THE
FALL
OF LOVE
Philosophical
Essays
Copyright
©
1979–2012 John O'Loughlin
________________
CONTENTS
1.
Classic
and Decadent Literature
2.
Music
in the Western World
3.
An
Outline of Transcendental Meditation
4.
Partial
Knowledge
5.
Urban
Sterility and the Modern Soul
6.
The
Fall of Love
_______________
CLASSIC
AND
DECADENT LITERATURE
There
are
fundamentally always two kinds of art: the classic and
the decadent. "What are called
classic," writes
Most people are
undoubtedly familiar with the romantic aspect of decadence as
exemplified in
the music of composers such as Liszt, Beethoven (particularly his late
works),
Schubert, Chopin, Weber, et al., where 'the whole' is generally
subordinated to
'the parts' and sentiment gets the better of form.
Likewise most people are familiar with the
classicism of Mozart, Haydn, the early Beethoven, and even much of
Mendelssohn,
where 'the parts' are generally subordinated to 'the whole' and form
gets the
better of sentiment. This classic/romantic
dichotomy is especially apparent in music, but it is also apparent in
the arts
of poetry, literature, sculpture, architecture, and painting, where one
or
another of the two creative tendencies are
usually
found to predominate.
Some artists, it is
true, seem to be a subtle combination of both classicism and decadence
(to use
the more comprehensive term), or at least they display a mostly classic
or
decadent approach to their respective arts at different stages in their
creative lives. But a majority of
artists seem to be mainly one or the other, and to remain fairly
consistently
so, throughout the course of their creative lives.
It also seems that the classic tends to
alternate with the decadent, and that an epoch in art may be
characterized by
the prevalence of whichever tendency happens to predominate during that
time. On average an art epoch tends to
last between twenty and forty years, and each successive epoch becomes
a
revolt, in one way or another, against the preceding one.
This is especially true of the early
twentieth century, which heralded in the works of authors like D.H.
Lawrence,
Thomas Hardy, André Gide, Hermann Hesse,
and John Cowper Powys a classical revival in reaction to the
predominating tone
of fin-de-siècle
decadence which had immediately preceded it.
There are, however,
always exceptions to the general rule, and one finds certain writers
producing
works seemingly quite out-of-character with the prevailing tendency of
their
epoch: writers, for example, like Knut Hamsun, who wrote predominantly classic
literature during
the last decade of the nineteenth century, and, conversely, Aldous
Huxley, who, in his otherworldly and mystical predilections, was
arguably an
outsider in relation to early twentieth-century classicism! Of course, one could argue that Hamsun, who continued to write in a
predominantly classical
spirit well into the twentieth century, was really a herald and
forerunner of
the classical revival, and that Huxley was effectively a protracted
extension
of fin-de-siècle
decadence. But whatever the
case, it should be apparent
that this general alternation between the two schools of art provides
the
necessary incentive for each school to flourish in the manner most
suited to
itself, since without a tension of opposites there would be little or
no chance
of maintaining either!
I began by citing
Havelock Ellis' definitions of the two main kinds of art, and in order
to
clarify the differences between them, as well as extend our study of
this into
an investigation of the leading creative tendencies of a number of
individual
authors, I would like to define, in greater detail, exactly what
I
consider to be the two chief forms of literary classicism and decadence
respectively.
Firstly, there is the
classicism of what Ellis calls "The love of natural things", which is
to say, the appreciation of nature both as it confronts our vision as external
phenomena and our understanding as internal phenomena. Thus these natural phenomena may range over a
vast area of experience which encompasses anything from the splendour
of a
brightly-burning sun glimpsed at midday to the celestial beauty of
certain star
formations seen at midnight; from the mystery of birth to the mystery
of death;
from the changing generations of man to the constancy of human life;
from the
daily intake of food and drink to the daily voiding of excrement and
urine, and
so on. The love of natural things, which
was brought to such a high pitch in the pagan culture of the early
Classical
Age, only to be superseded by Christian decadence, with its emphasis on
the
Beyond and the futility of worldly life, finds one of its earliest and
most
notable Western supporters in Michel de Montaigne,
who
lived
towards the close of the Middle Ages and whose legendary tower,
containing thousands of mostly classical writings, provided him with
both the
necessary vantage-point over and isolation from his age through which
to
transcend its decadent limitations and, by turning his scholarly
attention back
towards the ancient Greeks, to indirectly point the way forward towards
the
long-awaited future revival of the classical ideal, as understood by a
love of
natural things.
In more recent times,
however, one finds this form of classicism brought to a veritable
apotheosis in
D.H. Lawrence, who must surely rank as one of the few great classic
poets of
Western literature, as also in some of the works of André Gide,
notably Fruits
of
the Earth, and still more recently in Gide's
great classical heir and spiritual disciple, Albert Camus, whose outstanding fictional character,
Patrice Mersault, remains one of the most
poignant examples of
twentieth-century classicism that we possess.
With his emphasis on sun and sea, human love and human
happiness,
sensual enjoyment, travel, frugality, physicality, etc., Camus
returns us to the simplicity and ancient nobility of pagan life, and
never more
seductively so than in lyrical essays like
Nuptials (1939) and Summer (1954). "Over the sea," he writes in Nuptials
at Tipasa, "hangs the vast silence of
But there is another
voice which runs roughly parallel with what may be termed secular
naturalism,
and has also become louder in recent times.
I refer, of course, to the voice of religious naturalism. This classicism extends beyond the largely
aesthetic surface appreciation of nature by those authors dedicated to
secular
naturalism, and embraces a pantheistic or semi-pantheistic appreciation
of it,
such as one finds to varying extents in Goethe and Rousseau in the
eighteenth
century, in Wordsworth, Emerson, Thoreau, Whitman, and Arnold in the
nineteenth
century, and in Hardy, Hesse, and, most
poignantly,
John Cowper Powys in the twentieth century.
This religious aspect of man's relationship to nature is
perfectly
expressed in Wordsworth's Lines
Composed
a few miles above Tintern Abbey,
wherein the poet tells of:-
"...
a sense sublime
Of
something far more deeply interfused,
Whose
dwelling is the light of setting suns,
And
the round ocean and the living air,
And the blue sky, and in the mind of man."
Likewise we find, in his
essay On
Nature, Emerson writing: "It seems as if the day was
not wholly profane, in which we have given heed to some natural
object." -
This, then, is the positive side of classical naturalism, the side we
find
predominating in John Cowper Powys, particularly in works such as The
Art
of
Happiness, A Philosophy of Solitude, and In Defence
of
Sensuality, where his philosophy of 'Elementalism',
or
the
cult of nature worship, draws our attention to a partly spiritual
rather
than simply material identification with nature. If
D.H.
Lawrence stands out as the leading
British exponent of profane naturalism in the first-half of the
twentieth
century, then John Cowper Powys must surely rank as the leading British
exponent of religious naturalism - its spiritual counterpart.
However,
contemporaneously with the natural form of classicism we find another
form, on
the whole a less noble and agreeable form but, nevertheless, one which
has also
made itself increasingly heard in recent years: what might be termed
the
classicism of social phenomena, or the love of everyday life. If the most suitable term we could find to
define
the first form of classicism was naturalism, then this second form of
it can
only be defined in terms of realism, albeit a realism that accepts
rather than
rejects the society or life it strives to portray.
Indeed, such a classical realism regularly
delights in the minutiae of everyday commonplace life, committing
itself to a
portrayal of even the most seemingly trivial actions and situations. It is not the sublime colours of various
kinds of flowers, the beauty of a sunset, the mystery of birth and
death, or a
spiritual identification with plant life which mostly concerns the
authors of
this school but, on the contrary, such things as the baseness of
certain
people, the seductive powers of various women, the financial positions
of
particular individuals, the nature of so-and-so's clandestine amours,
etc.,
which goad their pens into scathing action.
To some extent one might
divide this school of writers into nobles and plebeians, or those who,
whatever
their social background, grant most of their literary attention to the
portrayal of grand-bourgeois and upper-class life and, conversely,
those who
grant most of it to the portrayal of
working-class and petty-bourgeois life.
This distinction is, I believe, relatively significant, because
it helps
us to know whether the realism in question is likely to be clean or
dirty,
proud or humble, prim or obscene, rich or poor, choice or vulgar, etc.
etc.,
according to the context. The most
typical examples of the 'noble' classical-realist tradition are authors
such as
Stendhal, Flaubert, Proust, Turgenev,
Henry James, and Thomas Mann, while the tradition of 'plebeian'
classical
realism calls to mind authors like Dickens, Balzac, Zola, Hamsun,
Joyce, and Henry Miller. Obviously there
are exceptions and borderline cases, and no-one can be classified as
wholly one
thing or another. But, for purposes of a
fairly tenable categorization, such generalizations are not without
some merit.
Having briefly dealt
with the main classical literary approaches based solely on theme, it
is now
time for us to examine, in slightly greater detail, their decadent and
more
prevalent antitheses, which, at least in one of their popular
manifestations,
correspond to what Havelock Ellis defines as: "The research for the
things
which seem to lie beyond Nature."
As I attempted to describe the classic forms in a given order, I
shall
do the same with their decadent counterparts, and thereby endeavour to
highlight the corresponding antitheses to each classic form.
Firstly we have the
decadence which stands in opposition to profane naturalism, the
decadence,
namely, of profane antinaturalism and
aestheticism. One finds here a
predominating tone of disgust with natural facts and occurrences, a
revolt
against the natural-world-order, against the apparent beauty or utility
of
various natural phenomena, against the imposition to eat, drink, sleep,
copulate, urinate, defecate, etc., which invariably characterizes the
lifestyles of human beings. It's as
though man, the eternal slave of nature, wishes to overcome nature, to
live, in
a spirit of reckless defiance, outside of and beyond it.
A very clear example of this disgust with the
natural-world-order, particularly that aspect of it entailing
defecation, is to
be found in Jonathan Swift in the eighteenth century.
But more recent examples undoubtedly include
Baudelaire, Wilde, Huysmans, Beckett, Genêt, and Sartre, whose various natural bêtes
noires confirm their respective claims
to the kind of
decadence we are characterizing by disgust with natural phenomena. In the late-nineteenth century this disgust
reached a veritable apogee with Huysmans' Against
the
Grain, whose leading character, Des Esseintes,
contrives
to
live in complete solitude in his specially-designed villa at Fontenay, to pass much of his time there in a
highly-sophisticated aesthetic contemplation of certain choice works,
both
literary and plastic, and to avoid, as far as possible, any direct
contact with
the outside world. Unfortunately for him,
this life of aesthetic sophistication - with its unbounded admiration
for such hyperdecadent artists and poets
as Redon,
Luyken, Moreau, Poe, Baudelaire, and Mallarmé - eventually leads to a series of
nervous crises
which, in their final consummation, make it imperative for him to
return to the
less-unnatural world of Parisian society from which he had so earnestly
fled. As is well known, Against the
Grain was to have a profound influence on Oscar Wilde, and his Picture
of
Dorian
Gray, though less decadent than its great French prototype,
nevertheless
brought this kind of writing to a head in late-nineteenth-century
However, with the
general change of literary approach to one of classicism in the early
decades
of the next century, profane antinaturalism,
though
not
entirely vanquished, played a much-less pervasive role.
But its voice began to reappear from time to
time in the 'thirties, and never more unashamedly so than in Sartre's
Nausea
(1938). Like the protagonist
of Huysmans' novel, Antoine Roquentin
lives against the grain. But he lives
against the grain of life as life rather than as time spoilt
by human
folly, without even the consolation or raison d'être of the
sophisticated aestheticism which Huysmans'
tragic
character reserves for himself. If human
folly is a sufficiently strong motive to drive Des Esseintes
into a monk-like isolation from society, in order to lead a life he
considers
to be of some intrinsic value (the Nietzschean
overtones of which are impossible to ignore), the only motive strong
enough to
isolate Roquentin from humanity is the
sheer
absurdity of life itself, the apparent pointlessness of an existence
which
exists for no other reason than its inability not to
exist, and
the contemplation of which engenders that disgust and revolt epitomized
by the
word 'nausea'. When, trapped in a moment
of such nausea in the local park at Bouville,
Roquentin shouts: "What filth! What
filth!", it
is with all the poignant anguish of one who realizes that existence is
eternal
and inescapable, and that it's therefore impossible for anything,
including the
idea of existence, not to exist. The man
is virtually suffocating in the oppressive consciousness of existence,
which,
aggravated by the realization that external phenomena are like masks
over the
uniform substance of things, is as apparent in the sight of a gnarled
tree root
as in the rest of the tree itself.
Fortunately for him, however, this oppressive consciousness is
an
intermittent rather than a permanent condition, so Roquentin
is enabled to breathe a clearer air, so to speak, once the 'nausea' has
passed.
While discussing
Sartre's general approach to decadence, which is essentially Protestant
in
character, it is worth drawing attention to his psychoanalytical
biography of
Baudelaire, a key work in the understanding of decadent consciousness. For by dwelling on the psychological rather
than the purely material or factual aspects of his subject's life,
Sartre lays
bare the underlining consciousness of profane antinaturalism
with a sureness and deftness only to be expected from a profoundly
kindred
spirit. Speculative though much of the
work may be, we are inexorably led towards the conclusion that the
dedication
and fastidiousness with which Baudelaire applied himself to the
regulation of
his decadent lifestyle - and thus to the perpetuation of a calculated
degree of
spiritual sterility (aecidia) - was of such a magnitude as to make even
the
lifestyle of Huysmans' Des Esseintes
appear comparatively naturalistic!
