzled by various philosophical
questions. After enumerating them he
says: 'These questions led me from Bonn to Strassburg,
where I found Professor Simmel.' Now, it would be absurd to deny that these questions
caused his body to move from Bonn to Strassburg, and
yet it must be supposed that a set of purely mechanical antecedents could also
be found which would account for this transfer of matter from one place to
another. Owing to this plurality of causal
series antecedent to a given event, the notion of the cause becomes
indefinite, and the question of independence becomes correspondingly
ambiguous. Thus, instead of asking
simply where A is independent of B, we ought to ask whether there
is a series determined by such and such causal laws leading from B to A. This point is important in connection with
the particular question of objects of perception. It may be that no objects quite like those
which we perceive ever exist unperceived; in this case there will be a causal
law according to which objects of perception are not independent of being
perceived. But even if this be the case,
it may nevertheless also happen that there are purely physical causal laws determining
the occurrence of objects which are perceived by means of other objects which
perhaps are not perceived. In that case,
in regard to such causal laws objects of perception will be independent of
being perceived. Thus the question
whether objects of perception are independent of being perceived is, as it
stands, indeterminate, and the answer will be yes or no according to the method
adopted of making it determinate. I
believe that this confusion has borne a very large part in prolonging the
controversies on this subject, which might well have seemed capable of
remaining for ever undecided. The view
which I should wish to advocate is that objects of perception do not persist
unchanged at times when they are not perceived, although probably objects more
or less resembling them do exist at such times; that objects of perception are
part, and the only empirically knowable part, of the actual subject-matter of
physics, and are themselves properly to be called physical; that purely
physical laws exist determining the character and duration of objects of
perception without any reference to the fact that they are perceived; and that
in the establishment of such laws the propositions of physics do not presuppose
any propositions of psychology or even the existence of mind. I do not know whether realists would
recognize such a view as realism. All
that I should claim for it is, that it avoids
difficulties which seem to me to beset both realism and idealism as hitherto
advocated, and that it avoids the appeal which they have made to ideas which
logical analysis shows to be ambiguous.
A further defence and elaboration of the positions which I advocate, but
for which time is lacking now, will be found indicated in my book on Our
Knowledge of the External World. [Open Court Company, 1914.]
The
adoption of scientific method in philosophy, if I am not mistaken, compels us
to abandon the hope of solving many of the more ambitious and humanly
interesting problems of traditional philosophy.
Some of these it relegates, though with little expectation of a
successful solution, to special sciences, others it shows to be such as our
capacities are essentially incapable of solving. But there remains a
large number of the recognized problems of philosophy in regard to which the
method advocated gives all those advantages of division into distinct
questions, of tentative, partial, and progressive advance, and of appeal to
principles with which, independently of temperament, all competent students
must agree. The failure of philosophy
hitherto has been due in the main to haste and ambition: patience and modesty,
here as in other sciences, will open the road to solid and durable progress.
CHAPTER VII
The Ultimate Constituents of Matter
[An address delivered to the Philosophical Society of
Manchester in February 1915. Reprinted from The Monist, July, 1915.]
I WISH to discuss in this article no less a question than the ancient metaphysical query, 'What is matter?' The question, 'What is matter?' insofar as it concerns philosophy, is, I think, already capable of an answer which in principle will be as complete as an answer can hope to be; that is to say, we can separate the problem into an essentially soluble and an essentially insoluble portion, and we can now see how to solve the essentially soluble portion, at least as regards its main outlines. It is these outlines which I wish to suggest in the present article. My main position, which is realistic, is, I hope, and believe, not remote from that of Professor Alexander, by whose writings on this subject I have profited greatly. [Cf. especially Samuel Alexander, 'The Basis of Realism', British Academy, Vol. VI.] It is also in close accord with Dr Nunn. ['Are Secondary Qualities Independent of Perception?' Proc. Arist. Soc., 1909-10, pp. 191-218.]
Common sense is accustomed to the division of the
world into mind and matter. It is
supposed by all who have never studied philosophy that the distinction between
mind and matter is perfectly clear and easy, that the two do not at any point
overlap, and that only a fool or a philosopher could be in doubt as to whether
any given entity is mental or material.
This simple faith survives in Descartes and in a somewhat modified form
in Spinoza, but with Leibniz it begins to disappear, and from his day to our
own almost every philosopher of note has criticized and rejected the dualism of
common sense. It is my intention in this
article to defend this dualism; but before defending it we must spend a few
moments on the reasons which have prompted its rejection.
Our
knowledge of the material world is obtained by means of the senses, of sight
and touch and so on. At first it is
supposed that things are just as they seem, but two opposite sophistications
soon destroy this naive belief. On the
one hand the physicists cut up matter into molecules, atoms, corpuscles, and as
many more such subdivisions as their future needs may make them postulate, and
the units at which they arrive are uncommonly different from the visible,
tangible objects of daily life. A unit
of matter tends more and more to be something like an electromagnetic field
filling all space, though having its greatest intensity in a small region. Matter consisting of such elements is as
remote from daily life as any metaphysical theory. It differs from the theories of
metaphysicians only in the fact that its practical efficacy proves that it
contains some measure of truth and induces businessmen to invest money on the
strength of it; but, in spite of its connection with the money market, it
remains a metaphysical theory nonetheless.
The second
kind of sophistication to which the world of common sense has been subjected is
derived from the psychologists and physiologists. The physiologists point out that what we see
depends upon the eye, that what we hear depends upon the ear, and that all our
senses are liable to be affected by anything which affects the brain, like
alcohol or hashish. Psychologists point
out how much of what we think we see is supplied by association or unconscious
inference, how much is mental interpretation, and how doubtful is the residuum
which can be regarded as crude datum.
From these facts it is argued by the psychologists that the notion of a
datum passively received by the mind is a delusion, and it is argued by the
physiologists that even if a pure datum of sense could be obtained by the
analysis of experience, still this datum could not belong, as common sense
supposes, to the outer world, since its whole nature is conditioned by our
nerves and sense organs, changing as they change in ways which it is thought
impossible to connect with any change in the matter supposed to be
perceived. This physiologist's argument
is exposed to the rejoinder, more specious than solid, that our knowledge of
the existence of the sense organs and nerves is obtained by that very process
which the physiologist has been engaged in discrediting, since the existence of
the nerves and sense organs is only known through the evidence of the senses
themselves. This argument may prove that
some reinterpretation of the results of physiology is necessary before they can
acquire metaphysical validity. But it
does not upset the physiological argument insofar as this constitutes merely a reductio ad absurdum of naive realism.
These
various lines of argument prove, I think, that some
part of the beliefs of common sense must be abandoned. They prove that, if we take these beliefs as
a whole, we are forced into conclusions which are in part self-contradictory;
but such arguments cannot of themselves decide what portion of our common-sense
beliefs is in need of correction. Common
sense believes that what we see is physical, outside the mind, and continuing
to exist if we shut our eyes or turn them in another direction. I believe that common sense is right in
regarding what we see as physical and (in one of several possible senses)
outside the mind, but is probably wrong in supposing that it continues to exist
when we are no longer looking at it. It
seems to me that the whole discussion of matter has been obscured by two errors
which support each other. The first of
these is the error that what we see, or perceive through any of our other
senses, is subjective: the second is the belief that what is physical must be
persistent. Whatever physics may regard
as the ultimate constituents of matter, it always supposes these constituents
to be indestructible. Since the
immediate data of sense are not indestructible but in a state of perpetual
flux, it is argued that these data themselves cannot be among the ultimate
constituents of matter. I believe this
to be a sheer mistake. The persistent
particles of mathematical physics I regard as logical constructions, symbolic
fictions enabling us to express compendiously very complicated assemblages of
facts; and, on the other hand, I believe that the actual data in sensation, the
immediate objects of sight or touch or hearing, are extra-mental, purely
physical, and among the ultimate constituents of matter.
My meaning
in regard to the impermanence of physical entities may perhaps be made clearer
by the use of Bergson's favourite illustration of the
cinematograph. When I first read Bergson's statement that the mathematician conceives the
world after the analogy of a cinematograph, I had never seen a cinematograph,
and my first visit to one was determined by the desire to verify Bergson's statement, which I found to be completely true,
at least so far as I am concerned. When,
in a picture palace, we see a man rolling downhill, or running away from the
police, or falling into a river, or doing any of those other things to which
men in such places are addicted, we know that there is not really only one man
moving, but a succession of films, each with a different momentary man. The illusion of persistence arises only
through the approach to continuity in the series of momentary men. Now what I wish to suggest is that in this
respect the cinema is a better metaphysician than common sense, physics, or
philosophy. The real man too, I believe,
however the police may swear to his identity, is really a series of momentary
men, each different one from the other, and bound together, not by a numerical
identity, but by continuity and certain intrinsic causal laws. And what applies to men applies equally to tables
and chairs, the sun, moon and stars.
Each of these is to be regarded, not as one single persistent entity,
but as a series of entities succeeding each other in time, each lasting for a
very brief period, though probably not for a mere mathematical instant. In saying this I am only urging the same kind
of division in time as we are accustomed to acknowledge in the case of
space. A body which fills a cubic foot
will be admitted to consist of many smaller bodies, each occupying only a very
tiny volume; similarly a thing which persists for an hour is to be regarded as
composed of many things of less duration.
A true theory of matter requires a division of things into
time-corpuscles as well as into space-corpuscles.
The world
may be conceived as consisting of a multitude of entities arranged in a certain
pattern. The entities which are arranged
I shall call 'particulars'. The arrangement or patterns results from relations among
particulars. Classes or series of
particulars, collected together on account of some
property which makes it convenient to be able to speak of them as wholes, are
what I call logical constructions or symbolic fictions. The particulars are to be conceived, not on
the analogy of bricks in a building, but rather on the analogy of notes in a
symphony. The ultimate constituents of a
symphony (apart from relations) are the notes, each of which lasts only for a
very short time. We may collect together
all the notes played by one instrument: these may be regarded as the analogues
of the successive particulars which common sense would regard as successive
states of one 'thing'. But the 'thing'
ought to be regarded as no more 'real' or 'substantial' than, for example, the
role of the trombone. As soon as
'things' are conceived in this manner it will be found that the difficulties in
the way of regarding immediate objects of sense as physical have largely
disappeared.
When people
ask, 'Is the object of sense mental or physical?' they seldom have any clear
idea what is meant by 'mental' or 'physical', or what criteria are to be
applied for deciding whether a given entity belongs to one class or the
other. I do not know how to give a sharp
definition of the word 'mental', but something may be done by enumerating
occurrences which are indubitably mental: believing, doubting, wishing,
willing, being pleased or pained, are certainly mental occurrences; so are what
we may call experiences, seeing, hearing, smelling, perceiving generally. But it does not follow from this that what is
seen, what is heard, what is smelt, what is perceived, must be mental. When I see a flash of lightning, my seeing of
it is mental, but what I see, although it is not quite the same as what anybody
else sees at the same moment, and although it seems very unlike what the
physicist would describe as a flash of lightning, is not mental. I maintain, in fact, that if the physicist
could describe truly and fully all that occurs in the physical world when there
is a flash of lightning, it would contain as a constituent what I see, and also
what is seen by anybody else who would commonly be said to see the same
flash. What I mean may perhaps be made
plainer by saying that if my body could remain in exactly the same state in
which it is, although my mind had ceased to exist, precisely that object which
I now see when I see the flash would exist, although of course I should not see
it, since my seeing is mental. The
principal reasons which have led people to reject this view have, I think, been
two; first, that they did not adequately distinguish between my seeing and what
I see; secondly, that the causal dependence of what I see upon my body has made
people suppose that what I see cannot be 'outside' me. The first of these reasons need not detain
us, since the confusion only needs to be pointed out in order to be obviated;
but the second requires some discussion, since it can only be answered by
removing current misconceptions, on the one hand as to the nature of space, and
on the other, as to the meaning of causal dependence.
When people
ask whether colours, for example, or other secondary qualities are inside or
outside the mind, they seem to suppose that their meaning must be clear, and
that it ought to be possible to say yes or no without any further discussion of
the terms involved. In fact, however,
such terms as 'inside' or 'outside' are very ambiguous. What is meant by asking whether this or that
is 'in the mind'? The mind is not like a
bag or a pie; it does not occupy a certain region in space or, if (in a sense)
it does, what is in that region is presumably part of the brain, which would
not be said to be in the mind. When
people say that sensible qualities are in the mind, they do not mean 'spatially
contained in' in the sense in which the blackbirds were in the pie. We might regard the mind as an assemblage of
particulars, namely, what would be called 'states of mind', which would belong
together in virtue of some specific common quality. The common quality of all states of mind
would be the quality designated by the word 'mental'; and beside this we should
have to suppose that each separate person's states of mind have some common
characteristic distinguishing them from the states of mind of other
people. Ignoring this latter point, let
us ask ourselves whether the quality designated by the word 'mental' does, as a
matter of observation, actually belong to objects of sense, such as colours or
noises. I think any candid person must
reply that, however difficult it may be to know what we mean by 'mental', it is
not difficult to see that colours and noises are not mental in the sense of
having that intrinsic peculiarity which belongs to beliefs and wishes and
volitions, but not to the physical world.
Berkeley advances on this subject a plausible argument [First
dialogue between Hylas and Philonous,
Works (Fraser's edition, 1901), I, p. 384.] which
seems to me to rest upon an ambiguity in the word 'pain'. He argues that the realist supposes the heat
which he feels in approaching a fire to be something outside his mind, but that
as he approaches nearer and nearer to the fire the sensation of heat passes
imperceptibly into pain, and that no-one could regard pain as something outside
the mind. In reply to this argument, it
should be observed in the first place that the heat of which we are immediately
aware is not in the fire but in our own body.
It is only by inference that the fire is judged to be the cause of the
heat which we feel in our body. In the
second place (and this is the more important point), when we speak of pain we
may mean one of two things: we may mean the object of the sensation or other
experience which has the quality of being painful, or we may mean the quality
of painfulness itself. When a man says
he has a pain in his great toe, what he means is that he has a sensation
associated with his great toe and having the quality of painfulness. The sensation itself, like every sensation,
consists in experiencing a sensible object, and the experiencing has that
quality of painfulness which only mental occurrences can have, but which may
belong to thoughts or desires, as well as to sensations. But in common language we speak of the
sensible object experienced in a painful sensation as a pain, and it is this way
of speaking which causes the confusion upon which the plausibility of
Berkeley's argument depends. It would be
absurd to attribute the quality of painfulness to anything non-mental, and
hence it comes to be thought that what we call a pain in the toe must be
mental. In fact, however, it is not the
sensible object in such a case which is painful, but the sensation, that is to
say, the experience of the sensible object.
As the heat which we experience from the fire grows greater, the
experience passes gradually from being pleasant to being painful, but neither
the pleasure nor the pain is a quality of the object experienced as opposed to
the experience, and it is therefore a fallacy to argue that this object must be
mental on the grounds that painfulness can only be attributed to what is mental.
If, then,
when we say that something is in the mind we mean that it has a certain
recognizable intrinsic characteristic such as belongs to thoughts and desires,
it must be maintained on grounds of immediate inspection that objects of sense are
not in any mind.
A different
meaning of 'in the mind' is, however, to be inferred from the arguments
advanced by those who regard sensible objects as being in the mind. The arguments used are, in the main, such as
would prove the causal dependence of objects of sense upon the percipient. Now the notion of causal dependence is very
obscure and difficult, much more so in fact than is generally realized by
philosophers. I shall return to this
point in a moment. For the present,
however, accepting the notion of causal dependence without criticism, I wish to
urge that the dependence in question in rather upon our bodies than upon our
minds. The visual appearance of an
object is altered is he shut one eye, or squint, or look previously at
something dazzling; but all these are bodily acts, and the alterations which
they affect are to be explained by physiology and optics, not by psychology.
[This point has been well urged by the American realists.] They are in
fact of exactly the same kind as the alterations effected
by spectacles or by a microscope. They
belong therefore to the theory of the physical world, and can have no bearing
upon the question whether what we see is causally dependent upon the mind. What they do tend to prove, and what I for my
part have no wish to deny, is that what we see is causally dependent upon our
body and is not, as crude common sense would suppose, something which would
exist equally if our eyes and nerves and brain were absent, any more than the
visual appearance present by an object seen through a microscope would remain
if the microscope were removed. So long
as it is supposed that the physical world is composed of stable and more or
less permanent constituents the fact that what we see is changed by changes in
our body appears to afford reason for regarding what we see as not an ultimate
constituent of matter. But if it is
recognized that the ultimate constituents of matter are as circumscribed in
duration as in spatial extent, the whole of this difficulty vanishes.
There
remains, however, another difficulty, connected with space. When we look at the sun we wish to know
something about the sun itself, which is ninety-three million miles away; but
what we see is dependent upon our eyes, and it is difficult to suppose that our
eyes can affect what happens at a distance of ninety-three millions miles. Physics tells us that certain electromagnetic
waves start from the sun, and reach our eyes after about eight minutes. They there produce disturbances in the rods
and cones, thence in the optic nerve, thence in the brain. At the end of this purely physical series, by
some odd miracle, comes the experience which we call 'seeing the sun', and it
is such experiences which form the whole and sole reason for our belief in the
optic nerve, the rods and cones, the ninety-three millions miles, the
electromagnetic waves, and the sun itself.
It is this curious oppositeness of direction between the order of
causation as affirmed by physics, and the order of evidence as revealed by theory
of knowledge, that causes the most serious perplexities in regard to the nature
of physical reality. Anything that
invalidates our seeing, as a source of knowledge concerning physical reality,
invalidates also the whole of physics and physiology. And yet, starting from a common-sense
acceptance of our seeing, physics has been led step by step to the construction
of the causal chain in which our seeing is the last link, and the immediate
object which we see cannot be regarded as that initial cause which we believe
to be ninety-three million miles away, and which we are inclined to regard as
the 'real' sun.
I have
stated this difficulty as forcibly as I can, because I believe that it can only
be answered by a radical analysis and reconstruction of all the conceptions
upon whose employment it depends.
Space,
time, matter and cause, are the chief of these conceptions. Let us begin with the conception of cause.
Causal
dependence, as I observed a moment ago, is a conception which it is very
dangerous to accept at its face value.
