What I
Owe to the Ancients
1
In conclusion, a word on that world into
which I have sought to find a way, into which I have perhaps found a new way -
the ancient world. My taste, which may
be called the opposite of a tolerant taste, is even here far from uttering a
wholesale Yes: in general it dislikes saying Yes, it
would rather say No, most of all it prefers to say nothing at all.... This
applies to entire cultures, it applies to books - it also applies to towns and countrysides. It is
really only quite a small number of books of antiquity which count for anything
in my life; the most famous are not among them.
My sense of style, of the epigram as style, was awoken almost instantaneously
on coming into contact with Sallust. I have not forgotten the astonishment of my
honoured teacher Corssen when he had to give top
marks to his worst Latin scholar - I had done all in a single blow. Compact, severe, with as
much substance as possible, a cold malice towards 'fine words', also towards
'fine feelings' - in that I knew myself.
One will recognize in my writings, even in my Zarathustra,
a very serious ambition for Roman style, for the 'aera
perennius' [more enduring than brass] in style - I had the same experience on first coming into contact
with Horace. From that day to this no
poet has given me the same artistic delight as I derived from the very first
from an Horatian ode. In certain languages what is achieved here is
not even desirable. This mosaic
of words in which every word, as sound, as locus, as concept, pours fourth its
power to left and right and over the whole, this minimum in the range and
number of signs which achieves a maximum of energy of these signs - all this is
Roman and, if one will believe me, noble par excellence. All other poetry becomes by comparison
somewhat too popular - a mere emotional garrulousness ...
2
I received absolutely no such strong
impressions from the Greeks; and, not to mince words, they cannot be to
us what the Romans are. One does not learn
from the Greeks - their manner is too strange, it is also too fluid to produce
an imperative, a 'classical' effect. Who
would ever have learned to write from a Greek!
Who would ever have learned it without the Romans! ... Let no-one
offer me Plato as an objection. In
respect to Plato I am a thorough sceptic and have always been unable to join in
the admiration of Plato the artist which is traditional among
scholars. After all, I have here the
most refined judges of taste of antiquity themselves on my side. It seems to me that Plato mixes together all
forms of style; he is therewith in the matter of style a first décadent: he has on his conscience something similar to
the Cynics who devised the Satura Menippea. [Menippus (third century B.C.), of the Cynic school of philosophy,
produced a number of satires no longer extant.] For the Platonic dialogue, that frightfully self-satisfied
and childish kind of dialectics, to operate as a stimulus one must never have
read any good French writers - Fontenelle, for
example. Plato is boring. - Ultimately
my mistrust of Plato extends to the very bottom of him: I have him deviated so
far from all the fundamental instincts of the Hellenes, so morally infected, so
much an antecedent Christian - he already has the concept 'good' as the supreme
concept - that I should prefer to describe the entire phenomenon 'Plato' by the
harsh term 'higher swindle' or, if you prefer, 'idealism', than by any other. It has cost us dear that this Athenian went
to school with the Egyptians (- or with the Jews in
3
From scenting out 'beautiful souls', [From the title of Book VII of Goethe's
novel WILHELM MEISTER'S APPRENTICESHIP: 'Confessions of a Beautiful Soul'.] 'golden means' and other perfections of
the Greeks, from admiring in them such things as their repose in grandeur,
their ideal disposition, their sublime simplicity - from this 'sublime
simplicity', a niaiserie allemande [German foolishness] when all is said and done, I was
preserved by the psychologist in me. I
saw their strongest instinct, the will to power, I saw them trembling at the
intractable force of this drive - I saw all their institutions evolve out of
protective measures designed for mutual security against the explosive
material within them. The tremendous
internal tension then discharged itself in fearful and ruthless external
hostility: the city states tore one another to pieces so that the citizens of
each of them might find peace within himself. One needed to be strong: danger was close at
hand - it lurked everywhere. The
splendid supple physique, the reckless realism and immoralism
which pertains to the Hellene was a necessity, not a 'natural
quality'. It was produced,
it was not there from the beginning. And
one employed festivals and arts for no other purpose than to feel oneself dominant, to show oneself dominant:
they are means for making oneself feared.... To judge the Greeks by their
philosophers, in the German manner, perchance to employ the philistinism of the
Socratic schools as a clue to what is fundamentally Hellenic! ... But the
philosophers are the décadents of Hellenism,
the counter-movement against the old, the noble taste (- against the agonal instinct, against the polis, against the
value of the race, against the authority of tradition). The Socratic virtues were preached because
the Greeks had lost them: excitable, timid, fickle, comedians every one, they
had more than enough reason to let morality be preached to them. Not that it would have done any good: but big
words and fine attitudes are so suited to décadents ...
4
I was the first to take seriously that
wonderful phenomenon which bears the name Dionysus as a means to understanding
the older Hellenic instinct, an instinct still exuberant and even overflowing:
it is explicable only as an excess of energy. Whoever has investigated the Greeks, such as
that profoundest student of their culture now living, Jacob Burckhardt
of
5
The psychology of the orgy as an
overflowing feeling of life and energy within which even pain acts as a stimulus
provided me with the key to the concept of the tragic feeling, which was
misunderstood as much by Aristotle as it especially was by our pessimists. Tragedy is so far from providing evidence for
pessimism among the Hellenes in Schopenhauer's sense that it has to be
considered the decisive repudiation of that idea and the counter-verdict
to it. Affirmation of life even in its
strangest and sternest problems, the will to life rejoicing in its own
inexhaustibility through the sacrifice of its highest types - that
is what I called Dionysian, that is what I recognized as the bridge to
the psychology of the tragic poet.
Not so as to get rid of pity and terror, not so as to purify
oneself of a dangerous emotion through its vehement discharge - it was thus Aristotle
understood it - : but, beyond pity and terror, to realize in oneself the
eternal joy of becoming - that joy which also encompasses joy in destruction....
And with that I again return to the place from which I set out - the Birth
of Tragedy was my first revaluation of all values: with that I again plant
myself in the soil out of which I draw all that I will and can - I, the
last disciple of the philosopher Dionysus - I, the teacher of the eternal
recurrence ... [For
Nietzsche's theory that all events recur eternally and its emotional
significance in providing the most extreme formula of life-affirmation, see
THUS SPOKE ZARATHUSTRA, Part III ('Of the Vision and the Riddle', 'The
Convalescent' and 'The Seven Seals') and Part IV ([The Intoxicated Song').]