As a spiritual
counterpart to the above-mentioned types of decadence and antithesis to
the
classicism we defined as religious naturalism, we find the decadence of
supernaturalism, or religious antinaturalism. Unlike its profane cousin, this is a positive
decadence, and one which, since the decline of Christianity (hitherto
its chief
Western manifestation), has increasingly come to be identified with
spiritualism, visionary experience, mysticism, astrology, the occult,
etc. With an emphasis on that which seems
to lie beyond
nature, supernaturalism has been championed by poets and writers such
as
William Blake, August Strindberg, J.K. Huysmans,
Barbey D'Aurevilly,
George
William
Russell (A.E.), W.B. Yeats, Aldous
Huxley,
Dennis Wheatley, and Colin Wilson, each with his own particular field
of
investigation. Thus, for example, we
find William Blake and George William Russell bringing to their
writings the
fruits of mystical and visionary experience more usually perceived by
artists,
that is to say, on a lower plane than the predominantly religious
natures. In this context, mysticism is
identified with
partial experience of the Godhead, or World Soul, through meditation of
a less
pure and impersonal kind than with the non-artistic and predominantly
religious
natures, while visionary experience is likewise identified with psychic
spectacles of a less pure and impersonal kind: human figures, chimeras,
transparent fruit, palaces, sickle moons, etc., which are individually
illuminated from the inside by variously- or uniformly-coloured lights
that set
them off against a dark background. Or,
alternatively, with spectacles of magnificent landscapes, seascapes, or
airscapes which are embellished with
self-luminous objects,
like gems. The highest visionary
experience tends to involve the contemplation of an intensely pure
inner light,
but, as a rule, this is not the visionary experience given to artists.
Indeed, it is primarily
on account of his knowledge about
such
psychic phenomena that we are justified in placing Aldous
Huxley in the context of the kind of decadence we're now discussing. For although he passed his life devoid of any
genuine mystical or visionary experience, his interest in and knowledge
about
such matters makes him an invaluable source of information to anyone
anxious to
acquire a general outline of what they entail and whom they concern.
(It is
interesting to note that the change of visual orientation Huxley
experienced
through the judicious use of mescaline, as described in The
Doors
of
Perception & Heaven and Hell, admits him, via the
contemplation of a
few flowers in a small glass vase, to "The miracle, moment by moment,
of
naked existence", which, in complete contrast to the naked existence
experienced by Antoine Roquentin in Nausea,
is
"Neither
agreeable nor disagreeable. It just is.")
Similarly one might
argue that the sceptical Huysmans (not the
later
Catholic convert) possessed a tendency to investigate and relate that
which was
fundamentally alien to his fundamental nature, and nowhere more clearly
so than
in the novel Down
Below
(Là Bas), where, largely
in consequence of his historical research into the life and crimes of
the
notorious fifteenth-century Satanist, Gilles de Rais,
its
leading
character, Durtal, becomes
acquainted
with late-nineteenth-century Satanism, though purely as an outsider. Here, too, we find Huysmans
confined, as an artist, to a mainly objective knowledge of occult
phenomena,
since a high degree of subjective knowledge here would inevitably have
turned
him into a religious propagandist and thereby prevented him from
functioning as
a genuine writer. Conversely we find
that Yeats, who was definitely a genuine writer, laid claim to a
certain amount
of subjective knowledge in spiritualism, and certainly his experiments
in
psychical research would seem to make him less of a 'spiritual
outsider' than
most other spiritually-inclined writers.
But, even so, there was much of the sceptic about Yeats and,
though
spiritualism may have appealed to his curiosity, it is doubtful that he
would have
become such an important poetic figure in early-twentieth-century
literature
had he allowed it to play a greater role in his life and writings than
it
apparently did. And the same, I suspect,
may be held true of Strindberg, whose Occult Diary stands
as
a
fairly isolated phenomenon in an otherwise predominantly rational
output.
However, let us now
progress to the second form of decadence, a decadence which may also be
subdivided into a positive and a negative approach, and deal, firstly,
with
what we shall term positive antirealism - the antithesis of 'noble'
classical
realism. This type of decadence also has
a number of branches at its disposal, but each of them is dedicated to
the sole
end of transcending, on as imaginative a plane as possible, the usual
references to the everyday reality of the classical realist. Thus it is a positive decadence because, like
the supernaturalism referred to above, it does not directly attack its
antithesis but, on the contrary, seeks to overcome it through the
establishment
of its own unique world, an imaginary world with a realism peculiar to
itself.
The most famous
contemporary example of this kind of writing is undoubtedly J.R.R. Tolkien's The
Lord
of the Rings - a work
of such imaginative scope as to be virtually in a class by itself. Frankly, there is nothing in the comparative
decadent literature of any age or time that can be placed by the side
of this
colossal feat of the imagination, and the human race may have to wait
many
years yet, before anything of equal import is produced, assuming
anything like
that could ever be produced again. For
in this sphere of creativity, Tolkien has
no
peer. He is virtually a god, a monster
of the imagination whose other works, including The Hobbit, Farmer
Giles of
Ham, and The Silmarillion, both
confirm and
consolidate his reputation as the foremost imaginative author of the
age. (To
the extent that we are categorizing various authors according to their
leading
creative tendencies, it should be apparent that, inasmuch as his
creative life
was solely dedicated to this particular branch of antirealism, Tolkien is one of the easiest and most clear-cut
authors to
categorize.) Other examples of this kind
of decadence include Lewis Carroll's
However, with this
highly imaginative branch of positive antirealism, which mostly appeals
to
children, there exists another and more adult branch, which again comes
in
various guises and which may be characterized by creations, on the one
hand,
like Goethe's Faust,
Maturin's Melmoth
the Wanderer, and Lautréamont's
Maldoror (whose omnipotent hero is
able to do
anything from turning himself into a cricket in Paris drains, to
swinging Mervyn, a helpless victim of his
spleen, around on the end
of a rope on the top of the Vendôme
Column, with a
view to precipitating him, projectile-like, in the general direction of
the Panthèon), and by creations, on the
other hand, like Jules
Verne's Twenty Thousand Leagues Under the Sea, H.G. Wells' The
War
of
the Worlds, and John Wyndham's The Day of the Triffids. The
first type tends to involve men or beings
who have been supernaturally endowed with special powers, usually to
the
detriment of other men, while the second type, in complete contrast,
focuses
one's attention on the struggle between men and nonhuman or subhuman
aggressors
who are stronger and more formidable than their human adversaries. In both cases, an unreal world is created,
but unlike that of Tolkien's hobbits,
which is pure
fantasy, it is one in which human beings are directly involved and, as
a
consequence, usually in a context not terribly far removed from the
bounds of
plausibility.
But there exists, in
addition to these otherworldly interpretations of positive antirealist
decadence, another interpretation which, while providing one with a
glimpse
into a different world from that usually portrayed in classical
realism,
nevertheless remains more attached to the real world than to any
imaginary
one. I refer, of course, to the
'romantic' decadence of authors such as Gerard de Nerval,
whose
Journey
to
the Orient unfolds vast worlds of
exotic experience not to be encountered between the pages of Stendhal,
Flaubert
(except in Salammbô), Proust,
or Henry James. One could of course
argue that works like Journey to the Orient are essentially classic, insofar as they endeavour to portray,
objectively
and unmaliciously, a society existing
abroad rather
than the one into which the author was born.
But, on deeper reflection, it does seem that the desire to
portray a
society other than one's own is fundamentally or implicitly a rejection
or, at
the very least, criticism of that society, and therefore something that
can
only be interpreted in terms of 'romantic' decadence: the need to turn
one's
back on familiar reality and, in consequence, explore the relatively
unfamiliar
reality of a different people.
Another more striking
example of this 'romantic' interpretation of positive antirealism,
however, can
be found in works which either take one back in time to 'the Culture'
or to
'the Civilization' (in the Spenglerian
sense of those
terms as described in The
Decline
of the West) of a remote
society, or forward in time to what the author supposes a future
society will
be like. Flaubert's Salammbô is an excellent example of this
tendency from
the historical point-of-view, while Hesse's
The
Glass Bead Game endeavours to portray an elite society of
ultra-refined
intellectuals who live, a few centuries hence, completely isolated from
the
everyday world of commerce in a civilization (Castalia) dedicated to
the study,
appreciation, assessment, and, where possible, manipulation of what is
best in
Western culture. The devotees of this
cult of the past do not, as a rule, create anything original themselves. For as members of a late 'Civilization' they
are obliged to sustain themselves on the accumulated cultural wealth of
earlier
centuries, rather like the ancient Greeks during the Hellenistic period. To some extent they are future Diderôts, compilers of a vast 'encyclopaedia' of
Western
culture; an achievement, however, which is destined to be discarded,
along with
its compilers, the 'Bead Game' players, come the dawn of a subsequent
'Culture'.
It is worth noting that Hesse, the outstanding master of this branch of
antirealism, had previously taken us back to the world of Medieval
Germany, to
the heart of the Western 'Culture', in his novel Narziss
and Goldmund, where Goldmund, its
principal character, carves a picaresque-like role for himself in
blatantly heathenistic opposition to the
prevailing Zeitgeist,
through his desire for sensual gratification.
The ascetic Narziss and the
hedonistic Goldmund, representing the
contrary claims of spirit and
body, are finally reconciled, however, when Goldmund,
certain
to
be executed for crimes appertaining to his former lifestyle, is
rescued from prison by Narziss and brought
back to
the monastic order from which he had sought worldly escape: a sort of
Des Esseintes in reverse, from spirit to
body and back to
spirit again. One might say that whereas
the body ultimately triumphs (through Joseph Knecht's
resignation from the Castalian order) in
'the
Civilization' of The Glass Bead Game, it is the spirit which is
compelled to triumph (through Goldmund's
reconciliation with the monastic order) in 'the Culture' of Narziss and Goldmund,
and
so
we are made conscious of the profound logic and inevitability of the
events
underlining its impressive dénouement.
Having dealt with the
chief branches of the decadence we have described as positive
antirealism, it
is now time for us to deal with its spiritual counterpart, which we
shall describe
as negative antirealism. This type of
decadence stands in an antithetical relationship to what we earlier
termed
'plebeian' classical realism, and its chief manifestations inevitably
take the
guise of defeatism, rebellion, and satire.
Now whereas the 'plebeian' classical-realist attitude more or
less
accepts the society it portrays or, at any rate, doesn't unduly attack
it, the
negative antirealist attitude makes an attack on society its very raison
d'être, the lifeblood of its tragic inspiration.
Such a book, for example, as Celine's
Journey to the End of the Night (Voyage au
Bout de la Nuit), belongs very much to
the class
of defeatist literature, a class which has proliferated, this century,
with the
spread of megalopolitan civilization, and
which can
be traced, in varying forms, to the works of authors like Kafka,
Beckett, and Ionesco.
The
predominating tone of such literature
seems to imply a disgust with megalopolitan
society,
a world-weariness, a fatalistic feeling of "What's the use?", coupled
to an almost apocalyptic pessimism concerning the future course of
world events
and man's helplessness in the face of the mechanistic hell he has
unleashed
upon himself. Indeed, there is more than
a hint of this tone in various of the writings of Henry Miller, T.S.
Eliot, and
J.K. Huysmans too, although not to the
extent that
one generally finds it in the aforementioned authors.
But if disgust with and
despair at a society best characterize the defeatist decadents, then it
is
above all in their contempt for and indifference towards a society that
we find
what could be called the rebellious decadents most characterized, and
nowhere
more tellingly so than in George Orwell's Keep
the
Aspidistra Flying,
whose mock-hero, Gordon Comstock, turns his back on the
money-worshipping
commercial society of his day to pursue a career, doomed from the
outset, of
lyric poet on a meagre salary secured by his humble position as
book-shop
assistant. The rebellious young Comstock
is fundamentally a late-romantic in a society which has long ceased to
have any
romantic pretensions, to produce, understand, or revere great poets,
and, as
such, his career goes from bad to worse, losing him one job after
another,
until, reduced to the meanest of book shops, he is finally brought to
his
senses by the love of a young woman he has made pregnant and whom, as a
last
resort, he decides to marry. The
materialistic society from which he had tried to flee may not have been
conducive to the fostering of his romantic ambitions as a poet, but it
was
still capable of exhibiting the redeeming power of womanly love, that
eternal
theme of the generations, and so, thanks in part to the generosity of
his
previous employer, our mock-hero returns to the money-dominated world
of
advertising he had earlier rejected. A
moral here there may well be, but, realist that he was, Orwell also had
a
strong streak of the genuine romantic about him, and this is certainly
apparent
when we consider his horrified reaction, voiced in the essay Inside
the
Whale, to the social passivity, resignation, and seeming
indifference of
Henry Miller with regard, for example, to the existence of
concentration camps,
purges, putsches, totalitarian regimes, weapons of mass destruction,
etc.,
which he was unable to accept or face with the same apparent
complacency. But nowhere is this romantic
streak more
evident than in his practical opposition to Franco which, to the utter
bewilderment of Miller, led him to venture out in the name of
democracy, to do
battle with what he would have considered to be an authoritarian ogre.
There are, of course,
other examples of rebellious antirealist decadence to be found in
Orwell, and
to some extent one also finds this tendency in authors like Hamsun
(Hunger),
and Hesse (Steppenwolf),
though with a very different emphasis in each case.
I think, for example, the plight of Harry
Haller in Steppenwolf becomes easier to understand once one
sees this
work in relation to what follows it, that is to say, once one sees the
contemporaneousness of its setting in relation, on the one hand, to the
past
'Culture' of Narziss and Goldmund
and in relation, on the other hand, to the envisaged future
'Civilization' of The Glass Bead Game, and thereby realizes
that, as a
man caught between two ages in a transitional period from, symbolically
speaking, the spirit to the body, Harry Haller had a lot to learn about
the
body and, as a consequence of the spirit's predominance in the recent
past of
the Western 'Culture' - not to mention, if one takes Haller for Hesse, in the history of his own deeply
religious family -
was neither particularly happy nor, despite his previous (failed)
marriage,
really conditioned to do so.