There exists a notion that in regard to any event there is something
which may be called the cause of that event - some one definite
occurrence, without which the event would have been impossible and with which
it becomes necessary. An event is
supposed to be dependent upon its cause in some way in which it is not
dependent upon other things. Thus men
will urge that the mind is dependent upon the brain, or, with equal
plausibility, that the brain is dependent upon the mind. It seems not improbable that if we had
sufficient knowledge we could infer the state of a man's mind from the state of
his brain, or the state of his brain from the state of his mind. So long as the usual conception of causal
dependence is retained, this state of affairs can be used by the materialist to
urge that the state of our brain causes our thoughts, and by the idealist to
urge that our thoughts cause the state of our brain. Either contention is equally valid or equally
invalid. The fact seems to be that there
are many correlations of the sort which may be called causal, and that, for example, either a physical or a mental event can
be predicted, theoretically, either from a sufficient number of physical
antecedents or from a sufficient number of mental antecedents. To speak of the cause of an event is
therefore misleading. And set of
antecedents from which the event can theoretically be inferred by means of
correlations might be called a cause of the event. But to speak of the cause is to imply a
uniqueness which does not exist.
The relevance of this to the experience which we call 'seeing the sun' is obvious. The fact that there exists a chain of antecedents which makes our seeing dependent upon the eyes and nerves and brain does not even tend to show that there is not another chain of antecedents in which the eyes and nerves and brain as physical things are ignored. If we are to escape from the dilemma which seemed to arise out of the physiological causation of what we see when we say we see the sun, we must find, at least in theory, a way of stating causal laws for the physical world, in which the units are not material things, such as the eyes and nerves and brain, but momentary particular. Instead of supposing, as we naturally do when we start from an uncritical acceptance of the apparent dicta of physics, that matter is what is 'really real' in the physical world, and that the immediate objects of sense are mere phantasms, we must regard matter as a logical construction, of which the constituents will be just such evanescent particulars as may, when an observer happens to be present, become data of sense to that observer. What physics regards as the sun of eight minutes ago will be a whole assemblage of particulars, existing at different times, spreading out from a centre with the velocity of light, and containing among their number all those visual data which are seen by people who are now looking at the sun. Thus the sun of eight minutes ago is a class of particulars, and what I see when I now look at the sun is one member of this class. The various particulars constituting this class will be correlated with each other by a certain continuity and certain intrinsic laws of variation as we pass outwards from the centre, together with certain modifications correlated extrinsically with other particulars which are not members of this class. It is these extrinsic modifications which represent the sort of facts that, in our former account, appeared as the influence of the eyes and nerves in modifying the appearance of the sun. [Cf. T.P. Nunn, 'Are Secondary Qualities Independent of Perception?' Proc. Arist. Soc., 1909-10.]
The prima
facie difficulties in the way of this view are chiefly derived from an
unduly conventional theory of space. It
might seem at first sight as if we had packed the world much fuller than it
could possibly hold. At every place
between us and the sun, we said, there is to be a particular which is to be a
member of the sun as it was a few minutes ago.
There will also, of course, have to be a particular which is a member of
any planet or fixed star that may happen to be visible from that place. At the place where I am, there will be
particulars which will be members severally of all the 'things' I am now said
to be perceiving.
Thus throughout the world, everywhere, there will be an enormous number
of particulars coexisting in the same place.
But these troubles result from contenting ourselves too readily with the
merely three-dimensional space to which schoolmasters have accustomed us. The space of the real world is a space of six
dimensions, and as soon as we realize this we see that there is plenty of room
for all the particulars for which we want to find positions. In order to realize this we have only to
return for a moment from the polished space of physics to the rough and untidy
space of our immediate sensible experience.
The space of one man's sensible objects is a three-dimensional space. It does not appear probable that two men ever
both perceive at the same time any one sensible object; when they are said to
see the same thing or hear the same noise, there will always be some
difference, however slight, between the actual shapes seen or the actual sounds
heard. If this is so, and if, as is
generally assumed, position in space is purely relative, it follows that the
space of one man's objects and the space of another man's objects have no place
in common, that they are in fact different spaces, and not merely different
parts of one space. I mean by this that
such immediate spatial relations as are perceived to hold between the different
parts of the sensible space perceived by one man, do not hold between parts of
sensible spaces perceived by different men.
There are therefore a multitude of three-dimensional spaces in the
world: there are all those perceived by observers, and presumably also those
which are not perceived, merely because no observer is suitably situated for
perceiving them.
But
although these spaces do not have to one another the same kind of spatial
relations as obtain between the parts of one of them, it is nevertheless
possible to arrange these spaces themselves in a three-dimensional order. This is done by means of the correlated
particulars which we regard as members (or aspects) of one physical thing. When a number of people are
said to see the same object, those who would be said to be near to the object
see a particular occupying a larger part of their field of vision than is
occupied by the corresponding particular seen by people who would be said to be
further from the thing. By means
of such considerations it is possible, in ways which need not now be further
specified, to arrange all the different spaces in a three-dimensional
series. Since each of the spaces is
itself three-dimensional, the whole world of particulars is thus arranged in a
six-dimensional space, that is to say, six co-ordinates will be required to
assign completely the position of any given particular, namely, three to assign
its position in its own space and three more to assign the position of its
space among the other spaces.
There are
two ways of classifying particulars: we may take together all those that belong
to a given 'perspective', or all those that are, as common sense would say,
different 'aspects' of the same 'thing'.
For example, if I am (as I said) seeing the sun, what I see belongs to
two assemblages: (1) the assemblage of all my presents objects of sense, which
is what I call a 'perspective'; (2) the assemblage of all the different
particulars which would be called aspects of the sun of eight minutes ago -
this assemblage is what I define as being the sun of eight minutes
ago. Thus 'perspectives' and 'things'
are merely two different ways of classifying particulars. It is to be observed that there is no a
priori necessity for particulars to be susceptible of this double
classification. There may be what might
be called 'wild' particulars, not having the usual relations by which the
classification is effected; perhaps dreams and hallucinations are composed of
particulars which are 'wild' in this sense.
The exact
definition of what is meant by a perspective is not quite easy. So long as we confine ourselves to visible
objects or to objects of touch we might define the perspective of a given particular
as 'all particulars which have a simple (direct) spatial relation to the given
particular'. Between two patches of
colour which I see now, there is a direct spatial relation which I equally see. But between patches of colour seen by
different men there is only an indirect constructed spatial relation by means
of the placing of 'things' in physical space (which is the same as the space
composed of perspectives). Those
particulars which have direct spatial relations to a given particular will belong
to the same perspective. But if, for
example, the sounds which I hear are to belong to the same perspective with the
patches of colour which I see, there must be particulars which have no direct
spatial relation and yet belong to the same perspective. We cannot define a perspective as all the data
of one percipient at one time, because we wish to allow the possibility of
perspectives which are not perceived by any one. There will be need, therefore, in defining a
perspective, of some principle derived neither from psychology nor from space.
Such a
principle may be obtained from the consideration of time. The one all-embracing time, like the one
all-embracing space, is a construction; there is no direct time-relation
between particulars belonging to my perspective and particulars belonging to
another man's. On the other hand, any
two particulars of which I am aware are either simultaneous or successive, and
their simultaneity or successiveness is sometimes itself a datum to me. We may therefore define the perspective to
which a given particular belongs as 'all particulars simultaneous with a given
particular', where 'simultaneous' is to be understood as a direct simple
relation, not the derivative constructed relation of physics. It may be observed that the introduction of
'local time' suggested by the principle of relativity has effected, for purely
scientific reasons, much the same multiplication of times as we have just been
advocating.
The
sum-total of all the particulars that are (directly) either simultaneous with
or before or after a given particular may be defined as the 'biography' to
which that particular belongs. It will
be observed that, just as a perspective need not be actually perceived by
anyone, so a biography need not be actually lived by anyone. Those biographies that are lived by no-one
are called 'official'.
The
definition of a 'thing' is effected by means of continuity and of correlations
which have a certain differential independence of other 'things'. That is to say, given a particular in one
perspective, there will usually in a neighbouring perspective be a very similar
particular, differing from the given particular, to the first order of small
quantities, according to a law involving only the difference of position of the
two perspectives in perspective space, and not any of the other 'things' in the
universe. It is this continuity and
differential independence in the law of change as we pass from one perspective
to another that defines the class of particulars which is to be called 'one
thing'.
Broadly
speaking, we may say that the physicist finds it convenient to classify
particulars into 'things', while the psychologist finds it convenient to
classify them into 'perspectives' and 'biographies', since one perspective may
constitute the momentary data of one percipient, and one biography may
constitute the whole of the data of one percipient throughout his life.
We may now
sum up our discussion. Our subject has
been to discover as far as possible the nature of the ultimate constituents of
the physical world. When I speak of the
'physical world', I mean, to begin with, the world dealt with by physics. It is obvious that physics is an empirical science,
giving us a certain amount of knowledge and based upon evidence obtained
through the senses. But partly through
the development of physics itself, partly through arguments derived from
physiology, psychology or metaphysics, it has come to be thought that the
immediate data of sense could not themselves form part of the ultimate
constituents of the physical world, but were in some sense 'mental', 'in the
mind', or 'subjective'. The grounds for
this view, insofar as they depend upon physics, can only be adequately dealt
with by rather elaborate constructions depending upon symbolic logic, showing
that out of such materials as are provided by the senses it is possible to
construct classes and series having the properties which physics assigns to
matter. Since this argument is difficult
and technical, I have not embarked upon it in this article. But insofar as the view that sense-data are
'mental' rests upon physiology, psychology, or metaphysics, I have tried to
show that it rests upon confusions and prejudices - prejudices in favour of
permanence in the ultimate constituents of matter, and confusions derived from
unduly simple notions as to space, from the causal correlation of sense-data
with sense-organs, and from failure to distinguish between sense-data and
sensations. If what we have said on
these subjects is valid, the existence of sense-data is logically independent
of the existence of mind, and is causally dependent upon the body of the
percipient rather than upon his mind.
The causal dependence upon the body of the percipient, we found, is a
more complicated matter than it appears to be, and, like all causal dependence,
is apt to give rise to erroneous beliefs through misconceptions as to the
nature of causal correlation. If we have
been right in our contentions, sense-date are merely those among the ultimate
constituents of the physical world, of which we happen to be immediately aware;
they themselves are purely physical, and all that is mental in connection with
them is our awareness of them, which is irrelevant to their nature and to their
place in physics.
Unduly
simple notions as to space have been a great stumbling-block to realists. When two men look at the same table, it is
supposed that what the one sees and what the other sees are in the same place. Since the shape and colour are not quite the
same for the two men, this raises a difficulty, hastily solved, or rather covered up, by declaring what each sees to be
purely 'subjective' - though it would puzzle those who use this glib word to
say what they mean by it. The truth
seems to be that space - and time also - is much more complicated than it would
appear to be from the finished structure of physics, and that the one
all-embracing three-dimensional space is a logical construction, obtained by
means of correlations from a crude space of six dimensions. The particulars occupying this
six-dimensional space, classified in one way, form 'things', from which, with
certain further manipulations, we can obtain what physics can regard as matter;
classified in another way, they form 'perspectives' and 'biographies', which
may, if a suitable percipient happens to exist, form respectively the
sense-data of a momentary or of a total experience. It is only when physical 'things' have been
dissected into series of classes of particulars, as we have done, that the conflict
between the point of view of physics and the point of view of psychology can be
overcome. This conflict, if what has
been said is not mistaken, flows from different methods of classification, and
vanishes as soon as its source is discovered.
In favour
of the theory which I have briefly outlined, I do not claim that it is certainly
true. Apart from the likelihood of
mistakes, much of it is avowedly hypothetical.
What I do claim for the theory is that it may be true, and that
this is more than can be said for any other theory except the closely analogous
theory of Leibniz. The difficulties
besetting realism, the confusions obstructing any philosophical account of
physics, the dilemma resulting from discrediting sense-data, which yet remain
the sole source of our knowledge of the outer world - all these are avoided by
the theory which I advocate. This does
not prove the theory to be true, since probably many other theories might be
invented which would have the same merits.
But it does prove that the theory has a better chance of being true than
any of its present competitors, and it suggests that
what can be known with certainty is likely to be discoverable by taking our
theory as a starting point, and gradually freeing it from all such assumptions
as seem irrelevant, unnecessary or unfounded.
On these grounds, I recommend it to attention as a hypothesis and a
basis for further work, though not as itself a finished or adequate solution of
the problem with which it deals.
CHAPTER VIII
The Relation of
Sense-data to Physics
I. THE PROBLEM STATED
PHYSICS is said to be an empirical science, based upon
observation and experiment.
It is
supposed to be verifiable, i.e. capable of calculating beforehand results subsequently
confirmed by observation and experiment.
What can we
learn by observation and experiment?
Nothing, so
far as physics is concerned, except immediate data of sense: certain patches of
colour, sounds, tastes, smells, etc., with certain spatio-temporal
relations.
The
supposed contents of the physical world are prima facie very different
from these: molecules have no colour, atoms make no noise, electrons have no
taste, and corpuscles do not even smell.
If such
objects are to be verified, it must be solely through their relation to
sense-data: they must have some kind of correlation with sense-data, and must
be verifiable through their correlation alone.
But how is
the correlation itself ascertained? A
correlation can only be ascertained empirically by the correlated objects
constantly being found together.
But in our case, only one term of the correlation, namely, the sensible
term, is ever found: the other term seems essentially incapable of being
found. Therefore, it would seem, the
correlation with objects of sense, by which physics was to be verified, is
itself utterly and forever unverifiable.
There are
two ways of avoiding this result.
(1) We may
say that we know some principle a priori, without the need of empirical
verification, e.g. that our sense-data have causes other than
themselves, and that something can be known about these causes by inference
from their effects. This way has been
often adopted by philosophers. It may be
necessary to adopt this way to some extent, but insofar as it is adopted
physics ceases to be empirical or based upon experiment and observation
alone. Therefore this way is to be
avoided as much as possible.
(2) We may
succeed in actually defining the objects of physics as functions of
sense-data. Just insofar as physics
leads to expectations, this must be possible, since we can only expect
what can be experienced. And insofar as
the physical state of affairs in inferred from sense-data, it must be capable
of expression as a function of sense-data.
The problem of accomplishing this expression leads to much interesting logico-mathematical work.
In physics
as commonly set forth, sense-data appear as functions of physical objects: when
such-and-such waves impinge upon the eye, we see such-and-such colours, and so
on. But the waves are in fact inferred
from the colours, not vice versa.
Physics cannot be regarded as validly based upon empirical data until
the waves have been expressed as functions of the colours and other sense-data.
Thus if
physics is to be verifiable we are faced with the following problem: Physics
exhibits sense-data as functions of physical objects, but verification is only
possible if physical objects can be exhibited as functions of sense-data. We have therefore to solve the equations
giving sense-data in terms of physical objects, so as to make them instead give
physical objects in terms of sense-data.
II. CHARACTERISTICS OF SENSE-DATA
When I
speak of a 'sense-datum', I do not mean the whole of what is given in sense at
any one time. I mean rather such a part
of the whole as might be singled out by attention: particular patches of
colour, particular noises, and so on.
There is some difficulty in deciding what is to be considered one
sense-datum: often attention causes divisions to appear where, so far as can be
discovered, there were no divisions before.
An observed complex fact, such as that this patch of red is to the left
of that patch of blue, is also to be regarded as a datum from our present point
of view: epistemologically it does not differ greatly from a simple sense-datum
as regards its function in giving knowledge.
Its logical structure is very different, however, from that of
sense: sense gives acquaintance with particulars, and is thus a two-term
relation in which the object can be named but not asserted, and
is inherently incapable of truth or falsehood, whereas the observation of a
complex fact, which may be suitably called perception, is not a two-term
relation, but involves the propositional form on the object-side, and gives
knowledge of a truth, not mere acquaintance with a particular. This logical difference, important as it is,
is not very relevant to our present problem; and it will be convenient to
regard data of perception as included among sense-data for the purposes of this
paper. It is to be observed that the
particulars which are constituents of a datum of perception are always
sense-data in the strict sense.
Concerning
sense-data, we know that they are there while they are data, and this is the
epistemological basis of all our knowledge of external particulars. (The meaning of the word 'external' of course
raises problems which will concern us later.)
We do not know, except by means of more or less precarious inferences,
whether the objects which are at one time sense-data continue to exist at times
when they are not data. Sense-data at
the times when they are data are all that we directly and primitively know of
the external world; hence in epistemology the fact that they are data is
all-important. But the fact that they
are all we directly know gives, of course, no presumption that they are all
that there is. If we could construct an
impersonal metaphysic, independent of the accidents of our knowledge and
ignorance, the privileged position of the actual data would probably disappear,
and they would probably appear as a rather haphazard selection from a mass of
objects more or less like them. In
saying this, I assume only that it is probable that there are particulars with
which we are not acquainted. Thus the
special importance of sense-data is in relation to epistemology, not to
metaphysics. In this respect, physics is
to be reckoned as metaphysics: it is impersonal, and nominally pays no special
attention to sense-data. It is only when
we ask how physics can be known that the importance of sense-data
re-emerges.
III. SENSIBILIA
I shall
give the name sensibilia to those objects
which have the same metaphysical and physical status as sense-data without
necessarily being data to any mind. Thus
the relation of a sensibile to a sense-datum
is like that of a man to a husband: a man becomes a husband by entering into
the relation of marriage, and similarly a sensibile
becomes a sense-datum by entering into the relation of acquaintance. It is important to have both terms; for we
wish to discuss whether an object which is at one time a sense-datum can still exist at a time when it is not a sense-datum. We cannot ask, 'Can sense-data exist without
being given?' for that is like asking, 'Can husbands exist without being
married?' We must ask, 'Can sensibilia exist without being given?' and also 'Can
a particular sensibile be at one time a
sense-datum, and at another not?' Unless
we have the word sensibile as well as the word
'sense-datum', such questions are apt to entangle us in trivial logical
puzzles.
It will be
seen that all sense-data are sensibilia. It is a metaphysical question whether all sensibilia are sense-data, and an epistemological
question whether there exist means of inferring sensibilia
which are not data from those that are.
A few
preliminary remarks, to be amplified as we proceed, will serve to elucidate the
use which I propose to make of sensibilia.