("Human life is reduced to real suffering, to hell, only when
two
ages, two cultures and religions overlap.
A man of the Classical age who had to live in medieval times
would
suffocate miserably just as a savage does in the midst of our
civilization. Now there are times when a
whole generation is caught in this way between two ages, between two
modes of
life and thus loses the feeling for itself,
for the
self-evident, for all morals, for being safe and innocent." - Here, in
his
preface to Steppenwolf lies the key to what follows.) I think the fact that the body, symbolized by
the world, finally 'wins out', thanks in large measure to the
assistance of Hermine, Maria, Pablo, et
al., should be seen as a pointer
towards The Glass Bead Game where, in strict accordance with
the
prevalence of an advanced 'Civilization', Joseph Knecht
ultimately resigns from his post as 'Magister
Ludi', thereby signifying the triumph of
the body over the
spirit. For the cause of Haller's
dilemma centres, it seems to me, on the battle between 'Culture-man'
and
'Civilization-man', and, in accordance with the historical change
destined for
the Western soul, the latter was ultimately fated to gain the
ascendancy.
Hesse
is unquestionably one of the Western world's greatest authors and, for
no small
reason, one of the most maligned and misunderstood.
I do not think he is likely to be seen in his
true stature by anyone not well acquainted with the works of Spengler and Jung.
For the literary surface of
The meaning of satire
is, I think, sufficiently appreciated by a majority of people not to
warrant
any additional explanation here, and very few of us would be ignorant
of the
satirical qualities to be encountered in authors like Swift and Pope,
where the
vices and follies of various persons are held up to ridicule in the
clearest of
critical lights. However, it is worth
reminding ourselves that satire is a relatively rare product of the
creative
imagination, demanding from its exponent a degree of intellectual
sophistication of sufficient magnitude to carry weight in an area where
attacks
on society or individuals can all-too-easily degenerate into or remain
mere
attacks, without the power to convince one of their moral legitimacy. Thus the great satirist is ever a first-rate
critic, but a critic whose criticism could never be confounded with
malice for
the sake of malice, or vengefulness as a consequence of former hurts,
or
prejudice against particular people, or propaganda in the interests of
personal
belief, political allegiance, etc. The
essential thing is that we should come to understand and appreciate the
fundamental logic underlining a satirist's criticisms.
For true satire has nothing to do with that
kind of writing, so easily mistaken for it, which merely acquaints one
with the
personal prejudices, grudges, revolutionary ambitions, or whatever, of
its
author. Works in that
category are almost invariably in the guise of either defeatist or
rebellious
decadence, both of which we briefly investigated above.
I think one of the best
examples of genuine satirical writing can be found in Strindberg's The
Red
Room, a novel published in 1879 which virtually lampoons everything
from the
civil service to brotherly love, from art criticism to publishing, from
journalism to politics, and from Stockholm society to acting. Indeed, there seems to be little that doesn't
fall for a scathing criticism of one sort or another in this daring
novel, which
must surely rank as one of the greatest satires ever written, and
certainly one
of the finest creative achievements of a man whose imaginative genius
was
virtually unparalleled in the entire history of nineteenth-century
literature.
Another fine example of
modern satire is Wyndham Lewis' The
Roaring
Queen, the
publication of which, scheduled to take place sometime in the
'thirties, was
held-up for a number of years on account of the 'libellous nature' of
its
criticism of Arnold Bennett who, in the 'infamous' role of Shodbutt,
is made the chief representative of a species of literary dictatorship
which
Lewis, seemingly, was unable to stomach.
Other works by this outstanding satirist of modern times,
including Tarr (which Ezra Pound
considered a masterpiece), are
also worth noting in the context of negative antirealism, the decadent
antithesis, you will recall, to what we earlier described as 'plebeian'
classical realism.
We have discovered,
then, a perspective relating to the various modes of literary activity
which
enables us to differentiate between the two kinds of literature, viz.
the
classic and the decadent, and, further, to divide them into two forms,
viz. the
naturalist and the realist, which we in turn subdivided, on the one
hand, into
profane and religious, and, on the other hand, into 'noble' and
'plebeian'
types, providing, in each case, the appropriate decadent antithesis. We also discovered that each literary form,
whether in terms of the classic or the decadent, could be divided into
a positive
and a negative approach. Thus we agreed
that the type of classical naturalism which dealt with the love of
natural
phenomena on a religious plane, as pantheism or elementalism,
was
positive
in relation to the purely profane or secular appreciation of
nature encountered in its classical counterpart. Likewise
we
discovered that the decadent
antithesis to each classical form could also be divided into a positive
and a
negative approach. And so we agreed that
the type of anti-natural decadence which dealt with a hatred of natural
phenomena was negative in relation to supernaturalism, its decadent
counterpart, which took a distinctly positive stand in the
investigation of or
belief in worlds apparently existing beyond the boundaries of the
everyday one. With these particular
divisions and
subdivisions at our disposal, we were able to classify various authors
in terms
of what we took to be their leading creative tendencies.
But in so doing, we were obliged to accept
the fact that, in a majority of cases, such classifications could only
serve as
loose guidelines, as rough approximations to an author's main creative
approach
rather than as immutable criteria by which to place him in a definitive
category. To be sure, we found that
certain authors, such as Camus and Tolkien, could be classified more easily in this
manner
than others, like, for example, Huysmans
and Hesse (whose works were divisible into
two or more
categories), and although we satisfied ourselves that these others have
been
classified in the most suitable way within the confines of a given
form, we are
not beyond acknowledging the fact that contrary approaches to
literature can
also be encountered in various of their writings, albeit to a much
lesser
extent.
Finally, it is important
for us to remember that, thus far, our categorizations have been based
solely
on thematic material within the sphere of literature, not on syntax,
vocabulary, formal structure, etc. Thus
we have confined ourselves to the essence of literature.
Also, except in passing, we have not presumed
to touch upon the relative classic/decadent dichotomy in art, music,
architecture, or sculpture, which, were we competent to deal with such
subjects
in a similar way, would necessitate a considerable extension to the
current essay! In this context it must
suffice us to realize
that a dichotomy between the two main creative norms does indeed exist
within
all of the other arts, though, needless to say, not in exactly the same
way as
with literature. Similarly, it must
suffice us to realize that a parallel division can be found in
philosophy
between the, as it were, classical philosophy of the philosopher whose
work
directly relates to life and can in some way affect the life of its
time in a
positive manner and, conversely, the decadent philosophy of the
philosopher
whose work exists in a kind of ivory tower of thought-for-thought's
sake,
without any real or positive applicability to the life of its time.
But let us now briefly
turn our attention to the question of vocabulary, syntax, phraseology,
etc., in
literature, so as to differentiate between the classic and the decadent
approaches to style. You will recall
that I cited
I think this fact is
made amply clear when we contrast the predominantly classic prose of a
novel
like Madame
Bovary with the predominantly decadent
prose of Against the Grain, the extremely well-chosen,
expansive,
tortured and tortuous vocabulary, complex syntax, methodical
phraseology, and
unusual, not to say unique, formal structure of which signify the
veritable
apotheosis of the decadent style. It
appears, from a general survey of decadent literature, that the chief
hallmarks
of its style can usually be found in the use of rhetorical effusions,
highly
technical expressions, exotic references, carefully-selected adjectives
and
adverbs, esoteric foreign words-and-phrases, elongated sentences, and a
structure which has been subordinated to the interests of the parts;
whilst a
similar scrutiny of classic literature will indicate, by contrast, that
the
chief hallmarks of its style are usually to be found in the use
of
short, simple sentences, exact rather than hyperbolic utterances,
relatively
simple adjectives and adverbs, parts that are subordinated to the
interests of
the overall structure, an appropriately formal or conventional syntax -
in
short, by the use of moderate as opposed to extreme techniques. One might contend, furthermore, that the
authors of a classical subject-matter tend to employ a classic
technique, those
of a decadent subject-matter a decadent technique, though this is by no
means
invariably the case, as can be seen, for example, by the predominance
of
decadent prose in James Joyce's Ulysses, which, thematically
considered,
is essentially a classic work, and, conversely, by the mainly classic
prose of J.R.R.Tolkien's The Lord of
the Rings, which
fundamentally belongs to the realm of the decadent.
However, whatever the
technique and subject-matter of any given work may happen to be, there
inevitably arises a serious question relating to the comparative merits
of the
two kinds of literature: the question, namely, as to whether the
classic and
the decadent are of equal importance or whether, artistically speaking,
the
former is superior to the latter?
Havelock Ellis was of the opinion that they were of equal value
in the
stream of Western literature, but I incline to the view that the
classic is
generally artistically superior to the decadent. There
are,
I fully admit, examples of decadent
literature which, like The
Lord
of the Rings and The Glass Bead
Game tower above many shorter and lesser classic works.
But, on the whole, it seems to me that the
subject-matter and technical treatment of classic literature must
inevitably
grant it precedence over the corresponding attributes of the decadent. Naturally, one's taste or temperament may
predispose one to prefer the decadent, even to loathe the classic. But I do not seriously believe that it would
entitle one to consider the decadent of equal artistic value to that
which, by dint
of its intrinsic proportion, beauty, wholesomeness, pertinence, and
relative positivity, must always remain
the perfect art!
MUSIC
IN
THE WESTERN WORLD
Music
may
be continuously changing from generation to generation,
but it doesn't necessarily change for the better. There
would
no more seem to be a
straightforward progression in music than in any of the other arts. What one may hear in the context of
twentieth-century composition does not, as a rule, signify a
progressive
refinement upon the music of earlier centuries.
On the contrary, it signifies the inevitability of change, the
overwhelming concern of modern composers to compose differently from
their
predecessors. The essential
qualification for a modern composer is that he should produce
compositions of a
different nature from those of Bach, Mozart, Beethoven, et al. The originality of his approach to music
should, in large measure, justify his claim to compositional
authenticity.
Some people, including
several contemporary composers, have maintained that the sense of
beauty
changes from age to age, so that what was regarded as beautiful by the
people
of one age may appear as anything but beautiful to those of another. The conclusion one should draw from this is
obviously one that will justify the often cacophonous sounds of
contemporary
composers in terms of a different sense of beauty among the moderns! Yet beauty isn't something that is one thing
now and a completely different thing later, in some other age. Beauty is the same in any age which has
anything approximating to a serious culture.
A beautiful face will remain distinctly beautiful for specific
reasons,
including form and texture, whether it belongs to a person living in
the
seventeenth century or to one living today.
The capacity to achieve and judge the Beautiful may of course
vary from
age to age, but beauty will remain a constant nonetheless.
Like any other fine art,
music is capable of attaining to great beauty, of arousing one's
aesthetic
admiration through the fact that sounds have been organized in the best
possible way or, failing that, in an indisputably ingenious way. There is a maximum aesthetic height to which
music can aspire, a maximum potential of well-ordered sound, which
lends it the
distinction commonly known as great music.
But great music, like great beauty, isn't something that is one
thing
now and another and completely different thing later.
Great music is great for all time, because it
signifies the best possible combination of sounds.
The only real alternative to such music is
poor music, i.e. music that is petty, bogus, ugly, and insignificant -
call it
what you like. The greatest music will
be that which signifies the Beautiful most commandingly.
The worst music, by contrast, will fail even
to approach the Beautiful. Its composers
will scorn the criteria of the Beautiful as being arbitrary,
contingent, transient, subject to whim.
Instead, they will apply other criteria, which they'll consider
to be
more tenable than traditional criteria, and, ipso
facto, people will
be expected to believe that the age has acquired a different sense of
beauty. Music will have 'progressed' to
new concerns, and aesthetic ingredients formerly considered sacrosanct
will be
systematically discarded in the interests of continuous experimentation. A musical idea that is broken off before it
can become a phrase will be deemed representative of the new beauty,
and the
polished phrases of Haydn, Mozart, and other such classical composers
duly held
up, by liberal academics and radical composers alike, as choice
examples of
historic beauty: an approach to beauty strictly appertaining to the
aesthetic
criteria of a former age.
I have stated that there
is a maximum aesthetic height to which music can aspire, a height
commensurate
with the most commanding representation of the Beautiful.
It is now necessary for me to define beauty
in terms of specific aesthetic criteria, the most obvious of which
being the
best possible organization of melodic sound.
Fundamentally music is melody, an arrangement of sounds
according to
pitch and rhythm, the one presupposing the other. You
do
not make music when you tap a finger
on the table to a given rhythm, and you mostly make only a very
uninspiring
type of music from notes (variations in pitch) which are all the same
duration. Clearly, to get the most
satisfactory results it is necessary to combine pitch and rhythm in the
best
possible way. For
although pitch usually takes priority over rhythm, it cannot achieve
anything
really notable without some form of rhythmic assistance. Thus the finest music will inevitably contain
the most enjoyable melodies, and it will flout these melodies with all
the
assurance of their intrinsic beauty, or proportion.
In the hierarchy of compositions, the more
ingenious melodies will take precedence over the less ingenious ones,
the more
aesthetically-satisfying melodies over the less
aesthetically-satisfying ones,
and so on.
But melody by itself,
even when beautiful, does not make for great music.
It requires the support of harmony, the
enrichment of its line by combinations of notes which both define and
embellish
its modality, adding flesh, so to speak, to the notational skeleton. The very word 'harmony' presupposes something
congruous, a combination of notes which complement one another. Discords do not form a harmony, and the
phrase 'discordant harmony' would be a contradiction in terms. If the notes combined are not concordant,
they can only be discordant, and the resulting effect on the eardrums
will be
suggestive of cacophony - the opposite of harmony.
Thus great music will
require a primary ingredient and a secondary one: the most satisfying
melody
supported, though never dominated, by the most appropriate harmony. And with this indispensable combination of
musical ingredients there will, of necessity, arise considerations of
logical
or congruous form, to be followed, in the hierarchy of compositional
ingredients, by considerations of tone and touch, modulation within a
logical framework,
tasteful instrumentation, carefully-balanced sound, subordinate
virtuoso
passages, etc., which form the icing on the cake, as it were, of great
music. However, there will never be more
icing than cake in such music, and, consequently, virtuoso passages
will always
be subordinate to the leading melodic ideas.
A composition where this is not the case can never make for the
finest
music, just as Paganini and Liszt, for all
their
instrumental brilliance, don't make for the finest composers.
Likewise, a composition
which takes little or no account of the natural hierarchy of musical
instruments but, for the sake of novelty or experimentation, gives its
leading
melodic ideas to lesser instruments ... will never make for the finest
music,
either. Strictly speaking, the violins
take precedence over the violas, the violas over the cellos, and the
cellos
over the double basses in all great music centred in or employing
strings. Now this same hierarchy, based on
pitch and
tone, applies equally well to the woodwind and brass sections of an
orchestra,
where flutes and trumpets, respectively, take the leading roles.
But there is, in
addition to these separate hierarchies of individual instrument
families, an
overall hierarchy which is even more important in the logic of great
orchestration, and which descends from the strings to the woodwind, and
then
from the woodwind to the brass, with other instruments, such as
timpani, harp,
celesta, etc., positioned at the base of the instrumental edifice. Of course, I do not mean to imply by this
that strings are technically superior, per
se, to woodwind, or woodwind
technically superior, per se, to brass, but, rather,
that the
higher strings (violin, viola) are technically superior to the higher
woodwind (flute,
oboe), the higher woodwind technically superior to the lower strings
(cello,
double bass), the higher brass (trumpet, horn) technically superior to
the
lower woodwind (clarinet, bassoon), etc., so that considerations of
pitch and
tone also cut across the three main instrument families, thus making
the final
choice of instrumentation a very difficult yet still definite art.
Now, in addition to the
final choice of instrumentation, a decision must arise concerning the
total
number of instruments to be employed, the greatest music almost
invariably
making use of a specific number of the best instruments, and no more! For just as 'too many
cooks
spoil the broth', so, in orchestral terms, do too many instruments
spoil the
music, and nothing genuinely first-rate can be expected from them. But, as I hinted above, it isn't enough that
orchestras should be of the right size; they must also contain the
right
instruments and the best possible combination of them, if first-rate
results
are to be achieved.
We therefore have before
us certain indispensable criteria for determining the general nature of
great
music, criteria which cannot be set aside without producing or
resulting in
degenerate compositions. The most
beautiful
or ingenious melodies, to briefly recapitulate, should be supported by
the most
appropriate harmonies, the combination thereby established being
accorded a
logically satisfying form, and the form itself, which is essentially a
product
of the artful linking-up of diverse melodies, duly being articulated
with the
best possible combination and number of musical instruments. If this is not achieved, then there is scant
possibility of truly great music being produced!
It stands to reason,
however, that in addition to a hierarchy of instruments, there must
also be a
hierarchy of compositional forms, a hierarchy starting with
compositions for
single instruments and extending up the scale of chamber and concerto
music to
the noblest and grandest form of them all - the classical symphony. Beyond the symphony at its greatest there is
nothing higher, nothing which evokes a stronger challenge than the
artful
combination of numerous instruments, and so it is inevitably in the
realm of
symphonic composition that one will find the greatest music. The concerto, particularly for piano, will
come next in line, and behind this will follow large-scale instrumental
compositions, opera, ballet, chamber music, piano sonatas, sonatas in
general,
miscellaneous piano compositions, songs, etc.
Naturally, this hierarchy of compositional forms does not imply
that the
finest piano sonata, for example, is of necessity musically inferior to
the
weakest piano concerto, but that, generally speaking, the great sonata
will
stand lower in the scale of musical forms than the great concerto, even
if it
towers above the weakest concerto on account, for instance, of its
superior
melodies and harmonic accompaniments.
But even if, to extend our argument, there are great piano
concertos
which are musically superior to various second-rate symphonies, it is
my firm
conviction that no piano concerto, no matter how great, can be
considered
musically superior to a really first-rate symphony - the crowning glory
of all
serious music.
I do not know how many
of my readers are familiar with Spengler's
The
Decline
of
the West, or indeed with any of his other major works.
But I will say, for the benefit of those who
are, that I wholeheartedly subscribe to the veracity of his thesis
concerning
Western decadence, and am in complete accord with his contention that
Western
music has been steadily on the decline since approximately the end of
the
eighteenth century. In the transition,
defined by Spengler, from 'Culture' to
'Civilization'
of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, there set in a systematic
attack
within music, as within most other things, on the preordained cultural
forms. Instead of signifying a
continuous expansion on the forms brought to perfection in the
classicism of
Mozart, musical composition has increasingly signified a disruption of
them, a
gradual reversal of that which grew to perfection in the prime of 'the
Culture'
and could not be improved upon.
Thus a majority of
serious compositions in the nineteenth and, more especially, twentieth
centuries signify an aesthetic regression rather than a straightforward
cultural progression, an aesthetic regression paralleling that from
Christianity to liberalism, and thus from beauty and love to ugliness
and
hatred. It is, above all, in the music
of Vivaldi, Corelli,
Scarlatti,
Couperin, Rameau, Purcell, Telemann, Handel, Bach, Haydn, Mozart, and the
early
Beethoven that we hear the progressive growth of Western civilization. But already in the late Beethoven, in
Schubert, Schumann, Mendelssohn, Berlioz, and Chopin, the seeds of
revolution
which were sown towards the end of the eighteenth century are beginning
to
sprout in the form of romanticism, to be cultivated to a much greater
extent by
Wagner, Liszt, Bruckner, Brahms,
Saint-Saëns, Massenet, Franck,
Tchaikovsky, Dvorák,
et al., in the latter-half of the 19th century.
It is in romanticism, which (to use a Spenglerian
phrase) is essentially 'musical socialism', that we find the voice of
'the
Civilization' beginning to assert itself over the classically-inspired
'Culture' from which it sprang, and with increasing boldness from
decade to
decade. For socialism, as outlined by Spengler in The
Hour
of Decision, is
fundamentally nothing less than the systematic destruction of Western
civilization by means of a gradual undermining of its slowly-evolved
traditions, a destruction as apparent in the class struggle and the
resultant
growth of the Labour Movement, as in the anti-Christian polemics of any
rationalist philosopher; as apparent in the rise of feminism and the
resultant
demand for equal opportunity (as a springboard to female dominance for
a
creature rooted, inflexibly, in a XX-chromosomal genetic integrity), as
in the
cacophonous music of the avant-garde. It
is a fact of contemporary life, not something to be condemned as though
it
shouldn't have happened but, on the contrary, understood in the context
of the
transition from 'Culture' to 'Civilization' through which Western
society is
passing and out of which it should emerge, if total chaos is to be
avoided, in
a new and anti-socialist guise. At
bottom we are all socialist in certain respects, even if only to the
extent of
despising Christianity or admiring the music of Liszt, when socialism
is thus
comprehended as the process of undermining everything that was
systematically
evolved and considered sacrosanct in and by 'the Culture'.
But this process, I shall argue, was
inescapable, a phenomenon to be encountered in various guises in the
corresponding epochs of former civilizations, and not a contingent
anomaly
peculiar to Western Europe alone.
Thus it transpires that
the growth of romanticism - which, despite changes in terminology, has
continued virtually unabated since the early decades of the nineteenth
century
- is not something to be foolishly condemned in a spirit of philistine
ignorance, but, on the contrary, accepted as an historical
inevitability, and
its chief exponents perceived as victims of time's dictatorship. If classical music, brought to perfection by
Mozart, signifies the musical Right, to adopt a political analogue,
then the
Romantic Movement inaugurated by Beethoven very definitely signifies
the
musical Left, or the gradual undermining of classical criteria in terms
of a
development which was aesthetically regressive, as from poetry to prose. Of course, there are classical elements to be
found in all romantic composers and, conversely, romantic elements in
even the
most classical ones, Mozart not excepted. But such elements very rarely play the
leading role, particularly in the music of late-nineteenth-century and
early-twentieth-century composers, where the distance between 'the
Culture' and
'the Civilization' is greater than it was for either the late
classicists or
the early romantics.
It should be evident
from the foregoing remarks that serious music began to decline from an
all-time
high of classical perfection throughout the nineteenth century. The criteria of musical greatness, stemming
from the brilliance of melody writing and extending, via a variety of
channels,
to the manipulation of the best possible instrumental combinations,
were being
increasingly discarded in the interests of the romantic Weltanschauung.
Where, formerly, the parts of a given composition were strictly
subordinated to the interests of the whole and perfection of form was
considered
of consummate importance, the whole gradually gave way, as in political
socialism, to the interests of the parts, and form, if and when it
appeared,
duly acquired a much looser guise. Where
the sonata form, hitherto the basis of sonatas, concertos, and
symphonies
alike, was seen as a foundation and help by classical composers, the
Romantics
mostly regarded it as an imposition and hindrance, to be supplanted by
leitmotivs, idées
fixes,
and other such recurrent themes, which would enable them to explore the
passions and simultaneously extend the range of virtuoso playing to an unprecedentedly high level of instrumental
complexity. Likewise the growth of melodic
complexity
throughout the nineteenth century signalled an inversion of the
cultural
standards, and harmony, hitherto largely confined to a secondary and
subordinate role, increasingly began to
dictate the
direction music should take, in defiance of melodic sovereignty. And with the corruption of harmony as a
support for melody came the corruption of harmony as harmony,
and the
gradual incorporation of discordant and inharmonious elements into its
formerly
congruous structures - an exact musical parallel, it seems to me, with
the
phenomenon of feminism within the necessarily anti-Christian structure
of
liberal freedom.
But if melody, formerly
a relatively natural and straightforward ingredient of musical
perfection, and
harmony, its subordinate component, could be radically altered to suit
the
romantic Weltanschauung,
then
there
was very little to prevent composers from radically altering
everything
else as well, and to do so, moreover, under the illusion of continual
progress! Thus arose the use of extremes
in pitch, volume, and tone; the use of unprecedented combinations of
instruments; the ever-increasing size of orchestras; the important
roles played
by instruments which stood relatively low in the instrumental
hierarchy; the
greater attention to virtuoso playing; a preference for large-scale
works, and
other such radical alterations in composition which contributed, step
by step,
to the progressive degeneration of music from the classical zenith
attained to
by Mozart. For musical beauty, to
repeat, is ever a mean, a product of instruments which have been
combined in
the best possible way to produce the most satisfying aesthetic results,
and
whenever that mean is tampered with, be it to extend the range of pitch
to its
extreme depths or heights, or to utilize greater extremities of tone
and volume
than ever before, or to score parts for combinations of instruments
which
appeal to the sense of novelty rather than to a profound aesthetic
charm, the
only possible consequence is a disruption of the delicate balance of
harmonious
relations which make for beauty and their replacement, to varying
extents, by
less-harmonious and less-balanced relations of sound that make for
ugliness.
Thus we find that,
throughout the nineteenth century, musical ugliness is slowly and
painfully
gaining the ascendancy over musical beauty, an inevitability of the
times
largely brought about by the impossibility of improving upon earlier
composers,
who had set definitive standards of musical greatness.
Here, if anywhere, is evidence of the fact,
acknowledged by Arthur Koestler in his
retrospective
book Janus
- A Summing Up,
that the various fine arts don't necessarily progress in
a
straight line of increased perfection or greatness from generation to
generation, but are largely conditioned by the standards set by
precedence,
which may or may not allow for artistic improvement.
In the case of Western music from Beethoven
onwards there has, I repeat, been a steady decline, an aesthetic
regression
from the standards set in the eighteenth century, which could not be
improved
upon. Hence every romantic composer was,
to a greater or lesser extent, consciously or unconsciously, coerced
into
producing worse music than his immediate predecessors.
He was compelled not to respect his
predecessors' innovations, but either to extend them or dedicate himself to the formulation of other innovations
and thereby
produce his own music. But his own
music, unlike that of the great composers who had been engulfed by 'the
Culture', and therefore composed at its theocratic behest, was
predominantly a
matter of his own doing, an indication of the musical anarchy, born of
democratic freedom, which gradually turned composers from service of
'the
Culture' to service of themselves, in an effort to transcend the
standards set
by their predecessors and thus attain to musical originality.
One might say that where,
formerly, the macrocosm of 'the Culture' had governed the microcosm of
individual composers, this process was gradually reversed throughout
the
nineteenth century, and the microcosm of individual composers began to
act
increasingly like an autonomous whole in the vast stream of Western
music,
paying less and less heed to the macrocosm of 'the Culture' against
which it
had been forced to rebel in the interests of constant change, particles
superseding wavicles.
Naturally, it is fair to say that some composers were more
conservative
than others vis-à-vis the radical changes which stood for the onslaught
of 'the
Civilization' and its collective values.
Nevertheless, even they were irreversibly caught-up in the swift
current
of musical socialism that bore everything along in the direction of
greater
dissolution and anarchy. Even Brahms and
Bruckner indicate a more anarchic
turn-of-mind than
Mendelssohn and Schumann, their two outstanding predecessors, and these
latter
composers are certainly less conservative, in their turn, than either
Beethoven
or Schubert, and are veritable radicals when compared with Haydn and
Mozart! But if such classic-romantic
composers appear conservative or reactionary when compared with the
more
fervent musical socialists such as Berlioz, Liszt, Wagner, Chopin,
Franck, and Dvorák, they are still
significant contributors to the
continuous march of musical regress, a march which was to find an even
firmer
footing in the twentieth century, as free enterprise gained in momentum
to the
detriment of centralized patronage.