I regard
sense-data as not mental, and as being, in fact, part of the actual
subject-matter of physics. There are
arguments, shortly to be examined, for their subjectivity, but these arguments
seem to me only to prove physiological subjectivity, i.e. causal
dependence on the sense-organs, nerves, and brain. The appearance which a thing presents to us
is causally dependent upon these, in exactly the same way as it is dependent
upon intervening fog or smoke or coloured glass. Both dependencies are contained in the
statement that the appearance which a piece of matter presents when viewed from
a given place is a function not only of the piece of matter, but also of the
'view from a given place', 'appearance', 'intervening medium' - will all be
defined in the course of the present paper.)
We have not the means of ascertaining how things appear from places not
surrounded by brain and nerves and sense-organs, because we cannot leave the
body; but continuity makes it not unreasonable to suppose that they present some
appearance at such places. And such
appearance would be included among sensibilia. If - per impossibile
- there were a complete human body with no mind inside it, all those sensibilia would exist, in relation to that body,
which would be sense-data if there were a mind in the body. What the mind adds to sensibilia,
in fact, is merely awareness: everything else is physical or
physiological.
IV. SENSE-DATA ARE PHYSICAL
Before
discussing this question it will be well to define the sense in which the terms
'mental' and 'physical' are to be used.
The word 'physical', in all preliminary discussions, is to be understood
as meaning 'what is dealt with by physics'.
Physics, it is plain, tells us something about some of the constituents
of the actual world; what these constituents are may be doubtful, but it is
they that are to be called physical, whatever their nature may prove to be.
The
definition of the term 'mental' is more difficult, and can only be
satisfactorily given after many difficult controversies have been discussed and
decided. For present purposes therefore
I must content myself with assuming a dogmatic answer to these
controversies. I shall call a particular
'mental' when it is aware of something, and I shall call a fact 'mental' when
it contains a mental particular as a constituent.
It will be
seen that the mental and the physical are not necessarily mutually exclusive,
although I know of no reason to suppose that they overlap.
The doubt
as to the correctness of our definition of the 'mental' is of little importance
in our present discussion. For what I am
concerned to maintain is that sense-data are physical,
and this being granted it is a matter of indifference in our present inquiry
whether or not they are also mental.
Although I do not hold, with Mach and James and the 'new realists', that
the difference between the mental and the physical is merely one of
arrangement, yet what I have to say in the present paper is compatible with
their doctrine and might have been reached from their standpoint.
In
discussions on sense-data, two questions are commonly confused, namely:
(1) Do
sensible objects persist when we are not sensible of them? in
other words, do sensibilia which are data at a
certain time sometimes continue to exist at times when they are not data? And (2) are sense-data mental or physical?
I propose
to assert that sense-data are physical, while yet maintaining that they
probably never persist unchanged after ceasing to be data. The view that they do not persist is often
thought, quite erroneously in my opinion, to imply that they are mental; and
this has, I believe, been a potent source of confusion in regard to our present
problem. If there were, as some have
held, a logical impossibility in sense-data persisting after ceasing to
be data, that certainly would tend to show that they were mental; but if, as I
contend, their non-persistence is merely a probable inference from empirically
ascertained causal laws, then it carries no such implication with it, and we
are quite free to treat them as part of the subject-matter of physics.
Logically a
sense-datum is an object, a particular of which the subject is aware. It does not contain the subject as a part, as
for example beliefs and volitions do.
The existence of the sense-datum is therefore not logically dependent
upon that of the subject; for the only way, so far as I know, in which the
existence of A can be logically dependent upon the existence of B
is when B is a part of A.
There is therefore no a priori reason why a particular which is a
sense-datum should not persist after it has ceased to be a datum, nor why other
similar particulars should not exist without ever being data. The view that sense-data are mental is
derived, no doubt, in part from their physiological subjectivity, but in part also
from a failure to distinguish between sense-data and 'sensations'. By a sensation I mean the fact consisting in
the subject's awareness of the sense-datum.
Thus a sensation is a complex of which the subject is a constituent and
which therefore is mental. The
sense-datum, on the other hand, stands over against the subject as that
external object of which in sensation the subject is aware. It is true that the sense-datum is in many
cases in the subject's body, but the subject's body is as distinct from the
subject as tables and chairs are, and is in fact merely a part of the material
world. So soon, therefore, as sense-data
are clearly distinguished from sensations, and as their subjectivity is
recognized to be physiological, not physical, the chief obstacles in the way of
regarding them as physical are removed.
V. 'SENSIBILIA' AND 'THINGS'
But if 'sensibilia' are to be recognized as the ultimate
constituents of the physical world, a long a difficult journey is to be
performed before we can arrive either at the 'thing' of common sense or at the
'matter' of physics. The supposed
impossibility of combining the different sense-data which are regarded as
appearances of the same 'thing' to different people has made it seem as though
these 'sensibilia' must be regarded as mere
subjective phantasms. A given table will
present to one man a rectangular appearance, while to another it appears to
have two acute angles and two obtuse angles; to one man it appears brown, while
to another, towards whom it reflects the light, it appears while and shiny. It is said, not wholly without plausibility,
that these different shapes and different colours cannot coexist simultaneously
in the same place, and cannot therefore both be constituents of the physical
world. This argument I must confess
appeared to me until recently to be irrefutable. The contrary opinion has, however, been ably
maintained by Dr T.P. Nunn in an article entitled: 'Are Secondary Qualities
Independent of Perception?' [Proc. Arist.
Soc., 1909-10, pp. 191-218.] The supposed
impossibility derives its apparent force from the phrase: 'in the same
place', and it is precisely in this phrase that its weakness lies. The conception of space is too often treated
in philosophy - even by those who on reflection would not defend such treatment
- as though it were a given, simple, and unambiguous as Kant, in his
psychological innocence, supposed. It is
the unperceived ambiguity of the word 'place' which, as we shall shortly see,
has caused the difficulties to realists and given an undeserved advantage to
their opponents. Two 'places' of
different kinds are involved in every sense-datum, namely the place at
which it appears and the place from which it appears. These belong to different spaces, although,
as we shall see, it is possible, with certain limitations, to establish a
correlation between them. What we call
the different appearances of the same thing to different observers are each in a space private to the observer concerned. No place in the private world of one observer
is identical with a place in the private world of another observer. There is therefore no question of combining
the different appearances in the one place; and the fact that they cannot all
exist in one place affords accordingly no ground whatever for questioning their
physical reality. The 'thing' of common
sense may in fact be identified with the whole class of its appearances -
where, however, we must include among appearances not only those which are
actual sense-data, but also those 'sensibilia', if
any, which, on grounds of continuity and resemblance, are to be regarded as
belonging to the same system of appearances, although there happen to be no
observers to whom they are data.
An example
may make this clearer. Suppose there are
a number of people in a room, all seeing, as they say, the same tables and
chairs, walls and pictures. No two of
these people have exactly the same sense-data, yet there is sufficient
similarity among their data to enable them to group together certain of these
data in appearances of one 'thing' to the several spectators, and others as
appearances of another 'thing'. Besides
the appearances which a given thing in the room presents to the actual
spectators, there are, we may suppose, other appearances which it would present
to other possible spectators. If a man
were to sit down between two others, the appearance which the room would
present to him would be intermediate between the appearances which it presents
to the two others: and although this appearance would not exist as it is
without the sense organs, nerves and brain, of the newly arrived spectator,
still it is not unnatural to suppose that, from the position which he now
occupies, some appearance of the room existed before his arrival. This supposition, however, need merely be
noticed and not insisted upon.
Since the
'thing' cannot, without indefensible partiality, be identified with any single
one of its appearances, it came to be thought of as something distinct from all
of them and underlying them. But by the
principle of Occam's razor, if the class of
appearances will fulfil the purposes for the sake of which the thing was
invented by the prehistoric metaphysicians to whom common sense is due, economy
demands that we should identify the thing with the class of its appearances. It is not necessary to deny a
substance or substratum underlying these appearances; it is merely expedient to
abstain from asserting this unnecessary entity.
Our procedure here is precisely analogous to that which has swept away
from the philosophy of mathematics the useless menagerie of metaphysical
monsters with which it used to be infested.
VI. CONSTRUCTIONS VERSES INFERENCES
Before
proceeding to analyse and explain the ambiguities of the word 'place', a few
general remarks on method are desirable.
The supreme maxim in scientific philosophizing is this:
Wherever
possible, logical constructions are to be substituted for inferred entities.
Some
examples of the substitution of construction for inference in the realm of
mathematical philosophy may serve to elucidate the uses of this maxim. Take first the case of irrationals. In old days, irrationals were inferred as the
supposed limits of series of rationals which had no
rational limit; but the objection to this procedure was that it left the existence
of irrationals merely optative, and for this reason
the stricter methods of the present day no longer tolerate such a
definition. We now define an irrational
number as a certain class of ratios, thus constructing it logically by means of
ratios, instead of arriving at it by doubtful inference from them. Take again the case of cardinal numbers. Two equally numerous collections appear to
have something in common: this something is supposed to be their cardinal
number. But so long as the cardinal
number is inferred from the collections, not constructed in terms of them, its
existence must remain in doubt, unless in virtue of a metaphysical postulate ad
hoc. By defining the cardinal number
of a given collection as the class of all equally numerous collections, we
avoid the necessity of this metaphysical postulate, and thereby remove a
needless element of doubt from the philosophy of arithmetic. A similar method, as I have shown elsewhere,
can be applied to classes themselves, which need not be supposed to have any
metaphysical reality, but can be regarded as symbolically constructed fictions.
The method
by which the construction proceeds is closely analogous in these and all
similar cases. Given a set of
propositions nominally dealing with the supposed inferred entities, we observe
the properties which are required of the supposed entities in order to make
these propositions true. By dint of a
little logical ingenuity, we then construct some logical function of less
hypothetical entities which has the requisite properties. This constructed functions we substitute for
the supposed inferred entities, and thereby obtain a new and less doubtful
interpretation of the body of propositions in question. This method, so fruitful in the philosophy of
mathematics, will be found equally applicable in the philosophy of physics,
where, I do not doubt, it would have been applied long ago but for the fact
that all who have studied this subject hitherto have been completely ignorant
of mathematical logic. I myself cannot
claim originality in the application of this method to physics, since I owe the
suggestion and the stimulus for its application entirely to my friend and
collaborator Dr Whitehead, who is engaged in applying
it to the more mathematical portions of the region intermediate between
sense-data and the points, instants and particles of physics.
A complete
application of the method which substitutes constructions for inferences would
exhibit matter wholly in terms of sense-data, and even, we may add, of the sense-data
of a single person, since the sense-data of others cannot be known without some
element of inference. This, however,
must remain for the present an ideal, to be approached as nearly as possible,
but to be reached, if at all, only after a long preliminary labour of which as
yet we can only see the very beginning.
The inferences which are unavoidable can, however, be subjected to
certain guiding principles. In the first
place, they should always be made perfectly explicit, and should be formulated
in the most general manner possible. In
the second place, the inferred entities should, whenever this can be done, be
similar to those whose existence is given, rather than, like the Kantian ding
an sich, something
wholly remote from the data which nominally support the inference. The inferred entities which I shall allow
myself are of two kinds: (a) the sense-data of other people, in favour
of which there is the evidence of testimony, resting ultimately upon the
analogical argument in favour of minds other than my own; (b) the 'sensibilia' which would appear from places where there
happen to be no minds, and which I suppose to be real although they are
no-one's data. Of these two classes of
inferred entities, the first will probably be allowed to pass
unchallenged. It would give me the
greatest satisfaction to be able to dispense with it, and thus establish
physics upon a solipsistic basis; but those - and I fear they are the majority
- in whom the human affections are stronger than the desire for logical
economy, will, no doubt, not share my desire to render solipsism scientifically
satisfactory. The second class of
inferred entities raises much more serious questions. It may be thought monstrous to maintain that
a thing can present any appearance at all in a place where no sense organs and
nervous structure exist through which it would appear. I do not myself feel the monstrosity;
nevertheless I should regard these supposed appearances only in the light of a hypothetical
scaffolding, to be used while the edifice of physics is being raised, though
possibly capable of being removed as soon as the edifice is completed. These 'sensibilia'
which are not data to anyone are therefore to be taken rather as an
illustrative hypothesis and as an aid in preliminary statement than as a
dogmatic part of the philosophy of physics in its final form.
VII. PRIVATE SPACE AND THE SPACE OF
PERSPECTIVES
We have now
to explain the ambiguity in the world 'place', and how it comes that two places
of different sorts are associated with every sense-datum, namely the place at
which it is and the place from which it is perceived. The theory to be advocated is closely
analogous to Leibniz's monadology, from which it
differs chiefly in being less smooth and tidy.
The first fact
to notice is that, so far as can be discovered, no 'sensibile'
is ever a datum to two people at once.
The things seen by two different people are often closely similar, so
similar that the same words can be used to denote them, without which
communication with others concerning sensible objects would be impossible. But, in spite of this similarity, it would
seem that some difference always arises from difference in the point of view. Thus each person, so far as his sense-data
are concerned, lives in a private world.
This private world contains its own space, or rather spaces, for it
would seem that only experience teaches us to correlate the space of sight with
the space of touch and with the various other spaces of other senses. This multiplicity of private spaces, however,
though interesting to the psychologist, is of no great importance in regard to
our present problem, since a merely solipsistic experience enables us to
correlate them into the one private space which embraces all our own sense-data. The place at which a sense-datum is, is a place in private space. This place therefore is different from any
place in the private space of another percipient. For if we assume, as logical economy demands, that all position is relative, a place is only
definable by the things in or around it, and therefore the same place cannot
occur in two private worlds which have no common constituent. The question, therefore, of combining what we
call different appearances of the same thing in the same place does not arise,
and the fact that a given object appears to different spectators to have
different shapes and colours affords no argument against the physical reality
of all these shapes and colours.
In addition
to the private spaces belonging to the private worlds of different percipients,
there is, however, another space, in which one whole private world counts as a
point, or at least as a spatial unit.
This might be described as the space of points of view, since each
private world may be regarded as the appearance which the universe presents
from a certain point of view. I prefer,
however, to speak of it as the space of perspectives, in order to
obviate the suggestion that a private world is only real when someone views
it. And for the same reason, when I wish
to speak of a private world without assuming a percipient, I shall call it a
'perspective'.
We have now
to explain how the different perspectives are ordered in one space. This is effected by
means of the correlated 'sensibilia' which are
regarded as the appearances, in different perspectives, of one and the same
thing. By moving, and by testimony, we
discover that two different perspectives, though they cannot both contain the
same 'sensibilia', may nevertheless contain very
similar ones; and the spatial order of a certain group of 'sensibilia'
in a private space of one perspective is found to be identical with, or very
similar to, the spatial order of the correlated 'sensibilia'
in the private space of another perspective.
In this way one 'sensibile' in one perspective
is correlated with one 'sensibile' in another. Such correlated 'sensibilia'
will be called 'appearances of the thing'.
In Leibniz's monadology, since each monad
mirrored the whole universe, there was in each perspective a 'sensibile' which was an appearance of each thing. In our system of perspectives, we make no
such assumption of completeness. A given
thing will have appearances in some perspectives, but presumably not in certain
others. The 'thing' being defined as the
class of its appearances, if k is the class of perspectives in which a certain thing
q appears, then q is a member of
the multiplicative class of k, k being a class of mutually exclusive classes of 'sensibilia'. And similarly a perspective is a member of
the multiplicative class of the things which appear in it.
The
arrangement of perspectives in a space is effected by means of the differences
between the appearances of a given thing in the various perspectives. Suppose, say, that a certain penny appears in
a number of different perspectives; in some it looks larger and in some
smaller, in some it looks circular, in others it presents the appearance of an
ellipse of varying eccentricity. We may
collect together all those perspectives in which the appearance of the penny is
circular. These we will place on one
straight line, ordering them in a series by the variations in the apparent size
of the penny. Those perspectives in
which the penny appears in a straight line of a certain thickness will
similarly be placed upon a plane (though in this case there will be many
different perspectives in which the penny is of the same size; when one
arrangement is completed these will form a circle concentric with the penny),
and ordered as before by the apparent size of the penny. By such means, all those perspectives in
which the penny presents a visual appearance can be arranged in a
three-dimensional spatial order.
Experience shows that the same spatial order of perspectives would have
resulted if, instead of the penny, we had chosen any other thing which appeared
in all the perspectives in question, or any other method of utilizing the
differences between the appearances of the same things in different
perspectives. It is this empirical fact
which has made it possible to construct the one all-embracing space of physics.
The space
whose construction has just been explained, and whose elements are whole
perspectives, will be called 'perspective-space'.
VIII. THE PLACING OF 'THINGS' AND
'SENSIBILIA' IN PERSPECTIVE SPACE
The world
which we have so far constructed is a world of six dimensions, since it is a
three-dimensional series of perspectives, each of which is itself
three-dimensional. We have now to
explain the correlation between the perspective space and the various private
spaces contained within the various perspectives severally. It is by means of this correlation that the
one three-dimensional space of physics is constructed; and it is because of the
unconscious performance of this correlation that the distinction between
perspective space and the percipient's private space has been blurred, with
disastrous results for the philosophy of physics. Let us revert to our penny: the perspectives
in which the penny appears larger are regarded as being nearer to the penny
than those in which its appears smaller, but as far as experience goes the
apparent size of the penny will not grow beyond a certain limit, namely, that
where (as we say) the penny is so near the eye that if it were any nearer it
could not be seen. By touch we may
prolong the series until the penny touches the eye, but no further. If we have been travelling along a line of
perspectives in the previously defined sense, we may, however, by imagining the
penny removed, prolong the line of perspectives by means, say, of another
penny; and the same may be done with any other line of perspectives defined by
means of the penny. All these lines meet
in a certain place, that is, in a certain perspective. This perspective will be defined as 'the
place where the penny is'.
It is now
evident in what sense two places in constructed physical space are associated
with a given 'sensibile'. There is first the place which is the
perspective of which the 'sensibile' is a
member. This is the place from which
the 'sensibile' appears. Secondly there is the place where the other
thing is of which the 'sensibile' is a member, in
other words an appearance; this is the place at which the 'sensibile' appears.
The 'sensibile' which is a member of one
perspective is correlated with another perspective, namely, that which is the
place where the thing is of which the 'sensibile' is
an appearance. To the psychologist the
'place from which' is the more interesting, and the 'sensibile'
accordingly appears to him subjective and where the percipient is. To the physicist the 'place at which' is the
more interesting, and the 'sensibile' accordingly
appears to him physical and external.