Thus far,
twentieth-century music is chiefly characterized by two disparate
tendencies:
the tendency, on the one hand, to further the rot of romanticism
initiated by
Beethoven, and the tendency, on the other hand, to stem the rot either
by
indulging in a form of neo-classicism or, alternatively, by subscribing
to the
incorporation of jazz elements. Let us
examine the first tendency first.
The attack on 'the
Culture's' leading representatives is much fiercer in the twentieth
century
than at the time of Brahms, Saint-Saëns, Massenet,
and
Bruckner.
By comparison with Mahler (the first really powerful voice of
the
twentieth century), Stravinsky, Bartók,
Prokofiev,
Ives, Schoenberg, Webern, Berg, Varèse,
Sibelius, et al., the music of even the
most radical
late-nineteenth-century composers seems beautiful or conservative or
classical,
depending on your viewpoint. The
discords used by composers of the previous century seem tame and
sparing when
compared with their more radical use by the representatives of 'the
Civilization' in the first-half of the twentieth century.
And the melodies, whether complex, elongated,
or fragmented, of those same late-romantic composers likewise appear
beautiful
when compared with the greater complexity, elongation, and
fragmentation of
melodies composed during the early decades of the twentieth century. In virtually all aspects of musical
composition, late-romantic works have been made to seem conservative,
and the
ongoing aesthetic degeneration of serious music has more than kept
abreast of
the stupendous technological advancements being witnessed by modern man. (It hardly needs emphasizing that while the
capacity to progress has been inhibited in certain contexts, it has by
no means
been inhibited everywhere, so that the continuous improvements on the
design,
for example, of the automobile is achieved at the cost of the
continuing
regression of music from a maximum beauty towards a maximum ugliness. The technological advances of this century
are generally paralleled by its cultural retreats.)
Not only have orchestras become even bigger,
viz. Mahler, Strauss, Holst, et al., but
the
traditional combination and balance of instruments has been still more
radically altered, and, with this, the parts played by the various
instruments. Even the, by classical
standards, excessive importance attached to the double-bass parts by
Brahms,
whose father was a bassist, is moderate when compared with certain more
recent
scores, where the bass parts, besides having extra work to do, are
further
strengthened by the incorporation of additional bases!
And, similarly, the brass sections, which
many musicologists would claim to have been used excessively by Franck,
Bruckner and Saint-Saëns, have undergone a
transformation
of importance and acquired a stridency of effect that could only have
horrified
any late nineteenth-century composer.
However, just as there
were relatively conservative composers and even relatively conservative
compositions occasionally being written, in the nineteenth century, by
composers who were anything but conservative, so there were
like-composers and
tendencies at work in the first-half of the twentieth century, and for
similar
reasons. Considering that England had
been musically rather quiet for at least two centuries, it isn't
altogether
surprising that some of the most conservative neo-classical tendencies
should
have come from there, and nowhere more notably so than in the guise of Elgar, many of whose works, including the
immensely popular
Enigma
Variations and the Cello Concerto,
belong spiritually to the late-nineteenth century and not to the steady
upsurge
of atonal cacophony which was destined to dominate serious composition
throughout the subsequent decades. But
if the Catholic Elgar may be considered
less
musically socialist than a majority of his contemporaries, he was still
compelled to pay court to the twentieth century and be carried along,
willy-nilly, in the direction of greater aesthetic dissolution. In
In the case, for
example, of Ravel, who, for all his innovations, was fundamentally more
conservative
than his two great compatriots, the dissolution into the cacophony of
large
orchestras that was fast befalling many contemporary composers was
partly
avoided by a concentration on lighter music and the concomitant use of
smaller
ensembles, the music occasionally veering in the direction of Jazz, a
direction
which Satie was also to take in a number
of
compositions, most notably his Ragtime
Parade. However, in Debussy's case the
introduction
of the whole-note pentatonic scale lent his music a more radical bias
than that
of his musical contemporaries, and the impressionistic haze of sound
that
resulted from this should be seen as a greater concession to the
romantic
debunking attitude underlining modern developments than can be found in
either
Ravel or Satie, romantic though much of
their music
undoubtedly was! But even in Satie, who regularly endeavoured to simplify his
music to
the utmost possible extent, the romantic attitude of debunking the
classical
norm was not without its radical overtones, as we discover in his
predilection
for jazz rhythms, strange harmonic and enharmonic juxtapositions, odd
combinations of instruments, and unprecedented tonal effects. The overwhelming distinction between Bach's
legendary Prelude and Fugue in D Minor and Satie's Ragtime Parade looms
gigantic
over
Western music, though the only real alternative to this is not to
be found
in Elgar's Enigma Variations, nor
even
Prokofiev's 3rd Piano Concerto, but in Stravinsky's Rite
of Spring. For the continuing expansion
of romanticism
into still greater melodic and rhythmic complexities has inexorably led
to the
cacophonous triumphing over both neo-classical and romantic-jazz
composers
alike, with an inevitable consequence that modern composition has
brought music
the furthest remove from the classical height attained to by Mozart and
plunged
it deeper and deeper into the overriding decadence of 'the
Civilization'.
Whether or not music can
become even more degenerate, even more anarchic, with the passing of
time is
something that remains to be seen or, rather, heard; although it does
seem
unlikely, at present, that it will either come to a complete standstill
or
retrace its steps. If the world is not
destroyed in a nuclear apocalypse, then there is a fair chance that the
leading
composers of contemporary Western civilization will appear relatively
conservative to the ears of a future generation, whose foremost
composers may
have regressed beyond mathematical and electronic investigations of
sound to
some completely unforeseen investigation that will take music a still
further
remove from the aesthetic 'gold standard', from which it was initially
plucked
in the early decades of the nineteenth century, and drive it deeper and
deeper
into musical anarchy.
I stated at the
beginning of this essay that beauty is a constant quality, not
something that
changes from age to age. It requires a
certain number of components to be arranged in a certain order, too
many or too
few inevitably disturbing the overall balance and, depending how they
are
arranged, making for a less beautiful or even an ugly effect. Thus beauty is ever the product of a golden
mean between components and the way they are arranged, a golden mean
ultimately
dependent upon the taste and discretion of its creator, the composer. For if its creator lacks a capacity to
appreciate and formulate a high standard of the Beautiful, then
nothing but a second- or third-rate composition can be expected from
him. Great works require great men, not
mediocre
men who are willing to work hard. And
great works can only be created during a limited period of time, while
the
possibility of progressive development prevails, not after both the
best
materials and the best means of exploiting them have been exhausted. Once a given soil has been properly
cultivated, it is necessary to move on to the cultivation of another
soil, even
if it be less good and can only supply a limited number of rather
seedy-looking
crops in consequence. As in agriculture,
so in music!
This, I think, is
sufficient to explain the revolutionary changes which Western music has
recently undergone, and to point out the reluctance in some people's
minds to
admit to the constancy of beauty. For
they were born too late to witness the creation of real beauty, and can
only look
back with mixed feelings of envy and wonder at the quality of music
created
while 'the Culture' was in its prime. If
they are not to feel unduly sorry for themselves or to despise
themselves on
that account, they will make some effort, no matter how reluctantly,
towards
overrating the efforts of contemporary composers, even if this entails
the
deception of a shift in their sense of beauty!
But, deep down, there are few cultured people who would consider
the breaking
off of an uninspiring musical phrase in mid-flight superior to the
completed,
not to say inspiring, phrase of earlier composers.
Or the use of random atonal
'harmonies' superior to the use of carefully-calculated tonal harmonies. Or the reiteration of
banal
rhythms without apparent melodic development superior to the beautiful
melody
whose rhythmic content follows naturally and inevitably. For it is, above all, to the sense of novelty
that so many of these modern developments appeal, supported, as they
usually
are, by the democratically fashionable, though fundamentally
superficial,
notion that art primarily exists to wake one up to new creative
possibilities,
instead of, as traditionally, to arouse one's admiration through the
strength
of its aesthetic charm. But when the
aesthetic charm is lacking because it can no longer be attained, it is
easy to
see why such a notion becomes so important in the realm of art dogma,
and why
so many people are gradually brainwashed into believing it! After all, it was only with the twentieth
century that notions of that order became necessary, and it was
possible for
various artists to formulate eccentric theories relating to the nature
of
beauty and ugliness.
In one such theory, it
was alleged that art made from ugly materials and focusing on ugly
subjects
could be just as good, i.e. artistically meritorious, as art made from
beautiful materials and focusing on beautiful subjects - quite as
though beauty
and ugliness were equal qualities and not subject to the value
differentials
which accrue to all antitheses, where the positive component of the
duality,
viz. beauty, is qualitatively superior to its negative component, viz.
ugliness! In this instance, the
value-differential focuses on the pleasant effects created by the
Beautiful
and, by contrast, on the unpleasant effects created by the Ugly. The face of a beautiful woman will arouse a
very superior emotional response in most men to the face of an ugly
one, to a
woman who, instead of being admired for the pleasure she brings, will
be
despised for creating a disagreeable and even painful effect. Now, by a similar token, the spectacle of a
painting which depicts a dirty backyard, where dustbins are crammed to
overflowing with rubbish, will engender, if not an outright
disagreeable
emotional response in the viewer's mind, then certainly a less
agreeable
response than that engendered by the spectacle of a painting which
depicts a
beautiful sunset over an aesthetically-satisfying landscape. Clearly, the latter painting would be
qualitatively superior to the former both on account of the subject it
employs
and the response it evokes. The only
instance in which an ugly painting might
be
considered artistically or, at any rate, creatively superior to a
beautiful one
... would be if the latter was much smaller and thereby testified to
less
effort, on the part of its creator, than the former.
Then it might be possible for one to judge
the respective creative values of the two paintings chiefly on the
strength of
the amount of work and skill apparent there, even if the ugly one - a
canvas,
say, depicting overturned dustbins infested by rats - evoked an
inferior
emotional response to the beautiful miniature.
And the same, I venture to guess, could be held true of musical
compositions
with a similar compositional differential.
But in two works of identical size and length, wherein an
approximately
equal amount of work had been put into each, and where one testified to
a
preoccupation with ugly materials or subjects while the other, by
contrast,
bore testimony to a preoccupation with beautiful materials or subjects,
it is
only logically possible to conclude the latter artistically superior to
the
former, since beauty is ever qualitatively superior to ugliness.
Yet in an age which, to
a significant extent, has been deprived of the creation of beautiful
work
because virtually all of the possibilities relating to it have already
been
exploited, it is virtually inevitable that a kind of Nietzschean
"revaluation of all values" should also manifest itself in art
theories, and that the leading artists of the day should do their best
to
elevate the few scraps of creative possibility left them to an absurdly
pretentious level! If the art propaganda
initiated by progressive artists has had the desired effect in the
service of
their free enterprise, i.e. has been generally accepted by the
so-called
culture-loving public, then it should be possible for people to
conclude the
works of Bacon equal in value to those of Rembrandt, or the works of
Stockhausen equal in value to those of Mozart, and perhaps even
superior to
them, depending on the culture-loving public's readiness to accept new
criteria
without criticism (its being generally understood that professional
artists and
critics know best, and that lay criticism of the new topsy-turvy
doctrines is
therefore apt to be superficial!)
Thus when modern arts
propaganda is successful, the progressive degeneration of the
Arts is
seen as progress, and the concept of art as novelty, or something that
wakes
one up to new creative possibilities, becomes the overriding concern of
a
majority of artists, who, by classical standards, are really
anti-artists with
the sole intention, consciously or unconsciously, of furthering the rot
that
set-in with 'the Civilization' at the beginning of the nineteenth
century, and
who will doubtless continue to wage war on everything 'the Culture'
evolved
until such time as they are unable to regress any further and a new age
begins
to dawn on the Western world. It was not
Henry Miller who initially took literature off the 'gold standard', and
it is
not Miller who has taken it the furthest remove from there. A comprehensive history of Western literature
and anti-literature, art and anti-art, sculpture and anti-sculpture,
music and
anti-music, has still to be written. It
will doubtless be done by men of a future epoch or civilization!
But let us return to the
present and, more specifically, to the subject of music, which is the
branch of
the Arts we are most concerned with here.
Simultaneously with the continuous decline of Western music this
century, another music began to arise, not an African or an American
phenomenon
but a phenomenon of the black man in North America - in short, the
music of the
American Negro. It arose out of the
Civil War, when the newly-emancipated Negro was obliged, in a large
number of
cases, to consider an alternative means of earning a living and, if he
had
musical predilections, began to acquire and learn how to play whichever
musical
instrument most took his fancy or, more probably, came most readily to
hand. It developed quite steadily
throughout the remaining years of the nineteenth century and, shortly
after the
turn-of-the-century, it split into two
distinct forms
- namely, the Blues of the solo performer and the Jazz of the group. Throughout the early decades of the twentieth
century Blues and Jazz continued to develop quite steadily, the one
emerging as
the music of the underprivileged Black, the other as the music of the
intellectual Black. Thus within a
relatively short space of time, from the end of the Civil War to the
beginning
of the Second World War, i.e. within three generations, the American
negro had
evolved his own equivalents of white popular and serious music, and had
succeeded, moreover, in making the impact of these forms felt
throughout the
greater part of the Western hemisphere.
Not only did blues and jazz elements find their way into white
serious
music - as, for example, Ravel, Satie,
Gershwin,
Copland, et al. - but Blues and Jazz began to acquire general
acceptance among
the white populations of the various Western countries as an
alternative or
supplement to their own musical forms and, no less importantly, one to
be
imitated by white musicians who were interested in spreading the
gospel, so to
speak, of black creativity.
Now, since the Second
World War, this revolution in music has conquered even the English and
German
nations, hitherto among the most conservative peoples in their attitude
towards
Negro music. However, it is also true to
say that, in the past fifty or so years, black music has itself
undergone a
profound revolution. For not only have
the blues and jazz structures been radically altered in accordance with
evolutionary demands, but Blacks have increasingly felt the impact of
the white
world upon themselves and modified their music accordingly. Thus one finds a situation arising whereby
Blacks and Whites play in the same band and create a type of fusion
music from
the combination of Rock (sophisticated pop, adulterated classical,
etc.) and
Jazz, or, broadly, white and black musical forms, whereas formerly, in
the
early decades of the twentieth century, segregation obliged black
musicians to
keep to themselves in the creation of their own specifically jazz music. But if the Blues, initially the music of the
underprivileged Black, has itself undergone a radical transformation in
recent
decades and re-emerged in the guises of Soul, Funk, Funk-Soul, etc.,
the music
of the average rather than necessarily underprivileged Black, then the
transformation
of Jazz into Modern Jazz and/or Fusion Music has been just as radical,
and the
intellectual and predominantly instrumental Black has continued, with
the aid
of Whites, to develop his own essentially serious music.
Hence, broadly speaking, Blues and Jazz have
been transformed into Soul and Modern Jazz - the black equivalents of
Pop and
Classical. We are primarily concerned,
in this essay, with serious music, so let us leave the black pop
equivalence
out of our investigations and take a more detailed look at Modern Jazz.
There are, in this
sphere of creativity, two distinct tendencies at large.
On the one hand, there is what could be
called the Dionysian tendency towards excess and, on the other hand,
the
Apollonian tendency towards refinement. In
varying degrees, this duality has always existed in serious music,
whether we
are dealing with a symphony by Beethoven or an extended improvisation
by
Charlie Parker. There are the loud and
the quiet passages, the quick and the slow, the heavy and the light,
the rough
and the smooth, the emotional and the intellectual, etc.
Every extended serious composition demands
this alternation between Dionysian and Apollonian elements, and even in
the
classicism of Mozart it is unthinkable that an entire symphony or
concerto
could be all quick or all slow, all loud or all quiet.
However, it is also possible for us to
generalize, where different types of music are concerned.
For although we are aware that classical
music-proper, viz. Haydn, Mozart, the early Beethoven, is not entirely
Apollonian, we should be entitled to consider it essentially such in
contrast
to romanticism, which, especially from the time of Liszt, we should
regard as
distinctly Dionysian. In fact, we should
have no hesitation in categorizing everything that stands in opposition
to 'the
Culture' in terms of the Dionysian, even though we are aware that
Apollonian
qualities may well be in evidence. As
regards Modern Jazz, however, the categorization or generalization
towards
which we are led is decidedly the Apollonian, inasmuch as, stemming
from a
non-European source, Modern Jazz doesn't signify an attack on 'the
Culture' so
much as a new voice which happens to find itself juxtaposed with the
down-dragging musical currents of contemporary Western civilization. Modern Jazz is not the music of 'Faustian'
man, irrespective of the number of 'Faustians'
(Westerners,
in
Spenglerian parlance) it may enrol in
its service, but the music of Afro-Americans, and, as such, it
signifies an
upward growth analogous to that of a new culture. It
has,
to be sure, certain Dionysian
elements within the overall framework of its structures which maintain,
as in
other musical forms, a balance with its Apollonian elements. But the equilibrium thereby established need
not prevent us from generalizing it into an Apollonian, upwards-growing
phenomenon which, willy-nilly, stands in stark opposition to the
down-dragging
Dionysian phenomenon of contemporary Western music!
I think this factor is
of crucial significance in explaining both the abrupt rise and the
immense
popularity of black music, whether popular or serious, within the
traditionally
white nations, a large number of whose inhabitants have been enabled to
take
refuge from the regressive musical trends of their civilization in the
shelter
provided by a relatively young, exuberant, and progressive subculture. In this context, the finest examples of
Modern Jazz could be thought superior, in musical terms, to the
compositions of
avant-garde composers, and would provide a spiritual crutch for the
jaded
sensibilities of Western man who, by compromising with the music of a
subculture not strictly compatible with 'the Culture' from which he
springs, is
enabled to acquire a modicum of defence against the Dionysian plague
which
threatens to completely engulf him and to deprive him, inevitably, of
even the
faintest intimation of genuine music.
But if the contention
implicit in the Apollonian/Dionysian confrontation of Modern Jazz with
the
avant-garde ... leads us to the conclusion that the former is musically
superior to the latter, we must nevertheless endeavour to provide
tangible
proofs which will lend credibility to such a conclusion.
For it must be acknowledged that even though
Modern Jazz pertains to a growing subculture, it is unlikely that it
has yet
grown to full maturity and thereupon fully realized its dormant
potential. The concept of Jazz as an art
form is of
comparatively recent origin, stemming, in the main, from Charlie
Parker, whose
breathtaking performances on the saxophone in the nineteen thirties and
'forties fairly revolutionized the then-existing position of Jazz in
the
Western world. Now, since him, many
other great musicians, including Bud Powell, John Coltrane, Miles
Davis, Oscar
Peterson, and McCoy Tyner have likewise contributed towards the growth
of Jazz
as a serious art-form. Thus the past
five decades have witnessed an increase in sophistication of both
techniques
and compositions - an aesthetically progressive rather than regressive
development.
Regardless of this
progression, however, it has to be admitted that only a small
percentage of the
total jazz output of any one decade actually aspires to the status of
fine art,
and that, partly in accordance with the Afro-American predilection for
rhythms
and melodic reiterations, the bulk of it remains firmly attached to the
fundamentally 'primitive' criteria from which it initially sprang. For it must be remembered that, even in an
exuberant and progressive context, genius is a product which cannot be
manufactured in bulk - a majority of the musicians currently engaged in
the
production of Modern Jazz being anything but men of genius! However that may be, the element of genius
which can
be found in this context is sufficient to lend weight to our contention
regarding the musical superiority of the finest jazz compositions over
the
Dionysian compositions of contemporary so-called 'classical' composers. The criteria upon which we can base our
argument are manifold, but it will suffice if we list only the main
ones.
Thus the first and most
important consideration in favour of Jazz is the prevalence of melody,
sometimes of a very beautiful nature but almost invariably, in the
better
compositions, of an attractive or aesthetically-satisfying nature. The second consideration must entail harmony,
not cacophony or the dissolution of harmony into the inharmonious, but
genuine
diatonic harmony used in a subordinate and largely supportive role. The third consideration must bring to our
attention the prevalence of form, sometimes of a simple nature,
sometimes of a
fairly complex nature, but generally appertaining to a recognizable
pattern of
congruous import. These three primary
considerations, which constitute a sine
qua
non in the hierarchy of
compositional value, we investigated earlier, and to them were added
subordinate considerations, such as instrumentation, tone, volume,
number of
instruments, etc. In like manner,
similar subordinate criteria may be applied to Modern Jazz, so that a
composition, for example, with the best possible instrumentation will
usually
make for a more successful result than one where the logic of
instrumental
values or positions in the overall hierarchy has been overruled, not to
say
inverted, in the interests of novelty, change, socialistic radicalism,
etc. Similarly, the instruments combined
together in a jazz ensemble will make for a better or worse effect
depending on
the total numbers employed.
Of course, these
criteria cannot be taken in a literal classical sense.
For although the number of instruments
employed and the way they are combined appertain to the basic criteria
of
classical music in general, great divergences exist in terms of the
particular. Thus, for example, the
number of instruments appropriate to the finest classical music is
vastly
different from the number most suited to the best jazz compositions, in
which
the use of only a few electric instruments can make for a greater
volume of
sound than could be obtained from a large body of acoustic instruments
being
played as loudly as possible, and for which it is therefore imperative
to use
fewer instruments in order to obtain the most effective or satisfying
results. And even the best combination
of instruments differs in particulars from the classical ideal, to the
extent
that we are dealing with a subculture originated by negroes, who were
fundamentally spiritual outsiders in relation to the dualistic
integrity of Spengler's 'Faustian' man.
If Jazz attaches more importance to the use of percussion than
does the
serious music of the white man, it should be seen as partly deriving
from the
fact that drums of various shapes and sizes constituted such an
important role
in the music of the American negro's African ancestors, in consequence
of which
the urge and perhaps even the ability to play them was culturally
inherited. To be sure, there is nothing
in the entire history of Western music which corresponds to the Negro
predilection for complex rhythms: the percussion parts relating to
virtually
all orchestral compositions being frankly elementary when compared with
the
rhythmic complexities continuously being utilized by the finest jazz
drummers,
a majority of whom are black.
Indeed, one might expect
an orchestral percussionist to criticize Jazz for the - to his way of
thinking
- overwhelming amount of percussion relating to it.
Though such criticism would testify to a
misunderstanding of the vastly different importance attached to
percussion by
the leading black exponents of the American subculture, whose African
ancestry
would seem to have endowed them with their own rather more
rhythmically-oriented scale of musical priorities.
For Jazz does not imply an excessive use of
percussion. On the contrary, it entails
an African-derived use of percussion which appertains to a different
and
arguably older cultural ideal. But Jazz
is not, of course, an African phenomenon.
It is a hybrid resulting from the amalgamation of black and
white cultural
trends into a new synthesis. The
American Negro was induced to add a greater consideration for melody to
his
ingrained store of rhythmic vitality.
Thus he produced Jazz. And so arose a subculture under the nose of the Western
ideal.
To this has been added,
in recent years, a still greater integration of black and white
cultural
elements, the Afro-American no longer producing Jazz simply because his
forebears had been brought under the white man's influence, but also
influencing and being further influenced by him, so that, in the course
of
time, a new music arose which blended the predominantly black Jazz with
the
predominantly white Rock. The fact that
there are many white drummers in today's world is ample testimony to
the
influence of Jazz on the white man, just as the number of black
keyboardists
and guitarists in it testifies to the ubiquitous influence of Western
civilization on Blacks. But if Jazz and
Rock were to some extent already hybrid forms on that and similar
accounts,
then the coming together of the two into yet another synthesis has
resulted in
an even greater hybrid - namely, that of Fusion Music.
Now this term need not
imply that Blacks and Whites invariably play together in the same band,
even if
this is the usual implication of it. The
essential thing is that Jazz, with its emphasis on rhythm, should be
further
combined with melody and harmony than would otherwise be the case, if
it
remained purely jazzy. The improvisatory
qualities of the form are still there in some degree, if generally
confined to
a more subordinate role, and, by a like-token, the qualities extracted
from
Rock, such as vocals, harmony, persistent melodic motifs, clear-cut
form, etc.,
are likewise 'watered down' to blend-in with the new compromise
commonly known
as Fusion Music. Admittedly, the term
Modern Jazz has also been used in this context, though one might argue
that it
chiefly appertains to music which has remained predominantly Negro,
with a
stronger emphasis on rhythm and improvisation.
However, irrespective of whether or not one chooses to
differentiate
between these two tendencies, there nevertheless remains a constant
interplay
between black and white elements in this subculture, and I venture to
guess
that even the most jazzy of the moderns is, deep down, probably less
self-consciously black, in his intentions, than were his predecessors
in the
early decades of the twentieth century.
But it should be evident
that if we are to compare recent jazz trends with the regressive trends
of
contemporary Western music, and to contend from such a comparison that
the
former is musically superior to the latter, we must base our contention
on
factors which relate more closely to the essence of the 'Faustian' soul
than to
that of the negro soul. In other words,
it is necessary to pit a music with fine melodies and appropriate
harmonies against
a music which lacks these essential ingredients of musical value - as
most
contemporary Western compositions do - if we're not to get ourselves
caught in
futile cross-references between one culture and another.
Now if we are to
differentiate between Modern Jazz, as being predominantly rhythmic, and
Fusion
Music, as signifying a greater compromise between rhythm and melody,
then it
must be the best examples of the fusion form that we are most entitled
to
compare with and consider superior to contemporary Western
compositions, rather
than those examples of Modern Jazz which adhere to very different
criteria and
more or less go their own way in the interests, primarily, of the
American
negro soul. If, as the term suggests,
Fusion Music is closer to the Western soul than the predominantly black
Modern
Jazz, then it is, above all, from this closeness that we are enabled to
draw
comparisons with traditional musical developments and, in accordance
with the
musical superiority of that tradition vis-à-vis the decadence, pit
these
comparisons against the degenerate sounds of the avant-garde. Thus it is from the finest compositions of
fusion composers such as Jean-Luc Ponty,
Jan Hammer,
John McLaughlin, Chick Corea, Herbie
Hancock, Barry Miles, Stanley Clarke, and George Duke that we should
look for
the diatonic alternative to the mostly cacophonous sounds of the
Western
world's contemporary composers, who have been compelled, willy-nilly,
to drive
serious music a still further remove from the cultural 'gold standard'
set by
Mozart and Beethoven than did their immediate predecessors. For it is largely on account of the fact that
the best elements in both the black and white cultures have joined
forces to
produce Fusion Music, that the Whites most affected by this synthesis
have not
followed the downhill path to atonal cacophony of their more academic
cousins
but, on the contrary, have retained a melodic, harmonic, and diatonic
approach
to composition commensurate with the rhythmic essence of Jazz.
But if many of the
essential criteria of high-quality composition are to be found in
Fusion Music,
how, then, does it compare with the best traditional manifestations of
Western
music - with the compositions, for example, of Mozart and Beethoven? The answer to this question is, I believe,
that it doesn't compare too well. Or,
put more comprehensively, the best of today's Fusion Music is probably
musically superior, note for note, to the worst of the compositions of
the
great composers, but by no means superior to their finest compositions. For, although I have listened to an abundant
supply of the most outstanding Fusion Music, from Return
to
Forever and The Mahavishnu
Orchestra to Weather Report and
The
Mothers of Invention, I haven't heard anything to match or surpass,
for
sheer beauty and creative profundity, the finest music of Handel, Bach,
Haydn,
Mozart, Beethoven, Schubert, Schumann, Mendelssohn, Weber, et al.,
which sprang
from the depths of the 'Faustian' soul when 'the Culture' had not yet
degenerated into 'the Civilization' that we are now witnessing. To be sure, most fusion composers may utilize
more genuinely musical means than their partisan contemporaries of the
avant-garde. But they are still
essentially products of 'the Civilization' and, in many respects, its
materialistic victims, lacking the great spiritual and intellectual
depths to
be found in the works of the greatest classical, classical-romantic,
and even
romantic composers.