The causes, limits and partial justification of each of these two
apparently incompatible views are evident from the above duplicity of places
associated with a given 'sensibile'.
We have
seen that we can assign to a physical thing a place in the perspective
space. In this way different parts of
our body acquire positions in perspective space, and therefore there is a
meaning (whether true or false need not much concern us) in saying that the
perspective to which our sense-data belong is inside our head. Since our mind is correlated with the perspective
to which our sense-data belong, we may regard this perspective as being the
position of our mind in perspective space.
If, therefore, this perspective is, in the above-defined sense, inside
our head, there is a good meaning for the statement that the mind is in the
head. We can now say of the various
appearances of a given thing that some of them are nearer to the thing than
others; those are nearer which belong to perspectives that are nearer to 'the
place where the things is'. We can thus
find a meaning, true or false, for the statement that more is to be learnt
about a thing by examining it close to than by viewing it from a distance. We can also find a meaning for the phrase,
'the things which intervene between the subject and a thing of which an
appearance is a datum to him'. One reason
often alleged for the subjectivity of sense-data is that the appearance of a
thing may change when we find it hard to suppose that the thing itself has
changed - for example, when the change is due to our shutting our eyes, or to
our screwing them up so as to make the thing look double. If the thing is defined as the class of its
appearances (which is the definition adopted above), there is of course
necessarily some change in the thing whenever any one of its appearances
chance. Nevertheless there is a very
important distinction between two different ways in which the appearances may
change. If after looking at a thing I
shut my eyes, the appearance of my eyes changes in every perspective in which
there is such an appearance, whereas most of the appearances of the thing will
remain unchanged. We may say, as a
matter of definition, that a thing changes when, however near to the thing an
appearance of it may be, there are changes in appearance as near as, or still
nearer to, the thing. On the other hand,
we shall say that the change is in some other thing if all appearances of the
thing which are at not more than a certain distance from the thing remain
unchanged, while only comparatively distant appearances of the thing are
altered. From this consideration we are
naturally led to consideration of matter, which must be our next topic.
IX. THE DEFINITION OF MATTER
We defined
the 'physical thing' as the class of its appearances, but this can hardly be
taken as a definition of matter. We want
to be able to express the fact that the appearance of a thing in a given
perspective is causally affected by the matter between the thing and the
perspective. We have found a meaning for
'between a thing and a perspective'. But
we want matter to be something other than the whole class of appearances of a
thing, in order to state the influence of matter on appearances.
We commonly
assume that the information we get about a thing is more accurate when the
thing is nearer. Far off, we see it is a
man; then we see it is Jones; then we see he is smiling. Complete accuracy would only be attainable as
a limit: if the appearances of Jones as we approach him tend towards a limit,
that limit may be taken to be what Jones really is. It is obvious that from the point of view of
physics the appearances of a thing close to 'count' more than the appearances
far off. We may therefore set up the
following tentative definition:
The matter
of a given thing is the limit of its appearances as their distance from the
thing diminishes.
It seems
probable that there is something in this definition, but it is not quite
satisfactory, because empirically there is no such limit to be obtained from
sense-data. The definition will have to
be eked out by constructions and definitions.
But probably it suggests the right direction in which to look.
We are now
in a position to understand in outline the reverse journey from matter to
sense-data which is performed by physics.
The appearance of a thing in a given perspective is a function of the
matter composing the thing and of the intervening matter. The appearance of a thing is altered by
intervening smoke or mist, by blue spectacles or by alterations in the
sense-organs or nerves of the percipient (which also must be reckoned as part
of the intervening medium). The nearer
we approach to the thing, the less its appearance is affected by the
intervening matter. As we travel further
and further from the thing, its appearances diverge more and more from their
initial character; and the causal laws of their divergence are to be stated in
terms of the matter which lies between them and the thing. Since the appearances at very small distances
are less affected by causes other than the thing itself, we come to think that
the limit towards which these appearances tend as the distance diminishes is
what the thing 'really is', as opposed to what it merely seems to be. This, together with its necessity for the
statement of causal laws, seems to be the source of the entirely erroneous
feeling that matter is more 'real' than sense-data.
Consider
for example the infinite divisibility of matter. In looking at a given thing and approaching
it, one sense-datum will become several, and each of these will again
divide. Thus one appearance may
represent many things, and to this process there seems no end. Hence in the limit, when we approach
indefinitely near to the thing, there will be an indefinite number of units of
matter corresponding to what, at a finite distance, is only one appearance. This is
how infinite divisibility arises.
The whole
causal efficacy of a thing resides in its matter. This is in some sense an empirical fact, but
it would be hard to state it precisely, because 'causal efficacy' is difficult
to define.
What can be
known empirically about the matter of a thing is only approximate, because we
cannot get to know the appearances of the thing from very small distances, and
cannot accurately infer the limit of these appearances. But it is inferred approximately
by means of the appearances we can observe.
It then turns out that these appearances can be exhibited by physics as
a function of the matter in our immediate neighbourhood; e.g. the visual
appearance of a distant object is a function of the light-waves that reach the
eyes. This leads to confusions of
thought, but offers no real difficulty.
One
appearance, of a visible object for example, is not sufficient to determine its
other simultaneous appearances, although it goes a certain distance towards
determining them. The determination of
the hidden structure of a thing, so far as it is possible at all, can only be
effected by means of elaborate dynamical inferences.
X. TIME
[On this subject, compare A Theory of Time and Space, by Mr A.A. Robb (Camb. Univ. Press), which first suggested to me the views advocated here, though I have, for present purposes, omitted what is most interesting and novel in his theory. Mr Robb has given a sketch of his theory in a pamphlet with the same title (Heffer and Sons, Cambridge, 1913).]
It seems
that the one all-embracing time is a construction, like the one all-embracing
space. Physics itself has become
conscious of this fact through the discussions connected with relativity.
Between two
perspectives which both belong to one person's experience, there will be a
direct time-relation of before and after.
This suggests a way of dividing history in the same sort of way as it is
divided by different experiences, but without introducing experience or anything
mental: we may define a 'biography' as everything that is (directly) earlier or
later than, or simultaneous with, a given 'sensibile'. This will give a series of perspectives,
which might all form parts of one person's experience, though it is not necessary
that all or any of them should actually do so.
By this means, the history of the world is divided into a number of
mutually exclusive biographies.
We have now
to correlate the times in the different biographies. The natural thing would be to say that the appearance of a given (momentary) thing in two different
perspectives belonging to different biographies are to be taken as
simultaneous; but this is not convenient.
Suppose A shouts to B, and B replies as soon as he
hears A's shout. Then between A's
hearing of his own shout and his hearing of B's there is an interval;
thus if we made A's and B's hearing of the same shout exactly
simultaneous with each other, we should have events exactly simultaneous with a
given event but not with each other. To
obviate this, we assume a 'velocity of sound'.
That is, we assume that the time when B hears A's shout is
half-way between the time when A hears his own shout and the time when
he hears B's. In this way the
correlation is effected.
What has
been said about sound applies of course equally to light. The general principle is that the
appearances, in different perspectives, which are to be grouped together as
constituting what a certain thing is at a certain moment, are not to be all
regarded as being at that moment. On the
contrary, they spread outward from the thing with various velocities according
to the nature of the appearances. Since
no direct means exist of correlating the time in one biography with the
time in another, this temporal grouping of the appearances belonging to a given
thing at a given moment in part conventional.
Its motive is partly to secure the verification of such maxims as that events which are exactly simultaneous with the same
event are exactly simultaneous with one another, partly to secure convenience
in the formulation of causal laws.
XI. THE PERSISTENCE OF THINGS AND MATTER
Apart from
any of the fluctuating hypotheses of physics, three main problems arise in
connecting the world of physics with the world of sense, namely:
1. the construction of a single space;
2. the construction of a single time;
3. the construction of permanent things or matter.
We have
already considered the first and second of these problems; it remains to
consider the third.
We have seen
how correlated appearances in different perspectives are combined to form one
'thing' at one moment in the all-embracing time of physics. We have now to consider how appearances at
different times are combined as belonging to one 'thing', and how we arrive at
the persistent 'matter' of physics. The
assumption of permanent substance, which technically underlies the procedure of
physics, cannot of course be regarded as metaphysically legitimate: just as the
one thing simultaneously seen by many people is a construction, so the one
thing seen at different times by the same or different people must be a
construction, being in fact nothing but a certain grouping of certain 'sensibilia'.
We have
seen that the momentary state of a 'thing' is an assemblage of 'sensibilia', in different perspectives, not all
simultaneous in the one constructed time, but spreading out from 'the place
where the thing is' with velocities depending upon the nature of the 'sensibilia'. The
time at which the 'thing' is in this state is the lower limit of the
times at which these appearances occur.
We have now to consider what leads us to speak of another set of
appearances as belonging to the same 'thing' at a different time.
For this
purpose, we may, at least to begin with, confine ourselves within a single
biography. If we can always say when two
'sensibilia' in a given biography are appearances of
one thing, then, since we have seen how to connect 'sensibilia'
in different biographies as appearances of the same momentary state of a thing,
we shall have all that is necessary for the complete construction of the
history of a thing.
It is to be
observed, to begin with, that the identity of a thing for common sense is not
always correlated with the identity of matter for physics. A human body is one persisting thing for
common sense, but for physics its matter is constantly changing. We may say, broadly, that the common-sense
conception is based upon continuity in appearances at the ordinary distances of
sense-data, while the physical conception is based upon the continuity of
appearances at very small distances from the thing. It is probable that the common-sense
conception is not capable of complete precision. Let us therefore concentrate our attention
upon the conception of the persistence of matter in physics.
The first
characteristic of two appearances of the same piece of matter at different
times is continuity. The two
appearances must be connected by a series of intermediaries, which, if time and
space form compact series, must themselves form a compact series. The colour of the leaves is different in
autumn from what it is in summer; but we believe that the change occurs
gradually, and that, if the colours are different at two given times, there are
intermediate times at which the colours are intermediate between those at the
given times.
But there
are two considerations that are important as regards continuity.
First, it
is largely hypothetical. We do not
observe any one thing continuously, and it is merely a hypothesis to assume
that, while we are not observing it, it passes through conditions intermediate
between those in which it is perceived.
During uninterrupted observation, it is true, continuity is nearly
verified; but even here, when motions are very rapid, as in the case of
explosions, the continuity is not actually capable of direct verification. Thus we can only say that the sense-data are
found to permit a hypothetical complement of 'sensibilia'
such as will preserve continuity, and that therefore there may be such a
complement. Since, however, we have
already made such use of hypothetical 'sensibilia',
we will let this point pass, and admit such 'sensibilia'
as are required to preserve continuity.
Secondly, continuity
is not a sufficient criterion of material identity. It is true that in many cases, such as rocks,
mountains, tables, chairs, etc., where the appearances change slowly,
continuity is sufficient, but in other cases, such as the parts of an approximately
homogeneous fluid, it fails us utterly.
We can travel by sensibly continuous gradations from any one drop of the
sea at any one time to any other drop at any other time. We infer the motions of seawater from the
effects of the current, but they cannot be inferred from direct sensible
observation together with the assumption of continuity.
The
characteristic required in addition to continuity is conformity with the laws
of dynamics. Starting from what common
sense regards as persistent things, and making only such modifications as from
time to time seem reasonable, we arrive at assemblages of 'sensibilia'
which are found to obey certain simple laws, namely those of dynamics. By regarding 'sensibilia'
at different times as belonging to the same piece of matter, we are able to
define motion, which presupposes the assumption or construction of
something persisting throughout the time of motion. The motions which are regarded as occurring,
during a period in which all the 'sensibilia' and the
times of their appearance are given, will be different according to the manner
in which we combine 'sensibilia' at different times
as belonging to the same piece of matter.
Thus even when the whole history of the world is given
in every particular, the question what motions take place is still to a certain
extent arbitrary even after the assumption of continuity. Experience shows that it is possible to
determine motions in such a way as to satisfy the laws of dynamics, and that
this determination, roughly and on the whole, is fairly in agreement with the
common-sense opinions about persistent things.
This determination, therefore, is adopted, and leads to a criterion by
which we can determine, sometimes practically, sometimes only theoretically,
whether two appearances at different times are to be regarded as belonging to
the same piece of matter. The
persistence of all matter throughout all time can, I imagine, be secured by
definition.
To
recommend this conclusion, we must consider what it is that is proved by the
empirical success of physics. What is
proved is that its hypotheses, though unverifiable where they go beyond
sense-data, are at no point in contradiction with sense-data, but, on the
contrary, are ideally such as render all sense-data calculable when a
sufficient collection of 'sensibilia' is given. Now physics has found it empirically possible
to collect sense-data into series, each series being regarded as belonging to
one 'thing', and behaving, with regard to the laws of physics, in a way in which
series not belonging to one thing would in general not behave. If it is to be unambiguous whether two
appearances belong to the same thing or not, there must be only one way of
grouping appearances so that the resulting things obey the laws of physics. It would be very difficult to prove that this
is the case, but for our present purposes we may let this point pass, and
assume that there is only one way. Thus
we may lay down the following definition: Physical things are those series
of appearances whose matter obeys the laws of physics. That such series exist is an empirical fact,
which constitutes the verifiability of physics.
XII. ILLUSIONS, HALLUCINATIONS, AND DREAMS
It remains
to ask how, in our system, we are to find a place for sense-data which
apparently fail to have the usual connection with the world of physics. Such sense-data are of various kinds,
requiring somewhat different treatment.
But all are of the sort that would be called 'unreal', and therefore,
before embarking upon the discussion, certain logical remarks must be made upon
the conception of reality and unreality.
Mr A. Wolf ['Natural Realism and
Present Tendencies in Philosophy', Proc. Arist.
Soc., 1908-09, p. 165.] says:
'The
conception of mind as a system of transparent activities is, I think, also
untenable because of its failure to account for the very possibility of dreams
and hallucinations. It seems impossible
to realize how a bare, transparent activity can be directed to what is not
there, to apprehend what is not given.'
This
statement is one which, probably, most people would endorse. But it is open to two objections. First, it is difficult to see how an
activity, however un-'transparent', can be directed towards a nothing: a term
of a relation cannot be a mere nonentity.
Secondly, no reason is given, and I am convinced that none can be given,
for the assertion that dream-objects are not 'there' and not 'given'. Let us take the second point first.
(1) The
belief that dream-objects are not given comes, I think, from failure to
distinguish, as regards waking life, between the sense-datum and the
corresponding 'thing'. In dreams, there
is no such corresponding 'thing' as the dreamer supposes; if, therefore, the
'thing' were given in waking life, as, e.g. Meinong
maintains, [Die Erfahrungsgrundlagen Useres Wissens, p. 28.] then there would be a different in respect of givenness between dreams and waking life. But if, as we have maintained, what is given
is never the thing, then what we apprehend in a dream is just as much given as
what we apprehend in waking life.
Exactly the
same argument applies as to the dream-objects being 'there'. They have their position in the private space
of the perspective of the dreamer; where they fail is in their correlation with
other private spaces and therefore with perspective space. But in the only sense in which 'there' can be
a datum, they are 'there' just as truly as any of the sense-data of waking
life.
(2) The
conception of 'illusion' or 'unreality', and the correlative conception of
'reality', are generally used in a way which embodies
profound logical confusions. Words that
go in pairs, such as 'real' and 'unreal', 'existent' and 'non-existent',
'valid' and 'invalid', etc., are all derived from the one fundamental pair,
'true' and 'false'. Now 'true' and
'false' are applicable only - except in derivative significations - to propositions. Thus whenever the above pairs can be
significantly applied, we must be dealing either with propositions or with such
incompatible phrases as only acquire meaning when put into a context which,
with them, forms a proposition. Thus
such pairs of words can be applied to descriptions, [Cf. Principia
Mathematica, Vol. I,* 14, and
Introduction, Chap. III. For the definition of existence, cf.*
14.02.] For the definition of
'existence', cf. * 14.02.but not to proper
names: in other words, they have no application whatever to data, but only to
entities or non-entities described in terms of data.
Let us
illustrate by the terms 'existence' and 'non-existence'. Given any datum x, it is meaningless
either to assert or to deny that x 'exists'. We might be tempted to say: 'Of course x
exists, for otherwise it could not be a datum'.
But such a statement is really meaningless, although it is significant
and true to say, 'My present sense-datum exists', and it may also be true that
'x is my present sense-datum'.
The inference from these two propositions to 'x exists' is one
which seems irresistible to people unaccustomed to logic; yet the apparent
proposition inferred is not merely false, but strictly meaningless. To say 'My present sense-datum exists' is to
say (roughly): 'There is an object of which "my present sense-datum"
is a description'. But we cannot say:
'There is an object of which "x" is a description,' because 'x
is (in the case we are supposing) a name, not a description. Dr Whitehead and I
have explained this point fully elsewhere (loc. cit.) with the help of
symbols, without which it is hard to understand; I shall not therefore here
repeat the demonstration of the above propositions, but shall proceed with
their application to our present problem.
The fact
that 'existence' is only applicable to descriptions is concealed by the use of
what are grammatically proper names in a way which really transforms them into
descriptions. It is, for example, a
legitimate question whether Homer existed; but here 'Homer' means 'the author
of the Homeric poems', and is a description.
Similarly we may ask whether God exists; but then 'God' means 'the
Supreme Being' or 'the ens realissimum' or whatever other description we may
prefer. If 'God' were a proper name, God
would have to be a datum; and then no question could arise as to His
existence. The distinction between
existence and other predicates, which Kant obscurely felt, is brought to light
by the theory of descriptions, and is seen to remove 'existence' altogether
from the fundamental notions of metaphysics.
What has
been said about 'existence' applies equally to 'reality', which may, in fact,
be taken as synonymous with 'existence'.
Concerning the immediate objects in illusions, hallucinations, and
dreams, it is meaningless to ask whether they 'exist' or are 'real'. There they are, and that ends the
matter. But we may legitimately inquire
as to the existence or reality of 'things' or other 'sensibilia'
inferred from such objects. It is the
unreality of these 'things' and other 'sensibilia',
together with a failure to notice that they are not data, which has led to the
view that the objects of dreams are unreal.
We may now
apply these considerations in detail to the stock arguments against realism,
though what is to be said will be mainly a repetition of what others have said
before.
(1) We have
first the variety of normal appearances, supposed to be incompatible. This is the case of the different shapes and
colours which a given thing presents to different spectators. Locke's water which seems both hot and cold
belongs to this class of cases. Our
system of different perspectives fully accounts for these cases, and shows that
they afford no argument against realism.
(2) We have
cases where the correlation between different senses is unusual. The bent stick in water belongs here. People say it looks bent but is straight: this
only means that it is straight to the touch, though bent in sight. There is no 'illusion', but only a false
inference, if we think that the stick would feel bent to the touch. The stick would look just as bent in a
photograph, and, as Mr Gladstone used to say, 'the photograph cannot lie'.
[Cf., Edwin B. Holt, The Place of Illusory Experience in a Realistic World,
'The New Realism', p. 305, both on this point and as regards seeing double.] The case of seeing double also belongs here, though
in this case the cause of the unusual correlation is physiological, and would
therefore not operate in a photograph.
It is a mistake to ask whether the 'thing' is duplicated when we see it
double. The 'thing' is a whole system of
'sensibilia', and it is only those visual 'sensibilia' which are data to the percipient that are
duplicated. The phenomenon has a purely
physiological explanation; indeed, in view of our having two eyes, it is in
less need of explanation than the single visual sense-datum which we normally
obtain from the things on which we focus.
(3) We come
now to cases like dreams, which may, at the moment of dreaming, contain nothing
to arouse suspicion, but are condemned on the ground of their supposed
incompatibility with earlier and later data.
Of course it often happens that dream-objects fail to behave in the
accustomed manner: heavy objects fly, solid objects melt, babies turn into pigs
or undergo even greater changes. But
none of these unusual occurrences need happen in a dream, and it is not
on account of such occurrences that dream-objects are called 'unreal'. It is their lack of continuity with the
dreamer's past and future that makes him, when he wakes, condemn them; and it
is their lack of correlation with other private worlds that makes others
condemn them. Omitting the latter
ground, our reason for condemning them is that the 'things' which we infer from
them cannot be combined according to the laws of physics with the 'things'
inferred from waking sense-data. This
might be used to condemn the 'things' inferred from the data of dreams. Dream-data are no doubt appearances of
'things', but not of such 'things' as the dreamer supposes. I have no wish to combat psychological
theories of dreams, such as those of the psychoanalysts. But there certainly are cases where (whatever
psychological causes may contribute) the presence of physical causes also is
very evident. For instance, a door
banging may produce a dream of a naval engagement, with images of battleships
at sea and smoke. The whole dream will
be an appearance of the door banging, but owing to the peculiar condition of
the body (especially the brain) during sleep, this appearance is not that
expected to be produced by a door banging, and thus the dreamer is led to
entertain false beliefs. But his
sense-data are still physical, and are such as a completed physics would
include and calculate.
(4) The
last class of illusions are those which cannot be discovered within one
person's experience, except through the discovery of discrepancies with the
experiences of others. Dreams might
conceivably belong to this class, if they were jointed sufficiently neatly into
waking life; but the chief instances are recurrent sensory hallucinations of
the kind that lead to insanity. What
makes the patient, in such cases, become what others call insane is the fact
that, within his own experience, there is nothing to show that the
hallucinatory sense-data do not have the usual kind of connection with 'sensibilia' in other perspectives. Of course he may learn this through
testimony, but he probably finds it simpler to suppose that the testimony is
untrue and that he is being wilfully deceived.
There is, so far as I can see, no theoretical criterion by which the
patient can decide, in such a case, between the two equally satisfactory
hypotheses of his madness and of his friends' mendacity.
From the
above instances it would appear that abnormal sense-data, of the kind which we
regard as deceptive, have intrinsically just the same status as any others, but
differ as regards their correlations or causal connections with other 'sensibilia' and with 'things'. Since the usual correlations and connections
become part of our unreflective expectations, and even seem, except to the
psychologist, to form part of our data, it comes to be thought, mistakenly,
that in such cases the data are unreal, whereas they are merely the causes of
false inferences. The fact that
correlations and connections of unusual kinds occur adds to the difficulty of
inferring things from sense and of expressing physics in terms of
sense-data. But the unusualness would
seem to be always physically or physiologically explicable, and therefore
raises only a complication, not a philosophical objection.
I conclude,
therefore, that no valid objection exists to the view which regards sense-data
as part of the actual substance of the physical world, and that,
on the other hand, this view is the only one which accounts for the empirical
verifiability of physics. In the present
paper, I have given only a rough preliminary sketch. In particular, the part played by time
in the construction of the physical world is, I think, more fundamental than
would appear from the above account. I
should hope that, with further elaboration, the part played by unperceived 'sensibilia' could be indefinitely diminished, probably by
invoking the history of a 'thing' to eke out the inferences derivable from its
momentary appearance.
CHAPTER IX
On the Notion of
Cause
IN the following paper I wish, first, to maintain that
the word 'cause' is so inextricably bound up with misleading associations as to
make its complete extrusion from the philosophical vocabulary desirable;
secondly, to inquire what principle, if any, is employed in science in place of
the supposed 'law of causality' which philosophers imagine to be employed;
thirdly, to exhibit certain confusions, especially in regard to teleology and
determinism, which appear to me to be connected with erroneous notions as to
causality.
All
philosophers, of every school, imagine that causation is one of the fundamental
axioms or postulates of science, yet, oddly enough, in advanced sciences such
as gravitational astronomy, the word 'cause' never occurs. Dr James Ward, in his Naturalism and
Agnosticism, makes this a ground of complaint against physics: the business
of those who wish to ascertain the ultimate truth about the world, he
apparently thinks, should be the discovery of causes, yet physics never even
seeks them. To me it seems that
philosophy ought not to assume such legislative functions, and that the reason
why physics has ceased to look for causes is that, in fact, there are no such
things. The law of causality, I believe,
like much that passes muster among philosophers, is a relic of a bygone age,
surviving, like the monarchy, only because it is erroneously supposed to do no
harm.
In order to
find out what philosophers commonly understand by 'cause', I consulted
Baldwin's Dictionary, and was rewarded beyond my expectations, for I
found the following three mutually incompatible definitions:
'CAUSALITY. (1) The necessary connection of events in the
time-series....
'CAUSE (notion of). Whatever may be included in the
thought or perception of a process as taking place in consequence of another
process....
'CAUSE AND EFFECT. (1) Cause and effect ... are
correlative terms denoting any two distinguishable things, phrases, or aspects
of reality, which are so related to each other that whenever the first ceases
to exist the second comes into existence immediately after, and whenever the
second comes into existence, the first has ceased to exist immediately before.'
Let us
consider these three definitions in turn.
The first, obviously, is unintelligible without a definition of
'necessary'. Under this head, Baldwin's Dictionary
gives the following:
'NECESSARY. That is necessary which not only is true,
but would be true under all circumstances.
Something more than brute compulsion is, therefore, involved in the
conception; there is a general law under which the thing takes place.'
The notion
of cause is so intimately connected with that of necessity that it will be no
digression to linger over the above definition, with a view to discovering, if
possible, some meaning of which it is capable; for, as it stands, it is
very far from having any definite signification.
The first
point to notice is that, if any meaning is to be given to the phrase 'would be
true under all circumstances', the subject of it must be a propositional
function, not a proposition. [A propositional function is an expression
containing a variable, or undetermined constituent,
and becoming a proposition as soon as a definite value is assigned to the
variable. Examples are: 'A is A', 'x
is a number'. The variable is called the
argument of the function.] A proposition
is simply true or false, and that ends the matter: there can be no question of
'circumstances'. 'Charles I's head was cut off' is just as true in summer as in
winter, on Sundays as on Mondays. Thus
when it is worth saying that 'something would be true under all circumstances',
the something in question must be a propositional function, i.e. an expression
containing a variable, and becoming a proposition when a value is assigned to
the variable; the varying 'circumstances' alluded to are then the different
values of which the variable is capable.
Thus if 'necessary' means 'what is true under all circumstances', then
'if x is mortal' is necessary, because it is true for any possible value
of x. Thus we should be led to
the following definition:
'NECESSARY is a predicate of a propositional function,
meaning that it is true for all possible values of its argument or arguments.'
Unfortunately,
however, the definition in Baldwin's Dictionary says that what is
necessary is not only 'true under all circumstances' but is also 'true'. Now these two are incompatible. Only propositions can be 'true', and only
propositional functions can be 'true under all circumstances'. Hence the definition as it stands is
nonsense. What is meant seems to be
this: 'A proposition is necessary when it is a value of a propositional
function which is true under all circumstances, i.e. for all values of its argument
or arguments'. But if we adopt this
definition, the same proposition will be necessary or contingent according as
we choose one or other of its terms as the argument to our propositional
function. For example, 'if Socrates is a
man, Socrates is mortal', is necessary if Socrates is chosen as argument, but
not if man or mortal is chosen.
Again, 'if Socrates is a man, Plato is mortal' will be necessary if
either Socrates or man is chosen as argument, but not if Plato or mortal
is chosen. However, this difficulty can
be overcome by specifying the constituent which is to be regarded as argument,
and we thus arrive at the following definition:
'A
proposition is necessary with respect to a given constituent if it
remains true when that constituent is altered in any way compatible with the
proposition remaining significant.'
We may now
apply this definition to the definition of causality quoted above. It is obvious that the argument must be the
time at which the earlier event occurs.
Thus an instance of causality will be such as: 'If the event e1
occurs at the time t1, it will be followed by the event e2.' This proposition is intended to be necessary
with respect to t1, i.e. to remain true however t1
may be varied. Causality, as a universal
law, will then be the following: 'Given any event e1, there
is an event e2 such that, whenever e1
occurs, e2 occurs later.'
But before this can be considered precise, we must specify how much
later e2 is to occur.
Thus the principle becomes:
'Given any
event e1, there is an event e2 and a
time-interval t such
that, whenever e1 occurs, e2 follows after
an interval t.'
I am not
concerned as yet to consider whether this law is true or false. For the present I am merely concerned to
discover what the law of causality is supposed to be. I pass, therefore, to the other definitions
quoted above.
The second
definition need not detain us long, for two reasons. First, because it is psychological: not the
'thought or perception' of a process, but the process itself, must be what
concerns us in considering causality.
Secondly, because it is circular: in speaking of a process as 'taking
place in consequence of' another process, it introduces the very notion of
cause which was to be defined.
The third
definition is by far the most precise; indeed as regards clearness it leaves
nothing to be desired. But a great
difficulty is caused by the temporal contiguity of cause and effect which the
definition asserts. No two instants are
contiguous, since the time-series is compact; hence either the cause or the
effect or both must, if the definition is correct, endure for a finite time;
indeed, by the wording of the definition it is plain that both are assumed to
endure for a finite time. But then we
are faced with a dilemma: if the cause is a process involving change within
itself, we shall require (if causality is universal) causal relations between
its earlier and later parts; moreover, it would seem that only the later parts
can be relevant to the effect, since the earlier parts are not contiguous to
the effect, and therefore (by the definition) cannot influence the effect. Thus we shall be led to diminish the duration
of the cause without limit, and however much we may diminish it, there will
still remain an earlier part which might be altered without altering the
effect, so that the true cause, as defined, will not have been reached, for it
will be observed that the definition excludes plurality of causes. If, on the other hand, the cause is purely
static, involving no change within itself, then, in the first place, no such
cause is to be found in nature, and in the second place, it seems strange - too
strange to be accepted, in spite of bare logical possibility - that the cause,
after existing placidly for some time, should suddenly explode into the effect,
when it might just as well have done so at any earlier time, or have gone on
unchanged without producing its effect.
This dilemma, therefore, is fatal to the view that cause and effect can
be contiguous in time; if there are causes and effects, they must be separated
by a finite time-interval t ,
as was assumed in the above interpretation of the first definition.
What is
essentially the same statement of the law of causality as the one elicited
above from the first of
'The Law of Causation, the recognition of which is the main pillar of inductive science, is but the familiar truth, that invariability of succession is found by observation to obtain between every fact in nature and some other fact which has preceded it.' [Logic, Bk. III, Chap. V, §2.]
And Bergson, who has rightly perceived that the law as stated by
philosophers is worthless, nevertheless continues to suppose that it is used in
science. Thus he says:
'Now, it is argued, this law [the law of causality] means that every phenomenon is determined by its conditions, or, in other words, that the same causes produce the same effects. [Time and Free Will, p. 199.]
And again:
'We perceive physical phenomena, and these phenomena obey laws. This means: (1) That phenomena a, b, c, d, previously perceived, can occur again in the same shape; (2) that a certain phenomenon P, which appeared after the conditions a, b, c, d, and after these conditions only, will not fail to recur as soon as the same conditions are again present. [Time and Free Will, p. 202.]
A great
part of Bergson's attack on science rests on the
assumption that it employs this principle.
In fact, it employs no such principle, but philosophers - even Bergson - are too apt to take their views on science from
each other, not from science. As to what
the principle is, there is a fair consensus among philosophers of different
schools. There are, however, a number of
difficulties which at once arise. I omit
the question of plurality of causes for the present, since other graver
questions have to be considered. Two of
these, which are forced on our attention by the above statement of the law, are
the following:
(1) What is
meant by an 'event'?
(2) How
long may the time-interval be between cause and effect?
(1) An
'event', in the statement of the law, is obviously intended to be something that
is likely to recur, since otherwise the law becomes trivial. It follows that an 'event' is not a
particular, but some universal of which there may be many instances. It follows also that an 'event' must be
something short of the whole state of the universe, since it is highly
improbable that this will recur. What is
meant by an 'event' is something like striking a match, or dropping a penny
into the slot of an automatic machine.
If such an event is to recur, it must not be defined too narrowly: we must
not state with what degree of force the match is to be struck, nor what is to
be the temperature of the penny. For if
such considerations were relevant, our 'event' would occur at most once, and
the law would cease to give information.
An 'event', then, is a universal defined sufficiently widely to admit of
many particular occurrences in time being instances of it.
(2) The
next question concerns the time-interval.
Philosophers, no doubt, think of cause and effect as contiguous in time,
but this, for reasons already given, is impossible. Hence, since there are no infinitesimal
time-intervals, there must be some finite lapse of time t between cause
and effect. This, however, at once
raises insuperable difficulties. However
short we make the interval t ,
something may happen during the interval which prevents the expected
result. I put my penny in the slot, but
before I can draw out my ticket there is an earthquake which upsets the machine
and my calculations. In order to be sure
of the expected effect, we must know that there is nothing in the environment
to interfere with it. But this means
that the supposed cause is not, by itself, adequate to ensure the effect. And as soon as we include the environment,
the probability of repetition is diminished, until at last, when the whole
environment is included, the probability of repetition becomes almost nil.
In spite of
these difficulties, it must, of course, be admitted that many fairly dependable
regularities of sequence occur in daily life.
It is these regularities which have suggested the supposed law of
causality; where they are found to fail, it is thought that a better
formulation could have been found which would have never failed. I am far from denying that there may be such
sequences which in fact never do fail.
It may be that there will never be an exception to the rule that when a
stone of more than a certain mass, moving with more than a certain velocity,
comes into contact with a pane of glass of less than a certain thickness, the
glass breaks. I also do not deny that
the observation of such regularities, even when they are not without
exceptions, is useful in the infancy of a science: the observation that
unsupported bodies in air usually fall was a stage on the way to the law of
gravitation. What I deny is that science
assumes the existence of invariable uniformities of sequence of this kind, or
that it aims at discovering them. All
such uniformities, as we say, depend upon a certain
vagueness in the definition of the 'events'.
That bodies fall is a vague qualitative statement; since wishes to know
how fast they fall. This depends upon
the shape of the bodies and the density of the air. It is true that there is more nearly
uniformity when they fall in a vacuum; so far as Galileo could observe, the
uniformity is then complete. But later
it appeared that even there the latitude made a difference, and the
altitude. Theoretically, the position of
the sun and moon must make a difference.
In short, every advance in a science takes us farther away from the
crude uniformities which are first observed, into greater differentiation of
antecedent and consequent, and into a continually wider circle of antecedents
recognized as relevant.
The
principle, 'same cause, same effect', which philosophers imagine to be vital to
science, is therefore utterly otiose. As
soon as the antecedents have been given sufficiently fully to enable the
consequent to be calculated with some exactitude, the antecedents have become
so complicated that it is very unlikely they will ever recur. Hence, if this were the principle involved,
science would remain utterly sterile.
The
importance of these considerations lies partly in the fact that they lead to a
more correct account of scientific procedure, partly in the fact that they
remove the analogy with human volition which makes the conception of cause such
a fruitful source of fallacies. The
latter point will become clearer by the help of some illustrations. For this purpose I shall consider a few
maxims which have played a great part in the history of philosophy.
(1) 'Cause
and effect must more or less resemble each other.' This principle was prominent in the
philosophy of occasionalism, and is still by no means
extinct. It is still often thought, for
example, that mind could not have grown up in a universe which previously
contained nothing mental, and one ground for this belief is that matter is too
dissimilar from mind to have been able to cause it. Or, more particularly, what are termed the
nobler parts of our nature are supposed to be inexplicable, unless the universe
always contained something at least equally noble which could cause them. All such views seem to depend upon assuming
some unduly simplified law of causality; for, in any legitimate sense of
'cause' and 'effect', science seems to show that they are usually very widely
dissimilar, the 'cause' being, in fact, two states of the whole universe, and
the 'effect' some particular event.
(2) 'Cause
is analogous to volition, since there must be an intelligible nexus
between cause and effect.' This maxim
is, I think, often unconsciously in the imaginations of philosophers who would
reject it when explicitly stated. It is
probably operative in the view we have just been considering, that mind could
not have resulted from a purely material world.
I do not profess to know what is meant by 'intelligible'; it seems to
mean 'familiar to imagination'. Nothing
is less 'intelligible', in any other sense, than the connection between an act
of will and its fulfilment. But
obviously the sort of nexus desired between cause and effect is such as could
only hold between the 'events' which the supposed law of causality
contemplates; the laws which replace causality in such a science as physics
leave no room for any two events between which a nexus could be sought.
(3) 'The
cause compels the effect in some sense in which the effect does not
compel the cause.' This belief seems
largely operative in the dislike of determinism; but, as a matter of fact, it
is connected with our second maxim, and falls as soon as that is
abandoned. We may define 'compulsion' as
follows: 'Any set of circumstances is said to compel A when A desires to do
something which the circumstances prevent, or to abstain from something which
the circumstances cause.' This
presupposes that some meaning has been found for the word 'cause' - a point to
which I shall return later. What I want
to make clear at present is that compulsion is a very complex notion, involving
thwarted desire. So long as a person
does what he wishes to do, there is no compulsion, however much his wishes may
be calculable by the help of earlier events.