It is only with the
twentieth century and, most especially the latter-half of it, that one
can
seriously turn one's back on contemporary Western composition in favour
of the,
by classical standards, second-rate achievements of the most
outstanding fusion
composers, whose music is, I contend, genuinely superior.
(It is interesting to note that, in Hermann Hesse's
classic novel Steppenwolf,
Harry
Haller found Jazz in the nineteen twenties "repugnant ... and yet ten
times preferable to all the academic music of the day." - It was not by
pure chance or creative whim on the part of Hesse
that Haller's cultural heroes were Mozart and Goethe, the men who
represented
'the Culture' at its prime, or that he found both Wagner and Brahms
striving
for redemption in the 'purgatory' of the 'Magic Theatre' for the crime
of
"thick orchestration" which, so we are told, was "a fault of
their time.") Naturally, one's
taste and temperament may lead one to prefer Chick Corea
or Al DiMeola to Mozart or Beethoven. But, in the light of objective criteria, that
would be no reason for one to seriously consider the music of the
former
composers inherently superior to the music of the latter!
In musical criticism, there are certainly
more considerations to bear in mind than those relating to one's
personal
taste, significant as that may be up to a point.
But even if the finest
Fusion Music does not and cannot, through historical necessity, attain
to the
standards set by those composers born when Western civilization was in
its
spiritual prime and not yet far gone in materialistic degeneration, we
should
at least be grateful to its leading exponents for the work they are
doing to
keep melody and harmony alive in a world increasingly beset by atonal
cacophony. Who knows, but humanity may
not have heard the last note yet from a music which, if history is to
record,
could well transpire to have been the noblest cultural achievement of
the
twentieth century?
AN
OUTLINE
OF TRANSCENDENTAL MEDITATION
These
days
meditation has become quite popular. It
is practised daily by thousands of people
throughout Europe and North America, and even in other non-Eastern
parts of the
world. It is simple and effective and,
above all, extremely economical. In
fact, it needn't cost you a penny. You
can both relax yourself and 'get high' absolutely free-of-charge, with
no possibility
of serious addiction. True, you might
become a little too fond of it and subsequently find yourself without
friends
or money or opinions about world events.
But, in the main, you won't be seriously impaired by a daily
fidelity to
meditation. On the contrary, you'll be
enriched by it and, in some cases, quite considerably so!
But what, then, is
meditation? Is it a religion, a cult, a
method of contemplation, a way of life, a protest against society, or
what? Basically it is none of these
things,
though it can certainly be turned into something approximating to any
one of
them, if you so desire it. The truth is
that meditation is simply a way of enjoying your own company, a means
of
acquiring a better opinion of yourself.
It need not have anything whatsoever to do with mystical contact
with
the Godhead or World Soul or whatever you would like to equate divinity
with,
in spite of claims to the contrary by practising Transcendentalists. If you wish to associate a pleasant feeling
with the Godhead, that is your affair.
But it isn't absolutely necessary.
The essential thing is that you should eventually come to
experience a
state of mind which will free you from the tyranny of petty worries,
complaints, miseries, rivalries, etc., if only from 5-10 minutes a day. After all, a feeling approximating to bliss
is worth acquiring for even that short period of time.
And if you appreciate it enough to attempt
extending it from 10-20 minutes a day, well and good!
It won't cost you anything extra.
There are, however,
different methods of meditation, some dependent on breathing routines,
others,
less physical, which require a greater degree of willpower in
concentrating
psychic attention within the head. The
method that most appeals to me at present is the Taoist form
of
breathing from stomach to crown-centre, for which the most important
requirements are a fairly stable pair of lungs and the willpower to
continue
breathing within the confines of a pre-established routine for at least
twenty
minutes. You cannot get high without
making some sort of effort, and even good moods have to be earned one
way or
another - usually at the price of bad ones!
So unless you are prepared to put some physical effort into your
breathing
routine and put-up, initially, with a degree of vertigo partly
resulting from
this, you won't acquire a particularly satisfying level of tranquillity.
How, then, does one set
about meditating in this manner? Let me
explain! To begin with, it helps if you
have something soft to sit on, either a bed or a cushion or a settee. Once you are comfortably seated, you can
cross your legs, put your hands on your kneecaps, or just let them hang
loosely
in front of you. But make sure that your
back is straight! A bent back won't
assist your breathing.
After you've done these
simple things you are ready to proceed with the breathing exercises,
breathing
in-and-out through the nose as, presumably, you would normally do, but
with
greater vigour. The object of the initial
exercises is to stoke-up the fire of your metabolism, so to speak, for
the more
refined exercises to come. So it is
important to inhale as deeply as possible without, however, doing
yourself a
serious injury in the process! The lower
stages of this particular type of meditation are always somewhat
mechanical and
uninspiring, but they are well-worth persevering with, if you hope to
reap the
full benefit of the higher stages later on.
Thus, aided by the
self-imposed deception that your lungs are in your stomach, you
concentrate attention
on the stomach as you inhale, so that it is drawn-in with the breath. When you exhale, however, you let your
concentration flag with the breath, so that the stomach regains its
normal
posture. Thus there is a
centripetal/centrifugal alternation between concentration on the
stomach, as
required by the inhalation, and the natural dissipation of that
concentration
engendered by the exhalation. This
process of steady, full breathing should be continued for at least five
minutes, so it is a good idea to keep your eye on the time while you
are
struggling - though hopefully not flagging - with your deep breathing. The temptation to give-up after 3-4 minutes
of this exercise may well present itself.
But if you remember that everything worthwhile has to be earned,
one way
or another, then you should find the courage or willpower to proceed to
the
next stage of the routine, which will demand a shift of concentration
from the
stomach to the lungs.
Since one invariably
inhales into the lungs anyway, there is no need to impose a deception
upon
oneself here; though one should still alternate concentration on the
lungs, as
one inhales, with a dissipation of that
concentration
as one exhales, so that the centripetal/centrifugal balance of forces
is
maintained. This second stage of the
routine is usually the hardest, because the effort of deep, steady
breathing is
combined, to a greater extent than in the previous exercise, with a
feeling of
vertigo, which is, of course, engendered by both the effort itself and
the
continuous increase of oxygen in the bloodstream resulting from it. You may feel a bit sick at this stage, but
unless you had eaten a heavy meal just before you began these exercises
- a
thing, incidentally, you oughtn't to have done! - you
should survive the feeling on a settled stomach.
After five minutes of
this exercise, you move to the third stage of the routine and focus
your
attention upon the throat, much as though the throat was the receptacle
into
which the oxygen must now pass before you exhale. Here,
too,
some vertigo, tempered by what I
like to call psychic flickering, may persist.
But take courage! You have come
through the hardest stages of this meditation technique and are already
beginning
to feel a growing tranquillity pervade your mind as, with calmer
inhalations
and exhalations, you note the five minutes slipping by.
Now when this time has
elapsed,
it remains for you to shift attention to the crown of your head,
technically
termed the crown-centre, and to breathe up through your nostrils with
the
impression that the oxygen inhaled is not entering your lungs but
caressing the
centre of your brain (which, needless to say, it most certainly isn't
doing!). So here, too, it is necessary to
maintain a
deception, as you imagine that cool streams of air are caressing the
centre of
your brain as you inhale, and then completely forget about yourself as
you
exhale. This fourth and last breathing
exercise will be smoother, easier, more refreshing than the previous
ones, and,
as the five minutes quickly pass, the blissful tranquillity which you
have been
faithfully anticipating will begin to flood your mind, making you
momentarily
conscious, it may be, of a purity of being not altogether incompatible
with the
elevated mentality of Nietzsche's mountain recluse - Zarathustra!
The build-up of oxygen
in the blood produced by the breathing exercises is beginning to fully
assert
itself, not now in terms of vertigo, but in a steady stream of blissful
coolness and calmness. So all that
remains for you to do, once the final five minutes have been dutifully
dispatched, is to experience it where you sit, without particularly
concentrating on any part of your body, and without consciously
interfering with
your normal breathing routine.
Completely enveloped by the tranquillity within you, freed from
petty
thoughts, unannoyed by any neighbour or
family noises
which may be penetrating the thin walls of your room, though very alert
to the
slightest sound, your soul is detached from the narrow confines of the
ego and
becomes both a passive receptacle and an active generator of the purest
feelings.
For 5-10 minutes you sit
perfectly still, wallowing in the purity of your being, experiencing
yourself
with a sublimated feeling of pride, a secret exultation that your soul
is
capable of experiencing such a satisfying condition, with nothing
vulgar to
pollute it or pull it from its Zarathustrian
heights. The discomforts of the
breathing exercises are soon forgotten with the consummation they have
brought
about - a consummation which, if you bothered to reflect on it, would
seem to
be well-worth the previous discomforts!
And so, detached from
the usual claims of the ego in the face of private and public
opposition, you
experience a form of transcendental meditation, or meditation enabling
you to
transcend the narrow confines of the conscious self.
This product of the twenty minutes breathing
routine will normally only last, however, from 5-10 minutes, after
which time
the mind will return to a less-exultant condition, as the build-up of
oxygen in
the blood gradually recedes to a level compatible with the continuation
of
normal breathing. And with the decline
in the oxygen content to its normal level, your meditation officially
comes to
an end, so you might as well return to your usual preoccupations, as
continue
to sit on the bed or settee or whatever with legs crossed.
Altogether, then, this
experience has demanded thirty minutes of your time: twenty for
breathing exercises
and ten for transcendental meditation.
However, you may feel thirty minutes is too long and that the
breathing
exercises demand too much effort and are essentially too boring to be
worth
5-10 minutes' blissful tranquillity. If
so, then I suggest you cut the breathing routine to three minutes with
each of
the four exercises, so that after a twelve-minute accumulation of
oxygen you
will experience tranquillity from 3-6 minutes.
But be warned! These 3-6 minutes
won't grant you such a pleasurable state-of-mind as would have been
acquired
from a twenty-minute breathing routine!
If you do not wish to put much effort into the giving, you
cannot expect
to reap big dividends from the taking.
It's as simple as that!
I have endeavoured to
describe a method of meditation which is based on a simple but very
effective
breathing routine derived from the Chinese Tao te Ching. It can be practised twice a day, morning and
evening, or once a day, preferably in the evening.
It can be practised every day of the week, or
just one or two days a week, depending how you feel about it. There are some people who practise it
regularly for years on-end, but there is no
disgrace
in practising it for merely a few months, if that is all you can manage. You may feel that regular practice of this
meditation technique will simply result in your becoming stuck in
another rut,
with one more boring habit as your master.
If so, then continue it only for as long as it means anything to
you,
and abandon it as soon as you begin to weary of the stereotypical
experience it
seems to evoke. After all, there is a
place for other things in life besides meditation and, although a place
for
meditation can easily be found, there is no reason why it should come
to
dominate your activities to the exclusion of other agreeable
preoccupations. Naturally, like
virtually any other subject on earth, meditation has its hard-core of
fanatical
extremists. But if you are not cut-out
to be such a person yourself, there is little point in trying to follow
suit. Just practise it when and where
you want to experience your soul with a new pride, and it will speak
for itself
with all the justification that everything worthwhile invariably has on
its
side.
But is meditation of
this nature for everyone? Theoretically
one could argue that it is for everyone, insofar as almost everyone has
a pair
of lungs, a throat, a stable heart, etc.
But, in practice, one is obliged to admit that only a
comparatively
small minority of people are really qualified to indulge in it. To begin with, one must have the right
temperament, the right character, to enable one to take it seriously in
the
first place. It is therefore unlikely
that a majority of the working or middle classes would be qualified to
meditate
in this manner, especially those who are always in a rush!
And it is unlikely that people who are too
fat, and consequently unable to get themselves into an upright sitting
posture,
would be particularly qualified to do so, either. Likewise,
one
might argue that people with
poor lungs, whether from general ill-health or tobacco addiction, would
be
no-less poorly qualified to indulge in the increased flow of oxygen to
the
bloodstream, just as the elderly would not be a particularly good
proposition
in that respect. Obviously, one cannot
preach a crusade for universal, dynamic meditation among the masses,
any more
than one can preach a like-crusade for anything else.
And neither can one be surprised by the vast
numbers of people who, not being qualified to meditate in this manner,
are
coerced by what little self-respect they still possess into deriding it.
Put frankly, meditation
is essentially something which appeals to that relatively small
percentage of
the population of any given country who are always interested in the
promulgation of techniques for improving the quality of life, so that
the
individual interested in them may adopt as positive an attitude to life
as
seems compatible with the formulation of any genuinely moral or noble
orientation. Meditation, clearly, isn't
for those whose egocentric relationship to the world leads them to
instinctively shy away from attitudes or practices which imply
gratitude to
life, or a complacency not really
commensurate with
rebellious strictures. It depends to
some extent where one lives, whom one's friends are, what one's
experiences in
life have been, the condition of one's health, etc., as to whether or
not one
will take a positive attitude to meditation.
One can be perfectly justified in deriding it, just as one can
be
perfectly justified in praising it.
Those who do not meditate aren't necessarily fools on that
account. It is simply not for them, and
any attitude
which ignores this is undoubtedly mistaken.
You may, as a devotee of meditation, despise cigarette smokers
as much
as you like, but your feelings towards them will not entitle you to
consider
them wrong to smoke instead of to meditate.