And where desire does not come in, there can be no question of
compulsion. Hence it is, in general,
misleading to regard the cause as compelling the effect.
A vaguer
form of the same maxim substitutes the word 'determine' for the word 'compel';
we are told that the cause determines the effect in a sense in which the
effect does not determine the cause.
It is not quite clear what is meant by 'determining'; the only precise
sense, so far as I know, is that of a function or one-many
relation. If we admit plurality of
causes, but not of effects, that is, if we suppose that, given the cause, the
effect must be such and such, but, given the effect, the cause may have been
one of many alternatives, then we may say that the cause determines the effect,
but not the effect the cause. Plurality
of causes, however, results only from conceiving the effect vaguely and
narrowly and the cause precisely and widely.
Many antecedents may 'cause' a man's death, because his death is vague
and narrow. But if we adopt the opposite
course, taking as the 'cause' the drinking of a dose of arsenic, and as the
'effect' the whole state of the world five minutes later, we shall have
plurality of effects instead of plurality of causes. Thus the supposed lack of symmetry between
'cause' and 'effect' is illusory.
(4) 'A
cause cannot operate when it has ceased to exist, because what has ceased to
exist is nothing.' This is a common
maxim, and a still more common unexpressed prejudice. It has, I fancy, a good deal to do with the
attractiveness of Bergson's 'durée':
since the past has effects now, it must still exist in some sense. The mistake in this maxim consists in the
supposition that causes 'operate' at all.
A volition 'operates' when what it wills takes
place; but nothing can operate except a volition. The belief that causes 'operate' results from
assimilating them, consciously or unconsciously, to volitions. We have already seen that, if there are
causes at all, they must be separated by a finite interval of time from the
effects, and thus cause their effects after they have ceased to exist.
It may be
objected to the above definition of a volition 'operating' that it only
operates when it 'causes' what it wills, not when it merely happens to be
followed by what it wills. This
certainly represents the usual view of what is meant by a volition 'operating',
but as it involves the very view of causation which we are engaged in
combating, it is not open to us as a definition. We may say that a volition
'operates' when there is some law in virtue of which a similar volition in
rather similar circumstances will usually be followed by what it wills. But this is a vague conception, and
introduces ideas which we have not yet considered. What is chiefly important to notice is that
the usual notion of 'operating' is not open to us if we reject, as I contend
that we should, the usual notion of causation.
(5) 'A
cause cannot operate except where it is.'
This maxim is very widespread; it was urged against Newton, and has
remained a source of prejudice against 'action at a distance'. In philosophy it has led to a denial of transient
action, and thence to monism or Leibnizian monadism. Like the
analogous maxim concerning temporal contiguity, it rests upon the assumption
that causes 'operate', i.e. that they are in some obscure way analogous to
volitions. And, as in the case of
temporal contiguity, the inferences drawn from this maxim are wholly
groundless.
I return
now to the question, What law or laws can be found to
take the place of the supposed law of causality?
First,
without passing beyond such uniformities of sequence as are contemplated by the
traditional law, we may admit that, if any such sequence has been observed in a
great many cases, and has never been found to fail, there is an inductive
probability that it will be found to hold in future cases. If stones have hitherto been found to break
windows, it is probable that they will continue to do so. This, of course, assumes the inductive
principle, of which the truth may reasonably be questioned; but as this
principle is not our present concern, I shall in this discussion treat it as
indubitable. We may then say, in the
case of any such frequently observed sequence, that the earlier event is the cause
and the later event the effect.
Several
considerations, however, make such special sequences very different from the
traditional relation of cause and effect.
In the first place, the sequence, in any hitherto unobserved instance,
is no more than probable, whereas the relation of cause and effect was supposed
to be necessary. I do not mean by this
merely that we are not sure of having discovered a true case of cause and
effect; I mean that, even when we have a case of cause and effect in our
present sense, all that is meant is that on grounds of observation, it is
probable that when one occurs the other will also occur. Thus in our present sense, A may be the cause
of B even if there actually are cases where B does not follow A. Striking a match will be the cause of its
igniting, in spite of the fact that some matches are damp and fail to ignite.
In the
second place, it will not be assumed that every event has some
antecedent which is its cause in this sense; we shall only believe in causal
sequences where we find them, without any presumption that they always are to
be found.
In the
third place, any cause of sufficiently frequent sequence will be causal
in our present sense; for example, we shall not refuse to say that night is the
cause of day. Our repugnance to saying
this arises from the ease with which we can imagine the sequence to fail, but
owing to the fact that cause and effect must be separated by a finite interval
of time, any such sequence might fail through the interposition
of other circumstances in the interval.
Mill, discussing this instance of night and day, says:
'It is necessary to our using the word cause, that we should believe not only that the antecedent always has been followed by the consequent, but that as long as the present constitution of things endures, it always will be so.' [Loc. cit., § 6.]
In this
sense, we shall have to give up the hope of finding causal laws such as Mill
contemplated; any causal sequence which we have observed may at any moment be
falsified without a falsification of any laws of the kind that the more
advanced sciences aim at establishing.
In the
fourth place, such laws of probable sequence, though useful in daily life and
in the infancy of a science, tend to be displaced by quite different laws as
soon as a science is successful. The law
of gravitation will illustrate what occurs in any advanced science. In the motions of mutually gravitating
bodies, there is nothing that can be called a cause, and nothing that can be
called an effect; there is merely a formula.
Certain differential equations can be found, which hold at every instant
for every particle of the system, and which, given the configuration and
velocities at one instant, or the configurations at two instants, render the
configuration at any other earlier or later instant theoretically
calculable. That is to say, the
configuration at any instant is a function of that instant and the
configurations at two given instants.
This statement holds throughout physics, and not only in the special
case of gravitation. But there is
nothing that could be properly called 'cause' and nothing that could be properly
called 'effect' in such a system.
No doubt
the reason why the old 'law of causality' has so long continued to pervade the
books of philosophers is simply that the idea of a function is unfamiliar to
most of them, and therefore they seek an unduly simplified statement. There is no question of repetitions of the
'same' cause producing the 'same' effect; it is not in any sameness of causes
and effects that the constancy of scientific law consists, but in sameness of
relations. And even 'sameness of relations'
is too simple a phrase; 'sameness of different equations' is the only correct
phrase. It is impossible to state this
accurately in non-mathematical language; the nearest approach would be as
follows: 'There is a constant relation between the state of the universe at any
instant and the rate of change in the rate at which any part of the universe is
changing at that instant, and this relation is many-one, i.e. such that the
rate of change in the rate of change is determined when the state of the universe
is given.' If the 'law of causality' is
to be something actually discoverable in the practice of science, the above
proposition has a better right to the name than any 'law of causality' to be
found in the books of philosophers.
In regard
to the above principle, several observations must be made:
(1) No-one
can pretend that the above principle is a priori or self-evident or a
'necessity of thought'. Nor is it, in
any sense, a premise of science: it is an empirical generalization from a
number of laws which are themselves empirical generalizations.
(2) The law
makes no difference between past and future: the future 'determines' the past
in exactly the same sense in which the past 'determines' the future. The word 'determine', here, has a purely
logical significance: a certain number of variables 'determine' another
variable if that other variable is a function of them.
(3) The law
will not be empirically verifiable unless the course of events within some
sufficiently small volume will be approximately the same in any two states of
the universe which only differ in regard to what is at a considerable distance
from the small volume in question. For
example, motions of the planets in the solar system must be approximately the
same however the fixed stars may be distributed, provided that all the fixed
stars are very much farther from the sun than the planets are. If gravitation varied directly as the
distance, so that the most remote stars made the most difference to the motions
of the planets, the world might be just as regular and just as much subject to
mathematical laws as it is at present, but we could never discover the fact.
(4)
Although the old 'law of causality' is not assumed by science, something which
we may call the 'uniformity of nature' is assumed, or rather is accepted on
inductive grounds. The uniformity of
nature does not assert the trivial principle 'same cause, same effect', but the
principle of the permanence of laws.
That is to say, when a law exhibition, e.g. an acceleration as a
function of the configuration has been found to hold throughout the observable
past, it is expected that it will continue to hold in the future, or that, if
it does not itself hold, there is some other law, agreeing with the supposed
law as regards the past, which will hold for the future. The ground of this principle is simply the
inductive ground that it has been found to be true in very many instances;
hence the principle cannot be considered certain, but only probable to a degree
which cannot be accurately estimated.
The
uniformity of nature, in the above sense, although it is assumed in the
practice of science, must not, in its generality, be regarded as a kind of
major premise, without which all scientific reasoning would be in error. The assumption that all laws of nature
are permanent has, of course, less probability than the assumption that this or
that particular law is permanent; and the assumption that a particular law is
permanent for all time has less probability than the assumption that it will be
valid up to such and such a date.
Science, in any given case, will assume what the case requires, but no
more. In constructing the Nautical
Almanac for 1915 it will assume that the law of gravitation will remain
true up to the end of that year; but it will make no assumption as to 1916
until it comes to the next volume of the almanac. This procedure is, of course, dictated by the
fact that the uniformity of nature is not known a priori, but is an
empirical generalization, like 'all men are mortal'. In all such cases, it is better to argue
immediately from the given particular instances to the new instance, than to
argue by way of a major premise; the conclusion is only probable in either
case, but acquires a higher probability by the former method than by the
latter.
In all
science we have to distinguish two sorts of laws: first, those that are
empirically verifiable but probably only approximate; secondly, those that are
not verifiable, but may be exact. The
law of gravitation, for example, in its applications to the solar system, is
only empirically verifiable when it is assumed that matter outside the solar
system may be ignored for such purposes; we believe this to be only
approximately true, but we cannot empirically verify the law of universal
gravitation which we believe to be exact.
This point is very important in connection with what we may call
'relatively isolated systems'. These may
be defined as follows:
A system
relatively isolated during a given period is one which, within some assignable
margin of error, will behave in the same way throughout that period,
however the rest of the universe may be constituted.
A system
may be called 'practically isolated' during a given period if, although there might
be states of the rest of the universe which would produce more than the
assigned margin of error, there is reason to believe that such states do not in
fact occur.
Strictly
speaking, we ought to specify the respect in which the system is relatively
isolated. For example, the earth is
relatively isolated as regards falling bodies, but not as regards tides; it is practically
isolated as regards economic phenomena, although, if Jervon's
sun-spot theory of commercial crises had been true, it would not have been even
practically isolated in this respect.
It will be
observed that we cannot prove in advance that a system is isolated. This will be inferred from the observed fact
that approximate uniformities can be stated for this system alone. If the complete laws for the whole universe
were known, the isolation of a system could be deduced from them; assuming, for
example, the law of universal gravitation, the practical isolation of the solar
system in this respect can be deduced by the help of the fact that there is
very little matter in its neighbourhood.
But it should be observed that isolated systems are only important as
providing a possibility of discovering scientific laws; they have no
theoretical importance in the finished structure of a science.
The case
where one event A is said to 'cause' another event B, which philosophers take
as fundamental, is really only the most simplified instance of a practically
isolated system. It may happen that, as
a result of general scientific laws, whenever A occurs throughout a certain
period, it is followed by B; in that case, A and B form a system which is
practically isolated throughout that period.
It is, however, to be regarded as a piece of good fortune if this
occurs; it will always be due to special circumstances, and would not have been
true if the rest of the universe had been different though subject to the same
laws.
The
essential function which causality has been supposed to perform is the
possibility of inferring the future from the past, or, more generally, events
at any time from events at certain assigned times. Any system in which such inference is
possible may be called a 'deterministic' system. We may define a deterministic system as
follows:
A system is
said to be 'deterministic' when, given certain data, e1, e2, ..., en, at times t1, t2,
..., tn respectively, concerning
this system, if Et is the state of the system at any time t,
there is a functional relation of the form
Et = f (e1, t1, e2, t2,
... , en, tn,
t). (A)
The system will be 'deterministic throughout a given
period' if t, in the above formula, may be at any time within that
period, though outside that period the formula may be no longer true. If the universe, as a whole, is such a
system, determinism is true of the universe; if not, not. A system which is part of a deterministic
system I shall call 'determined'; one which is not part of any such system I
shall call 'capricious'.
The events e1, e2, ..., en
I shall call 'determinants' of the system. It is to be observed that a system which has
one set of determinants will in general have many. In the case of the motions of the planets,
for example, the configurations of the solar system at any two given times will
be determinants.
We may take
another illustration from the hypothesis of psycho-physical parallelism. Let us assume, for the purposes of this
illustration, that to a given state of brain a given state of mind always
corresponds, and vice versa, i.e. that there is a one-one relation between
them, so that each is a function of the other.
We may also assume, what is practically certain, that to a given state
of a certain brain a given state of the whole material universe corresponds,
since it is highly improbable that a given brain is ever twice in exactly the
same state. Hence there will be a
one-one relation between the state of a given person's mind and the state of
the whole material universe. It follows
that, if n states of the material universe are determinants of the
material universe, then n states of a given man's mind are determinants
of the whole material and mental universe - assuming, that is to say, that
psycho-physical parallelism is true.
The above
illustration is important in connection with a certain confusion which seems to
have beset those who have philosophized on the relation of mind to matter. It is often thought that, if the state of the
mind is determinant when the state of the brain is given, and if the material
world forms a deterministic system, then mind is 'subject' to matter in some
sense in which matter is not 'subject' to mind.
But if the state of the brain is also determinate when the state of the
mind is given, it must be exactly as true to regard matter as subject to mind
as it would be to regard mind as subject to matter. We could, theoretically, work out the history
of mind without ever mentioning matter, and then, at the end, deduce that
matter must meanwhile have gone through the corresponding history. It is true that if the relation of brain to
mind were many-one, not one-one, there would be a one-sided dependence of mind
on brain, while, conversely, if the relation were one-many, as Bergson supposes, there would be a one-sided dependence of
brain on mind. But the dependence
involved is, in any case, only logical; it does not
mean that we shall be compelled to do things we desire not to do, which is what
people instinctively imagine it to mean.
As another
illustration we may take the case of mechanism and teleology. A system may be defined as 'mechanical' when
it has a set of determinants that are purely material, such as the positions of
certain pieces of matter at certain times.
It is an open question whether the world of mind and matter, as we know
it, is a mechanical system or not; let us suppose, for the sake of argument,
that it is a mechanical system. This
supposition - so I contend - throws no light whatever on the question whether
the universe is or is not a 'teleological' system, but the argument is not much
affected by the particular definition we adopt.
Broadly, a teleological system is one in which purposes are realized,
i.e. in which certain desires - those that are deeper or nobler or more
fundamental or more universal or what not - are followed by their
realization. Now the fact - if it be a
fact - that the universe is mechanical has no bearing whatever on the question
whether it is teleological in the above sense.
There might be a mechanical system in which all wishes were realized,
and there might be one in which all wishes were thwarted. The question whether, or how far, our actual
world is teleological, cannot, therefore, be settled by proving that it is
mechanical, and the desire that it should be teleological is no ground for
wishing it to be not mechanical.
There is,
in all these questions, a very great difficulty in avoiding confusion between
what we can infer and what is in fact determined. Let us consider, for a moment, the various
senses in which the future may be 'determined'.
There is one sense - and a very important one - in which it is
determined quite independently of scientific laws, namely, the sense that it
will be what it will be. We all regard
the past as determined simply by the fact that it has happened; but for the accident
that memory works backward and not forward, we should regard the future as
equally determined by the fact that it will happen. 'But,' we are told, 'you cannot alter the
past, while you can to some extent alter the future.' This view seems to me to rest upon just those
errors in regard to causation which it has been my object to remove. You cannot make the past other than it was -
true, but this is a mere application of the law of contradiction. If you already know what the past was,
obviously it is useless to wish it different.
But also you cannot make the future other than it will be; this again is
an application of the law of contradiction.
And if you happen to know the future - e.g. in the case of a forthcoming
eclipse - it is just as useless to wish it different as to wish the past
different. 'But,' it will be rejoined,
'our wishes can cause the future, sometimes, to be different from what
it would be if they did not exist, and they can have no such effect upon the
past.' This, again, is a mere
tautology. An effect being defined
as something subsequent to its cause, obviously we can have no effect
upon the past. But that does not mean
that the past would not have been different if our present wishes had been
different. Obviously, our present wishes
are conditioned by the past, and therefore could not have been different unless
the past had been different; therefore, if our present wishes were different,
the past would be different. Of course,
the past cannot be different from what it was, but no more can our present
wishes be different from what they are; this again is merely the law of
contradiction. The facts seems to be
merely (1) that wishing generally depends upon ignorance, and is therefore
commoner in regard to the future than in regard to the past; (2) that where a
wish concerns the future, it and its realization very often form a 'practically
independent system’, i.e. many wishes regarding the future are realized. But there seems no doubt that the main
difference in our feelings arises from the accidental fact that the past but
not the future can be known by memory.
Although
the sense of 'determined' in which the future is determined by the mere fact
that it will be what it will be is sufficient (at least so it seems to me) to
refute some opponents of determinism, notably M. Bergson
and the pragmatists, yet it is not what most people have in mind when they
speak of the future as determined. What
they have in mind is a formula by means of which the future can be exhibited,
and at least theoretically calculated, as a function of the past. But at this point we meet with a great
difficulty, which besets what has been said above about deterministic systems,
as well as what is said by others.
If formulae of any degree of complexity, however great, are
admitted, it would seem that any system, whose state at a given moment is a
function of certain measurable quantities, must be a deterministic
system. Let us consider, in
illustration, a single material particle, whose co-ordinates at time t
are xt, yt, zt. Then, however the particle moves, there must
be, theoretically, functions f1, f2, f3,
such that
xt = f1
(t), yt
= f2 (t), zt = f3 (t).
It follows
that, theoretically, the whole state of the material universe at time t must
be capable of being exhibited as a function of t. Hence our universe will be deterministic in
the sense defined above. But if this be
true, no information is conveyed about the universe in stating that it is
deterministic. It is true that the formulae
involved may be of strictly infinite complexity, and therefore not practically
capable of being written down or apprehended.
But except from the point of view of our knowledge, this might seem to
be a detail: in itself, if the above considerations are sound, the material
universe must be deterministic, must be subject to laws.
This,
however, is plainly not what was intended.
The difference between this view and the view intended may be seen as
follows. Given some formulae which fits the facts hitherto - say the law of gravitation - there
will be an infinite number of other formulae, not empirically distinguishable
from it in the past, but diverging from it more and more in the future. Hence, even assuming that there are
persistent laws, we shall have no reason for assuming that the law of the
inverse square will hold in future; it may be some other hitherto
indistinguishable law that will hold. We
cannot say that every law which has held hitherto must hold in the
future, because past facts which obey one law will also obey others, hitherto
indistinguishable but diverging in future.
Hence there must, at every moment, be laws hitherto unbroken which are
now broken for the first time. What
science does, in fact, is to select the simplest formula that will fit
the facts. But this, quite obviously, is
merely a methodological precept, not a law of Nature. If the simplest formula ceases, after a time,
to be applicable, the simplest formula that remains applicable is selected, and
science has no sense that an axiom has been falsified. We are thus left with the brute fact that, in
many departments of science, quite simple laws have hitherto been found to
hold. This fact cannot be regarded as
having any a priori ground, nor can it be used to support inductively
the opinion that the same laws will continue; for at every moment laws hitherto
true are being falsified, though in the advanced sciences these laws are less
simple than those that have remained true.
Moreover, it would be fallacious to argue inductively from the state of
the advanced sciences to the future state of the others,
for it may well be that the advanced sciences are advanced simply because,
hitherto, their subject-matter has obeyed simple and easily ascertainable laws,
while the subject-matter of other sciences has not done so.
The
difficulty we have been considering seems to be met partly, if not wholly, by
the principle that the time must not enter explicitly into our
formulae. All mechanical laws exhibit
acceleration as a function of configuration, not of configuration and time
jointly; and this principle of the irrelevance of the time may be extended to
all scientific laws. In fact we might
interpret the 'uniformity of nature' as meaning just this, that no scientific law
involves the time as an argument, unless, or course, it is given in an
integrated form, in which case lapse of time, though not absolute time,
may appear in our formulae. Whether this
consideration suffices to overcome our difficulty completely, I do not know;
but in any case it does much to diminish it.
It will
serve to illustrate what has been said if we apply it to the question of free
will.
(1)
Determinism in regard to the will is the doctrine that our volitions belong to
some deterministic system, i.e. are 'determined' in the sense defined
above. Whether this doctrine is true or false, is a mere question of fact; no a priori
considerations (if our previous discussions have been correct) can exist on
either side. On the one hand, there is
no a priori category of causality, but merely certain observed
uniformities. As a matter of fact, there
are observed uniformities in regard to volitions; thus there is some empirical
evidence that volitions are determined.
But it would be very rash to maintain that the evidence if overwhelming,
and it is quite possible that some volitions, as well as some other things, are
not determined, except in the sense in which we found that everything must be
determined.
(2) But, on
the other hand, the subjective sense of freedom, sometimes alleged against
determinism, has no bearing on the question whatever. The view that it has a bearing rests upon the
belief that causes compel their effects, or that nature enforces obedience to
its laws as governments did. These are
mere anthropomorphic superstitions, due to assimilation of causes with
volitions and of natural laws with human edicts. We feel that our will is not compelled, but
that only means that it is not other than we choose it to be. It is one of the demerits of the traditional
theory of causality that it has created an artificial opposition between
determinism and the freedom of which we are introspectively conscious.
(3) Besides
the general question whether volitions are determined, there is the further question
whether they are mechanically determined, i.e. whether they are part of
what was above defined as a mechanical system.
This is the question whether they form part of a system with purely
material determinants, i.e. whether there are laws which, given certain
material data, make all volitions functions of those data. Here again, there is empirical evidence up to
a point, but it is not conclusive in regard to all volitions. It is important to observe, however, that
even if volitions are part of a mechanical system,
this by no means implies any supremacy of matter over mind. It may well be that the same system which is
susceptible of material determinants is also susceptible of mental
determinants; thus a mechanical system may be determined by sets of volitions,
as well as by sets of material facts. It
would seem, therefore, that the reasons which make people dislike the view that
volitions are mechanically determined are fallacious.
(4) The notion of necessity, which is
often associated with determinism, is a confused notion not legitimately
deducible from determinism. Three
meanings are commonly confounded when necessity is spoken of:
(a) An action is necessary when it will be
performed however much the agent may wish to do otherwise. Determinism does not imply that actions are
necessary in this sense.
(b) A propositional
function is necessary when all its values are true. This sense is not relevant to our present
discussion.
(g) A proposition
is necessary with respect to a given constituent when it is the value, with
that constituent as argument, of a necessary propositional function, in other
words, when it remains true however that constituent may be varied. In this sense, in a deterministic system, the
connection of a volition with its determinants is
necessary, if the time at which the determinants occur be taken as the
constituent to be varied, the time-interval between the determinants and the
volition being kept constant. But this
sense of necessity is purely logical, and has no emotional importance.
We may now
sum up our discussion of causality. We
found first that the law of causality, as usually stated by philosophers, is
false, and is not employed in science.
We then considered the nature of scientific laws, and found that, instead
of stating that one event A is always followed by another event B, they stated
functional relations between certain events at certain times, which we called
determinants, and other events at earlier or later times or at the same time. We were unable to find any a priori
category involved: the existence of scientific laws appeared as a purely
empirical fact, not necessarily universal, except in a trivial and
scientifically useless form. We found
that a system with one set of determinants may very likely have other sets of a
quite different kind, that, for example, a mechanically determined system may
also be teleologically or volitionally
determined. Finally we considered the
problem of free will: here we found that the reasons for supposing volitions to
be determined are strong but not conclusive, and we decided that even if
volitions are mechanically determined, that is no reason for denying freedom in
the sense revealed by introspection, or for supposing that mechanical events
are not determined by volitions. The
problem of free will verses determinism is therefore, if we were right,
mainly illusory, but in part not yet capable of being decisively solved.
CHAPTER X
Knowledge by
Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description
THE object of the following paper is to consider what
it is that we know in cases where we know propositions about 'the-so-and-so'
without knowing who or what the so-and-so is.
For example, I know that the candidate who gets most votes will be
elected, though I do not know who is the candidate who will
get most votes. The problem I
wish to consider is: What do we know in these cases, where the subject is
merely described? I have considered this
problem elsewhere [See references later.]
from a purely logical point of view;
but in what follows I wish to consider the problem in relation to theory of
knowledge as well as in relation to logic, and in view of the above-mentioned
logical discussions, I shall in this paper make the logical portion as brief as
possible.
In order to
make clear the antithesis between 'acquaintance' and 'description', I shall
first of all try to explain what I mean by 'acquaintance'. I say that I am acquainted with an
object when I have a direct cognitive relation to that object, i.e. when I am
directly aware of the object itself.
When I speak of a cognitive relation here, I do not mean the sort of
relation which constitutes judgement, but the sort
which constitutes presentation. I fact,
I think the relation of subject and object which I call acquaintance is simply
the converse of the relation of object and subject which constitutes
presentation. That is, to say that S has
acquaintance with O is essentially the same thing as to say that O is presented
to S. But the associations and natural
extensions of the word acquaintance are different from those of the word
presentation. To begin with, as
in most cognitive words, it is natural to say that I am acquainted with an
object even at moments when it is not actually before my mind, provided it has
been before my mind, and will be again whenever occasion arises. This is the same sense in which I am said to
know that 2 + 2 = 4 even when I am thinking of something else. In the second place, the word acquaintance
is designed to emphasize, more than the word presentation, the
relational character of the fact with which we are concerned. There is, to my mind, a danger that, in
speaking of presentation, we may so emphasize the object as to lose sight of
the subject. The result of this is either
to lead to the view that there is no subject, whence we arrive at materialism;
or to lead to the view that what is presented is part of the subject, whence we
arrive at idealism, and should arrive at solipsism but for the most desperate
contortions. Now I wish to preserve the
dualism of subject and object in my terminology, because this dualism seems to
me a fundamental fact concerning cognition.
Hence I prefer the word acquaintance, because it emphasizes the
need of a subject which is acquainted.
When we ask
what are the kinds of objects with which we are acquainted,
the first and most obvious example is sense-data. When I see a colour or hear a noise, I have
direct acquaintance with the colour or the noise. The sense-datum with which I am acquainted in
these cases is generally, if not always, complex. This is particularly obvious in the case of
sight. I do not mean, of course, merely
that the supposed physical object is complex, but that the direct sensible
object is complex and contains parts with spatial relations. Whether it is possible to be aware of a
complex without being aware of its constituents is not an easy question, but on
the whole it would seem that there is no reason why it should not be possible. This question arises in an acute form in
connection with self-consciousness, which we must now briefly consider.
In
introspection, we seem to be immediately aware of varying complexes, consisting
of objects in various cognitive and conative
relations to ourselves. When I see the
sun, it often happens that I am aware of my seeing the sun, in addition to
being aware of the sun; and when I desire food, it often happens that I am
aware of my desire for food. But it is
hard to discover any state of mind in which I am aware of myself alone, as
opposed to a complex of which I am a constituent. The question of the nature of
self-consciousness is too large, and too slightly connected with our subject,
to be argued at length here. It is
difficult, but probably not impossible, to account for plain facts if we assume
that we do not have acquaintance with ourselves. It is plain that we are not only acquainted
with the complex 'Self-acquainted-with-A', but we also know the
proposition 'I am acquainted with A'.
Now here the complex has been analysed, and if 'I' does not stand for
something which is a direct object of acquaintance, we shall have to suppose
that 'I' is something known by description.
If we wished to maintain the view that there is no acquaintance with Self, we might argue as follows: We are acquainted with acquaintance,
and we know that it is a relation. Also
we are acquainted with a complex in which we perceive that acquaintance is the
relating relation. Hence we know that
this complex must have a constituent which is that which is acquainted, i.e.
must have a subject-term as well as an object-term. This subject-term we define as 'I'. Thus 'I' means 'the
subject-term in awarenesses of which I am
aware'. But as a definition this cannot
be regarded as a happy effort. It would
seem necessary, therefore, either to suppose that I am
acquainted with myself, and that 'I', therefore, requires no definition, being
merely the proper name of a certain object, or to find some other analysis of
self-consciousness. Thus
self-consciousness cannot be regarded as throwing light on the question whether
we can know a complex without knowing its constituents. This question, however, is not important for
our present purposes, and I shall therefore not discuss it further.
The awarenesses we have considered so far have all been awarenesses of particular existents, and might all in a
large sense be called sense-data. For, from the point of view of theory of knowledge, introspective
knowledge is exactly on a level with knowledge derived from sight or hearing. But, in addition to awareness of the above
kind of objects, which may be called awareness of particulars, we have
also (though not quite in the same sense) what may be called awareness of universals. Awareness of universals is called conceiving,
and a universal of which we are aware is called a concept. Not only are we aware of particular yellows,
but if we have seen a sufficient number of yellows and have sufficient
intelligence, we are aware of the universal yellow; this universal is
the subject in such judgements as 'yellow differs from blue' or 'yellow
resembles blue less than green does'.
And the universal yellow is the predicate in such judgements as 'this is
yellow', where 'this' is a particular sense-datum. And universal relations, too, are objects of
awareness; up and down, before and after, resemblance, desire, awareness
itself, and so on, would seem to be all of them objects of which we can be
aware.
In regard
to relations, it might be urged that we are never aware of the universal relation
itself, but only of complexes in which it is a constituent. For example, it may be said that we do not
know directly such a relation as before, though we understand such a
proposition as 'this is before that', and may be directly aware of such a complex
as 'this being before that'. This view,
however, is difficult to reconcile with the fact that we often know
propositions in which the relation is the subject, or in which the relata are not definite given objects, but 'anything'. For example, we know that if one thing is
before another, and the other before a third, then the first is before the
third; and here the things concerned are not definite things, but
'anything'. It is hard to see how we
could know such a fact about 'before' unless we were acquainted with 'before',
and not merely with actual particular cases of one given object being before
another given object. And more directly:
A judgement such as 'this is before that', where this judgement is derived from
awareness of a complex, constitutes an analysis, and we should not understand
the analysis if we were not acquainted with the meaning of the terms
employed. Thus we must suppose that we
are acquainted with the meaning of 'before', and not merely with instances of
it.
There are
thus at least two sorts of objects of which we are aware, namely, particulars
and universals. Among particulars I
include all existents, and all complexes of which one or more constituents are
existents, such as this-before-that, this-above-that, the-yellowness-of-this. Among universals I include all objects of
which no particular is a constituent.
Thus the disjunction 'universal-particular' includes all objects. We might also call it the disjunction
'abstract-concrete'. It is not quite
parallel with the opposition 'concept-percept', because things remembered or
imagined belong with particulars, but can hardly be called percepts. (On the other hand, universals with which we
are acquainted may be identified with concepts.)
It will be
seen that among the objects with which we are acquainted are not included
physical objects (as opposed to sense-data), nor other people's minds. These things are known to us by what I call
'knowledge of description', which we must now consider.
By a
'description' I mean any phrase of the form 'a so-and-so' or 'the
so-and-so'. A phrase of the form 'a
so-and-so' I shall call an 'ambiguous' description; a phrase of the form 'the
so-and-so' (in the singular) I shall call a 'definite' description. Thus 'a man' is an ambiguous description, and
'the man with the iron mask' is a definite description. There are various problems connected with
ambiguous descriptions, but I pass them by, since they do not directly concern
the matter I wish to discuss. What I
wish to discuss is the nature of our knowledge concerning objects in cases
where we know that there is an object answering to a definite description,
though we are not acquainted with any such object. This is a matter which is concerned
exclusively with definite descriptions.
I shall, therefore, in the sequel, speak simply of 'descriptions' when I
mean 'definite descriptions'. Thus a
description will mean any phrase of the form 'the so-and-so' in the singular.
I shall say
that an object is 'known by description' when we known that it is 'the
so-and-so', i.e. when we know that there is one object, and no more, having a
certain property; and it will generally be implied that we do not have
knowledge of the same object by acquaintance.
We know that the man with the iron mask existed, and many propositions
are known about him; but we do not know who he was. We know that the candidate who gets most
votes will be elected, and in this case we are very likely also acquainted (in
the only sense in which one can be acquainted with someone else) with the man
who is, in fact, the candidate who will get most votes, but we do not know
which of the candidates he is, i.e. we do not know any proposition of the form
'A is the candidate who will get most votes' where A is one of the candidates
by name. We shall say that we have 'merely
descriptive knowledge; of the so-and-so when, although we know that the
so-and-so exists, and although we may possibly be acquainted with the object
which is, in fact, the so-and-son, yet we do not know any proposition 'a
is the so-and-so', where a is something with which we are acquainted.
When we say
'the so-and-so exists', we mean that there is just one object which is the
so-and-so. The proposition 'a is the so-and-so' means that a has the
property so-and-so, and nothing else has.
'Sir Joseph Larmor is the Unionist candidate'
means 'Sir Joseph Larmor is a Unionist candidate, and
no-one else is.' 'The Unionist candidate
exists' means 'someone is a Unionist candidate, and no-one else is.' Thus, when we are acquainted with an object
which we know to be so-and-so, we know that the so-and-so exists, but we may
know that the so-and-so exists when we are not acquainted with any object which
we know to be the so-and-so, and even when we are not acquainted with any object
which, in fact, is the so-and-so.
Common
words, even proper names, are usually really descriptions. That is to say, the thought in the mind of a
person using a proper name correctly can generally only be expressed explicitly
if we replace the proper name by a description.
Moreover, the description required to express the thought will vary from
different people, or for the same person at different
times. The only thing constant (so long
as the name is rightly used) is the object to which the name applies. But so long as this remains constant, the
particular description involved usually makes no difference to the truth or
falsehood of the proposition in which the name appears.
Let us take
some illustrations. Suppose some
statement made about Bismarck. Assuming
that there is such a thing as direct acquaintance with oneself, Bismarck
himself might have used his name directly to designate the particular person
with whom he was acquainted. In this
case, if he made a judgement about himself, he himself might be a constituent
of the judgement. Here the proper name
has the direct use which it always wishes to have, as simply standing for a
certain object, and not for a description of the object. But if a person who knew Bismarck made a
judgement about him, the case is different.
What this person was acquainted with were certain sense-data which he
connected (rightly, we will suppose) with Bismarck's body. His body as a physical object, and still more
his mind, were only known as the body and the mind connected with these
sense-data. That is, they were known by
description. It is, of course, very much
a matter of chance which characteristics of a man's appearance will come into a
friend's mind when he thinks of him; thus the description actually in the friend's
mind is accidental. The essential point
is that he knows that the various descriptions all apply to the same entity, in
spite of not being acquainted with the entity in question.
When we,
who did not know Bismarck, make a judgement about him, the description in our
minds will probably be some more or less vague mass of historical knowledge -
far more, in most cases, than is required to identify him. But, for the sake of illustration, let us
assume that we think of him as 'the first Chancellor of the German
Empire'. Here all the words are abstract
except 'German'. The word 'German' will
again have different meanings for different people. To some it will recall travels in Germany, to
some the look of Germany on the map, and so on.
But if we are to obtain a description which we know to be applicable, we
shall be compelled, at some point, to bring in a reference to a particular with
which we are acquainted. Such reference
is involved in any mention of past, present, and future (as opposed to definite
dates), or of here and there, or of what others have told us. Thus it would seem that, in some way or
other, a description known to be applicable to a particular must involve some
reference to a particular with which we are acquainted, if our knowledge about
the thing described is not to be merely what follows logically from the
description. For example, 'the most
long-lived of men' is a description which must apply to some man, but we can
make no judgements concerning this man which involve knowledge about him beyond
what the description gives. If, however,
we say, 'the first Chancellor of the German Empire was an astute diplomatist',
we can only be assured of the truth of our judgement in virtue of something with
which we are acquainted - usually a testimony heard or read. Considered psychologically, apart from the
information we convey to others, apart from the fact about the actual Bismarck,
which gives importance to our judgement, the thought we really have contains
the one or more particulars involved, and otherwise consists wholly of
concepts. All names of places - London,
England, Europe, the earth, the Solar System - similarly involve, when used,
descriptions which start from some one or more particulars with which we are
acquainted. I suspect that even the
Universe, as considered by metaphysics, involves such a connection with
particulars. In logic, on the contrary,
where we are concerned not merely with what does exist, but with whatever might
or could exist or be, no reference to actual particulars is involved.
It would
seem that, when we make a statement about something only known by description,
we often intend to make our statement, not in the form involving the
description, but about the actual thing described. That is to say, when we say anything about
Bismarck, we should like, if we could, to make the judgement which Bismarck
alone can make, namely, the judgement of which he himself is a
constituent. In this we are necessarily
defeated, since the actual Bismarck is unknown to us. But we know that there is an object B called
Bismarck, and that B was an astute diplomatist.
We can thus describe the proposition we should like to affirm,
namely, 'B was an astute diplomatist', where B is the object which was
Bismarck. What enables us to communicate
in spite of the varying descriptions we employ is that we know there is a true
proposition concerning the actual Bismarck, and that, however we may vary the
description (so long as the description is correct), the proposition described
is still the same. This proposition,
which is described and is known to be true, is what interests us; but we are
not acquainted with the proposition itself, and do not know it, though
we know it is true.
It will be
seen that there are various stages in the removal from acquaintance with
particulars: there is
The
fundamental epistemological principle in the analysis of propositions
containing descriptions is this: Every proposition which we can understand
must be composed wholly of constituents with which we are acquainted. From what has been said already, it will be
plain why I advocate this principle, and how I propose to meet the case of
propositions which at first sight contravene it. Let us begin with the reasons for supposing
the principle true.
The chief
reason for supposing the principle true is that it seems scarcely possible to
believe that we can make a judgement or entertain a
supposition without knowing what it is that we are judging or supposing
about. It we make a judgement about
(say) Julius Caesar, it is plain that the actual person who was Julius Caesar
is not a constituent of the judgement.
But before going further, it may be well to explain what I mean when I
say that this or that is a constituent of a judgement, or of a proposition which
we understand. To begin with judgements:
a judgement, as an occurrence, I take to be a relation of a mind to several
entities, namely, the entities which compose what is judged. If, e.g. I judge that A loves B, the
judgement as an event consists in the existence, at a certain moment, of a
specific four-term relation, called judging, between me and A and love
and B. That is to say, at the time when
I judge, there is a certain complex whose terms are myself and A and love and
B, and whose relating relation is judging. My reasons for this view have been set fourth
elsewhere, [Philosophical Essays, 'The Nature of Truth'. I have been persuaded by Mr Wittgenstein that
this theory is somewhat unduly simple, but the modification which I believe it
to require not does affect the above argument. - 1917.] and I shall not repeat them
here. Assuming this view of judgement,
the constituents of the judgement are simply the constituents of the complex
which is the judgement. Thus, in the
above case, the constituents are myself and A and love
and B and judging. But myself and judging are constituents shared by all my
judgements; thus the distinctive constituents of the particular
judgement in question are A and love and B.
Coming now to what is meant by 'understanding a proposition', I should
say that there is another relation possible between me and A
and love and B, which is called my supposing that A loves B.
[Cf. Meinong, Ueber
Annahmen, passim.
I formerly supposed, contrary to Meinong's
view, that the relationship of supposing might be merely that of
presentation. In this view I now think I
was mistaken, and Meinong is right. But my present view depends upon the theory
that both in judgement and in assumption there is no single Objective, but the
several constituents of the judgement or assumption are in a many-term relation
to the mind.]
When we can suppose that A loves B, we 'understand the
proposition' A loves B. Thus we can understand a proposition in cases
where we have not enough knowledge to make a judgement. Supposing, like judging, is a many-term
relation, of which a mind is one term.
The other terms of the relation are called the constituents of the
proposition supposed. Thus the principle
which I enunciated may be re-stated as follows: Whenever a relation of
supposing or judging occurs, the terms to which the supposing or judging mind
is related by the relation of supposing or judging must be terms with which the
mind in question is acquainted. This
is merely to say that we cannot make a judgement or a supposition without
knowing what it is that we are making our judgement or supposition about. It seems to me that the truth of this
principle is evident as soon as the principle is understood; I shall therefore,
in what follows, assume the principle, and use it as a guide in analysing
judgements that contain descriptions.
Returning
now to Julius Caesar, I assume that it will be admitted that he himself is not
a constituent of any judgement which I can make. But at this point it is necessary to examine
the view that judgements are composed of something called 'ideas', and that it
is the 'idea' of Julius Caesar that is a constituent of my judgement. I believe the plausibility of this view rests
upon a failure to form a right theory of descriptions. We may mean by my 'idea' of Julius Caesar the
things that I know about him, e.g. that he conquered Gaul, was assassinated on
the Ides of March, and is a plague to schoolboys. Now I am admitting, and indeed contending,
that in order to discover what is actually in my mind when I judge about Julius
Caesar, we must substitute for the proper name a description made up of some of
the things I know about him. (A
description which will often serve to express my thought is 'the man whose name
was Julius Caesar.' For whatever
else I may have forgotten about him, it is plain that when I mention him I have
not forgotten that that was his name.)
But although I think the theory that judgements consist of ideas may
have been suggested in some such way, yet I think the theory itself is
fundamentally mistaken. The view seems
to be that there is some mental existent which may be called the 'idea' of
something outside the mind of the person who has the idea, and that, since
judgement is a mental event, its constituents must be constituents of the mind
of the person judging. But in this view
ideas become a veil between us and outside things - we never really, in
knowledge, attain to the things we are supposed to be knowing
about, but only to the ideas of those things.
The relation of mind, idea, and object, on this view, is utterly
obscure, and, so far as I can see, nothing discoverable by inspection warrants
the intrusion of the idea between the mind and the object. I suspect that the view is fostered by the
dislike of relations, and that it is felt the mind could not know objects
unless there were something 'in' the mind which could be called the state of
knowing the object. Such a view,
however, leads at once to a vicious endless regress, since the relation of idea
to object will have to be explained by supposing that the idea itself has an
idea of the object, and so on ad infinitum. I therefore see no reason to believe that,
when we are acquainted with an object, there is in us something which can be
called the 'idea' of the object. On the
contrary, I hold the acquaintance is wholly a relation, not demanding any such
constituent of the mind as is supposed by advocates of 'ideas'. This is, of course, a large question, and one
which would take us far from our subject if it were adequately discussed. I therefore content myself with the above
indications, and with the corollary that, in judging, the actual objects
concerning which we judge, rather than any supposed purely mental entities, are
constituents of the complex which is the judgement.
When,
therefore, I say that we must substitute for 'Julius Caesar' some description
of Julius Caesar, in order to discover the meaning of a judgement nominally
about him, I am not saying that we must substitute an idea. Suppose our description is 'the man whose
name was Julius Caesar'. Let our
judgement be 'Julius Caesar was assassinated'.
Then it becomes 'the man whose name was Julius Caesar was
assassinated'. Here Julius Caesar
is a noise or shape with which we are acquainted, and all the other
constituents of the judgement (neglecting the tense in 'was') are concepts
with which we are acquainted. Thus our
judgement is wholly reduced to constituents with which
we are acquainted, but Julius Caesar himself has ceased to be a constituent of
our judgement. This, however, requires a
proviso, to be further explained shortly, namely, that 'the man whose name was Julius
Caesar' must not, as a whole, be a constituent of our judgement, that is to
say, this phrase must not, as a whole, have a meaning which enters into the
judgement. Any right analysis of the
judgement, therefore, must break up this phrase, and not treat it as a
subordinate complex which is part of the judgement. The judgement 'the man whose name was Julius
Caesar was assassinated' may be interpreted as meaning 'one and only one
man was called Julius Caesar, and that one was assassinated'. Here it is plain that there is no constituent
corresponding to the phrase, 'the man whose name was Julius Caesar'. Thus there is no reason to regard this phrase
as expressing a constituent of the judgement, and we have seen that this phrase
must be broken up if we are to be acquainted with all the constituents of the
judgement. This conclusion, which we
have reached from considerations concerned with the theory of knowledge, is
also forced upon us by logical considerations, which must now be briefly
reviewed.
It is common to distinguish two aspects, meaning and denotation, in such phrases as 'the author of Waverley'. The meaning will be a certain complex, consisting (at least) of authorship and Waverley with some relation; the denotation will be Scott. Similarly 'featherless bipeds' will have a complex meaning, containing as constituents the presence of two feet and the absence of feathers, while its denotation will be the class of men. Thus when we say 'Scott is the author of Waverley' or 'men are the same as featherless bipeds', we are asserting an identity of denotation, and this assertion is worth making because of the diversity of meaning. [This view has been recently advocated by Miss E.E.C. Jones. 'A New Law of Thought and its Implications', Mind, January, 1911.] I believe that the duality of meaning and denotation, though capable of a true interpretation, is misleading if taken as fundamental. The denotation, I believe, is not a constituent of the proposition, except in the case of proper names, i.e. of words which do not assign a property to an object, but merely and solely name it. And I should hold further that, in this sense, there are only two words which are strictly proper names of particulars, namely, 'I' and 'this'. [I should now exclude 'I' from proper names in the strict sense, and retain only 'this'. - 1917].
One reason
for not believing the denotation to be a constituent of the proposition is that
we may know the proposition even when we are not acquainted with the
denotation. The proposition 'the author
of Waverley is a novelist' was known to people who did not know that 'the
author of Waverley' denoted Scott. This
reason has been already sufficiently emphasized.
A second
reason is that propositions concerning 'the so-and-so' are possible even when
'the so-and-so' has no denotation. Take,
e.g. 'the golden mountain does not exist' or 'the round square is
self-contradictory'. If we are to
preserve the duality of meaning and denotation, we have to say, with Meinong, that there are such objects as the golden mountain
and the round square, although these objects do not have being. We even have to admit that the existent round
square is existent, but does not exist [Meinong,
Ueber Annahmen,
2nd ed., Leipzig, 1910, p. 141.] Meinong does not regard this as a contradiction, but I fail
to see that it is not one. Indeed, it
seems to me evident that the judgement 'there is no such object as the round
square' does not presuppose that there is such an object. If this is admitted, however, we are led to
the conclusion that, by parity of form, no judgement concerning 'the so-and-so'
actually involves the so-and-so as a constituent.
Miss Jones
[Mind, July 1910, p. 380.] contends that
there is no difficulty in admitting contradictory predicates concerning such an
object as 'the present King of France', on the ground that this object is in itself contradictory.
Now it might, of course, be argued that this object, unlike the round
square, is not self-contradictory, but merely non-existent. This, however, would not go to the root of
the matter. The real objection to such
an argument is that the law of contradiction ought not to be stated in the
traditional form 'A' is not both B and not B', but in the form 'no proposition
is both true and false'. The traditional
form only applies to certain propositions, namely, to those which attribute a
predicate to a subject. When the law is
stated of propositions, instead of being stated concerned subjects and
predicates, it is at once evident that the propositions about the present King
of France or the round square can form no exception, but are just as incapable
of being both true and false as other propositions.
Miss Jones
[Mind, July 1910, p. 379.] argues that
'Scott is the author of Waverley' asserts identity of denotation between Scott
and the author of Waverley. But there
is some difficulty in choosing among alternative meanings of this
contention. In the first place, it
should be observed that the author of Waverley is not a mere
name, like Scott. Scott is
merely a noise or shape conventionally used to designate a certain person; it
gives us no information about that person, and has nothing that can be called
meaning as opposed to denotation. (I
neglect the fact, considered above, that even proper names, as a rule, really
stand for descriptions.) But the
author of
If, then, we are asserting identity of denotation, we must not mean
by denotation the mere relation of a name to the thing named. In fact, it would be nearer to the truth to
say that the meaning of 'Scott' is the denotation of 'the author
of Waverley'. The relation of 'Scott' to
Scott is that 'Scott' means Scott, just as the relation of 'author' to the
concept which is so called is that 'author' means this concept. Thus if we distinguish meaning and denotation
in 'the author of Waverley', we shall have to say that 'Scott' has meaning but
not denotation. Also when we say 'Scott
is the author of Waverley', the meaning of 'the author of Waverley' is
relevant to our assertion. For if the
denotation alone were relevant, any other phrase with the same denotation would
give the same proposition. Thus 'Scott
is the author of Marmion' would be the same
proposition as 'Scott is the author of Waverley'. But this is plainly not the case, sine from
the first we learn that Scott wrote Marmion and from
the second we learn that he wrote Waverley, but the first tells us nothing
about Waverley and the second nothing about Marmion. Hence the meaning of 'the author of
We have
thus agreed that 'the author of Waverley' is not a mere name, and that its
meaning is relevant in propositions in which it occurs. Thus if we are to say, as Miss Jones does,
that 'Scott is the author of Waverley' asserts an identity of denotation, we
must regard the denotation of 'the author of Waverley' as the denotation of what
is meant by 'the author of Waverley'.
Let us call the meaning of 'the author of Waverley' M. Thus M is what 'the author of Waverley'
means. Then we are to suppose that
'Scott is the author of Waverley' means 'Scott is the denotation of M'. But here we are explaining our proposition by
another of the same form, and thus we have made no progress towards a real
explanation. 'The denotation of M', like
'the author of Waverley', has both meaning and denotation, on the theory we are
examining. If we call its meaning M, our
proposition becomes 'Scott is the denotation of M'. But this leads at once to an endless
regress. Thus the attempt to regard our
proposition as asserting identity of denotation breaks down, and it becomes
imperative to find some other analysis.
When this analysis has been completed, we shall be able to reinterpret
the phrase 'identity of denotation', which remains obscure so long as it is
taken as fundamental.
The first point to observe is that, in any proposition about 'the author of Waverley', provided Scott is not explicitly mentioned, the denotation itself, i.e. Scott, does not occur, but only the concept of denotation, which will be represented by a variable. Suppose we say 'the author of Waverley was the author of Marmion', we are certainly not saying that both were Scott - we may have forgotten that there was such a person as Scott. We are saying that there is some man who was the author of Waverley and the author of Marmion. That is to say, there is someone who wrote Waverley and Marmion, and no-one else wrote them. Thus the identity is that of a variable, i.e. of an identifiable subject, 'someone'. This is why we can understand propositions about 'the author of Waverley', without knowing who he was. When we say 'the author of Waverley was a poet', we mean 'one and only one man wrote Waverley, and he was a poet'; when we say 'the author of Waverley was Scott' we mean 'one and only one man wrote Waverley, and he was Scott'. Here the identity is between the variable, i.e. an indeterminate subject ('he'), and Scott; 'the author of Waverley' has been analysed away, and no longer appears as a constituent of the proposition.' [The theory which I am advocating is set forth fully, with the logical grounds in its favour, in Principia Mathematica, Vol. I, Introduction, Chap. III; also, less fully, in Mind, October, 1905.]
The reason
why it is imperative to analyse away the phrase, 'the author of Waverley' may
be stated as follows. It is plain that
when we say 'the author of
We may now
define the denotation of a phrase. If we
know that the proposition 'a is the so-and-so' is true, i.e. that a
is so-and-so and nothing else is, we call a the
denotation of the phrase 'the so-and-so'.
A very great many of the propositions we naturally make about 'the
so-and-so' will remain true or remain false if we substitute a
for 'the so-and-so', where a is the denotation of 'the
so-and-so'. Such propositions will also
remain true or remain false if we substitute for 'the so-and-so' any other
phrase having the same denotation.
Hence, as practical men, we become interested in the denotation more
than in the description, since the denotation decides as to the truth or
falsehood of so many statements in which the description occurs. Moreover, as we saw earlier in considering
the relation of description and acquaintance, we often wish to reach the
denotation, and are only hindered by lack of acquaintance: in such cases the
description is merely the means we employ to get as near as possible to the
denotation. Hence it naturally comes to
be supposed that the denotation is part of the proposition in which the
description occurs. But we have seen, both
on logical and on epistemological grounds, that this is an error. The actual object (if any) which is the
denotation is not (unless it is explicitly mentioned) a constituent of
propositions in which descriptions occur; and this is the reason why, in order
to understand such propositions, we need acquaintance with the constituents of
the description, but do not need acquaintance with its denotation. The first result of analysis, when applied to
propositions whose grammatical subject is 'the so-and-so', is to substitute a
variable as subject; i.e. we obtain a proposition of the form: 'There is something
which alone is so-and-so, and that something is
such-and-such.' The further analysis of
propositions concerning 'the so-and-so' is thus merged in the problem of the
nature of the variable, i.e. of the meanings of some, any, and all. This is a difficult problem, concerning which
I do not intend to say anything at present.
To sum up
our whole discussion: We began by distinguishing two sorts of knowledge of
objects, namely, knowledge by acquaintance and knowledge by description. Of these it is only the former that brings
the object itself before the mind. We
have acquaintance with sense-data, with many universals, and possibly with
ourselves, but not with physical objects or other minds. We have descriptive knowledge of an
object when we know that it is the object having some property or
properties with which we are acquainted; that is to say, when we know that the
property or properties in question belong to one object and no more, we are
said to have knowledge of that one object by description, whether or not we are
acquainted with the object. Our
knowledge of physical objects and of other minds is only knowledge by
description, the description involved being usually such as involve
sense-data. All propositions
intelligible to us, whether or not they primarily concern things only known to
us by description, are composed wholly of constituents with which
we are acquainted, for a constituent with which we are not acquainted is
unintelligible to us. A judgement, we
found, is not composed of mental constituents called 'ideas', but consists of
an occurrence whose constituents are a mind [I use this phrase merely to
denote the something psychological which enters into judgement, without
intending to prejudge the question as to what this something is.] and certain objects, particulars or universals. (One at least must be universal.) When a judgement is rightly analysed, the
objects which are constituents of it must all be objects with which the mind
which is a constituent of it is acquainted.
This conclusion forces us to analyse descriptive phrases occurring in
propositions, and to say that the objects denoted by such phrases are not
constituents of judgements in which such phrases occur (unless these objects
are explicitly mentioned). This leads us
to the view (recommended also on purely logical grounds) that when we say 'the
author of Marmion was the author of Waverley', Scott
himself is not a constituent of our judgement, and that the judgement cannot be
explained by saying that it affirms identity of denotation with diversity of
meaning. It also, plainly, does not
assert identity of meaning. Such
judgements, therefore, can only be analysed by breaking up the descriptive
phrases, introducing a variable, and making propositional functions the
ultimate subjects. In fact, 'the
so-and-so is such-and-such' will mean that 'x is so-and-so and nothing
else is, and x is such-and-such' is capable of truth. The analysis of such judgements involves many
fresh problems, but the discussion of these problems is not undertaken in the
present paper.
MYSTICISM AND LOGIC (polychrome version)