Superior to many of them you may well be, but their inferiority
is
perfectly legitimate, since the foundation, often enough, upon which
your own
superiority has been erected. The only
alternative perspective to this is one of presupposing that what is
right for
oneself should be right for everyone else as well, irrespective of how
sadly
mistaken one could be!
But let us leave these
wider philosophical issues and return, finally, to transcendental
meditation,
which, so we have argued, is not for everyone.
I intimated earlier that meditation isn't a religion or, at any
rate,
need not become one. The fact is that it
can be driven in either an ideological or a religious direction,
depending upon
the nature of the people who practise it and their motives for doing so. By itself, meditation doesn't amount to a
religion. But in the hands of
mystically-minded individuals, it can certainly be used as a very
important
ingredient in one - as, for example, with a number of modern fringe
cults who
practise their own kind of meditation as a means to identification with
the
Godhead.
The kind of meditation
that I have outlined here does not aspire to any mystical
identification with
God conceived, say, in terms of Creator of the Universe, but is simply
an
occupation which, carried out in all sincerity, can provide one with a
highly
satisfying state-of-mind for 5-10 minutes whenever one chooses to
practise
it. You can call this a process of
self-realization if you like, though there is always an element of
doubt, these
days, as to exactly what is meant by this all-too-pervasive expression,
and a
limit, moreover, as to how far it can be taken, since, as the
eighteenth-century Scottish philosopher John Hume pointed out, sense
impressions do not constitute the self any more than the thoughts one
thinks -
full knowledge of the self, as thing-in-itself, ultimately being beyond
one's
cognitive grasp. All one can do, it
seems, is to acquire a rough approximation of the self, and in this
respect the
Orient has more to teach and better techniques at its disposal for the
acquirement of this elusive self-approximation than both the Occident
and the
rest of the world put together!
But
internal
sense impressions certainly can
be
experienced through transcendental meditation, and, as already
intimated, the
purity of these sensible impressions is well-worth the initial struggle
to
attain them. For in a world increasingly
beset by chaos, noise, anarchy, restlessness, tension, doubt, etc.,
meditation
can be of considerable value in enabling one to take temporary refuge
from the
plethora of diurnal events which constantly bombard one's sensibilities
and threaten
to destroy all genuine peace of mind.
Yet the course of action
I have described here has very little to do with the pitiful artaraxia
of the ancient Greeks in their
Hellenistic decadence or, alternatively, with its Buddhist equivalent
of
indifference to pleasure and pain. It is
not a kind of spiritual suicide carried-on with the sole intent of
shutting out
the various contradictory emotional impressions which inevitably befall
anyone
who goes about the world in a natural, open, adventurous manner. Certain so-called sages of the East have long
been renowned, it is true, for their imperturbability - an
imperturbability,
however, which too often smacks of defeatism in the face of life's
manifold
demands on the human spirit and which, in many Westerner's minds, is
still
wrongly associated with any form of meditation.
But that is a
specifically Buddhist form of meditation which has very little to do
with the
thirty minutes combination of breathing routine and the transcendental
tranquillity resulting from it. On the
contrary, we are concerned here with a positive experience, not a
defeatist one
which smacks of world-weariness. We are
concerned here not only in taking a little refuge from the commonplace
demands
and experiences of everyday life but, more importantly, in equipping
ourselves
with another weapon for dealing with them.
For, in the battle of life, meditation may not be the most
powerful
weapon at our disposal, but it is by no means the least powerful, and
many
people's lives are richer and saner for a daily fidelity to thirty
minutes
spent in the above-mentioned fashion than would otherwise be the case. It can help, for one thing, to ease
depression, and, as well as providing one with a temporary sanctuary
from noisy
neighbours, it can put one in a more positive frame-of-mind for
appreciating
the fine arts, especially music - the most idealistic art-form of them
all.
However, like most
things, meditation has to be indulged in moderation, otherwise the
advantages
to be acquired from it will quickly be replaced by disadvantages, and
one may
subsequently find oneself meditating to the exclusion of talking or
reading or
walking or any other such important activities.
The rule, as ever, is to approximate to Aristotle's 'golden
mean',
which, in popular parlance, means that 'variety is the spice of life',
with no
undue emphasis on any one subject to the total exclusion of everything
else. Easier said than done, of course,
but generally followed nonetheless!
PARTIAL
KNOWLEDGE
One
is
always amazed by the vast number of works of art currently
existing in the world, particularly in the Western part of it. What man alive, no matter how well-educated
or cultured he may happen to consider himself, has viewed every great
painting
or listened to every serious musical composition or read every book of
literary
value? The chances of one's stumbling
upon a man who has a complete knowledge of works of art in any one
field are,
to say the least, extremely remote. And
yet there are
men who dedicate the greater part of their lives to the study of
a given art form, men who can talk about painting or music or
literature with
the assurance of people who never waste an opportunity to expand their
knowledge and who know - or imagine they do - as much about it as
anyone. But when all's said and done, how
much do
they really know? Who among them could,
with equal assurance, say: "I have nothing further to learn about my
subject; everything is known to me"?
Is it not more probable that even the most highly-informed
specialists
would have to admit, if they were honest with themselves, that their
knowledge
of art or music or whatever was partial, and that, in contrast to all
the
material corresponding to their subject currently available in the
world, its
partiality represented only a tiny fraction of what would
be the
case, were one ever to arrive at a complete or total knowledge of the
subject
in question. What artist or art critic,
for example, could inform one as to exactly how many paintings and/or
drawings
of quality are to be found in, say, Western Europe or North America in
general? And, similarly, what composer
or music critic could inform one as to the exact number of serious
compositions
which have come down to us from approximately the seventeenth century
to the
present day?
Clearly, there is a
limit to the total number of works of art available.
But is it a limit with which anyone is truly
familiar? One may indeed have to wait a
long time before one meets or hears of anyone who professes to such a
familiarity! Perhaps it would be necessary
for even the
most intelligent and studious of cultured men to live two or three
times the
average life-span, in order to have seen or heard or read everything of
value
in the arts. And perhaps even then it
wouldn't be possible. One might find
oneself with a fairly thorough knowledge of everything West European or
North
American, but with a comparatively scant knowledge of everything
African or
Asian or Middle Eastern or East European or South American or
Australasian. The total number of
valuable works of art available in any one field, be
it visual or aural or otherwise, would, I suspect, suffice to make even
the
most cultured people amazed at the extent of their ignorance where many
such
works are concerned. The only
alternative to a fairly thorough knowledge of the works of one's own
culture-complex, or civilization, would seem to be a general smattering
of the
works of all culture-complexes, both past and present.
Being cultured, like
being well-educated, is always a question of degree, of knowing either
more or
less than someone else but never knowing everything.
The most cultured people are probably
ignorant of more things appertaining to their particular subject than
their
impressive knowledge would suggest. What
they have learnt may, by average standards, be phenomenal and yet still
be
relatively insignificant in terms of the totality of what is
potentially there
to be
learnt. For all we know, their knowledge
of the works of a given art-form might amount to no more than 10% of
the
hypothetical totality of relevant knowledge.
It might even be less. And yet,
human nature being what it is, we needn't
expect them
to be in any degree ashamed of or humiliated by this relatively
humbling
state-of-affairs. Fortunately, where
matters of learning are concerned, our pride in what we know far
outweighs any
shame we may feel for what we don't know, simply because we usually
aren't in
the least aware of the probable extent of our ignorance!
And this, of course, also means that we
generally aren't aware of our exact relationship to other cultured
people -
whether, for instance, they are more cultured or less cultured than we
like to
imagine, or whether their culture, their knowledge of art or music or
literature or sculpture, is superior or inferior to our own. In this respect, as in so many others, we are
isolated in our individual worlds, obliged to construct hypotheses
relating to
our cultural positions, as it were, in the overall hierarchy of
cultural
knowledge. Now sometimes we mistake
these hypotheses for literal facts, and thereupon wrongly assume that
we are
more cultured than an objective appraisal of the situation would in
fact
indicate.
Thus it may happen that
a man with knowledge, shall we say, of six hundred paintings will
convince
himself, on the strength of this fact, that he is highly cultured. Another man may have knowledge of two
thousand, a third of six thousand, a fourth of ten thousand, and so on. In all probability, they will all regard
themselves as highly cultured, and take a certain pride in their
knowledge. But can we reasonably
suppose, other things being equal, that the man with six hundred
paintings to
his credit stands on an equal footing, in terms of art appreciation,
with the
others, or that all the others stand on an equal footing with one
another and
are thus equally cultured?
No, it would seem
unlikely - if the criterion of numbers is to be taken seriously - that
we
can. For their dissimilar knowledge must
mean that one is more cultured than another, and that the man with a
knowledge
of ten thousand paintings has a greater right to consider himself
highly
cultured, in this respect, than the one whose knowledge embraces a mere
six
hundred! And yet, there is still no
reason for us not to suppose that the latter will consider himself
highly
cultured on the strength of what he does
know or,
alternatively, that the former - the man with ten thousand paintings to
his
credit - may not be as highly cultured as he appears to be when
contrasted to
someone with, say, a knowledge of thirty thousand paintings. Indeed, one begins to sense how contingent
and provisional an opinion of oneself in terms of the degree of one's
culture
could be in relation to other people. If
a man with a knowledge of thirty thousand
paintings is
more cultured than one whose knowledge embraces ten thousand, what is
to
prevent us from supposing that even he
might not
be as highly cultured as he imagines, that, compared to someone with
fifty
thousand paintings to his credit, he may only be moderately cultured?
Yet what exactly do we
mean by 'knowledge of paintings'? Is it
a question of having viewed a painting and memorized who it is by and
what it
is called? Is it, rather, a question of
having memorized the general theme and technical outlines of a painting? Or is it a question of having analysed a
painting in some depth, so that one is familiar with whatever symbolism
it may
contain, or with the techniques employed in its execution, or with its
colour
scheme? Obviously, one could ask other
such questions relating to this problem 'knowledge of paintings' and,
in
answering them or having them answered by others, find that one man's
definition
of the concept was very different from another's - indeed, that what
one man
meant by it was insignificant compared with what another meant, and so
on. At the risk of further complicating
matters,
one might even find that, in consequence of a profounder interpretation
of
'knowledge', the man with a mere six hundred paintings to his aesthetic
credit
was more cultured than a majority of those who had viewed or studied a
greater
number, but not viewed or studied them as thoroughly.
Who knows, but the world is full of such
complexities, and we are simply being superficially presumptuous when
we strive
to impose our simplicity upon it.
This is essentially
what, in a rather roundabout way, I am driving at in this essay:
namely, the
uncertainty of so much of our knowledge about ourselves in relation to
other
people, and the degree of self-deception to which subjectivity in our
opinions
about ourselves can accordingly lead us.
And in terms of how cultured or well-educated we are, there is
indeed
room for a great deal of self-deception!
What to one man may seem like refinement may appear unspeakably
crude to
another. What we took to be a vast
reservoir of cultural information in one man may be little more than a
drop in
the ocean, so to speak, of a truly comprehensive cultural knowledge. We simplify out of habit and necessity, and
we are so accustomed to doing so ... that we often overlook the fact
that the
complexities are still there, no less real than before.
But self-doubts still lurk behind the mask of
complacency, and it is to our credit that we occasionally remove the
mask and
air them to the extent that we can, enabling ourselves to extend the
boundaries
of knowledge and explore a few of those complexities to which custom
had
hitherto blinded us. Thus it is that we
may come to view our cultural opinion of ourselves with less certainty
and more
sceptical detachment than would otherwise have been the case, had we
not
bothered to question ourselves but allowed our presumption to take root
in a
false security.
Returning to the subject
of art and to the varying extents of our knowledge about it, we are
obliged to
confess that what we took to be a high level of cultural awareness may
not be
as high as we imagined, if only because there are so many paintings,
drawings,
etchings, engravings, etc., which we have still to view.
And in the totality of the existing works of
art, it could well transpire that even the most well-informed of us is
some way
short of having viewed everything, both within and without their own
culture-complex.
But what applies to art
in particular also applies, in large measure, to the arts in general -
to
music, literature, and sculpture, where the overwhelming mass of
available
material makes virtual dilettantes of us all, including the most
cultured and
specialized of us, whose immense knowledge, if it were computable,
would shame
any layman intelligent enough to appreciate the virtues of scholarship
into
respectful silence. Here, too, in music
and literature no less than painting, there are doubtless many
misunderstandings and misconceptions concerning the extent of one's
knowledge
or the degree of one's culture. Some
people are much more cultured than others, and yet this doesn't prevent
a
number of those who are less cultured from assuming that they are
highly
cultured. And neither, of course, does
it prevent some of those who, in relation to the latter, are highly
cultured
from assuming that they have little more to learn.
In each case, human vanity works the same
way, so that a majority of people with any degree of culture are
generally
going to think better of themselves than facts, if known, might
otherwise
convince them. Again, of all the works
of literature or serious music currently available in the world, one
needn't be
particularly surprised if it could be shown that even the most
knowledgeable of
people knew no more than about 10%, and, in all but a few cases, this
tiny
fraction would take the form of a provincial or national thoroughness,
as it
were, rather than a universal smattering.
But I do not intend this
comment to be taken for an indictment, still less as an example of
cynicism
from some smart-aleck who thereby hopes to make himself
out to be cleverer or better-informed than he really is.
The author of this humble essay makes no
claims to cultural omniscience himself (unlike certain learned
Frenchmen) and
would hesitate to consider himself highly cultured, particularly
vis-à-vis the
arts of painting and sculpture, for which, in any case, he has a rather
limited
interest. What culture he has
acquired
may indeed be somewhat in excess of that meted-out to the average man,
but it
is altogether doubtful whether, in relation to his relative youth, it
would
entitle him to consider himself among the most highly cultured of
persons. As yet, he still has some way to
go, a number
of decades ahead, during which time he will probably continue to peruse
books,
listen to music, and scrutinize various paintings, drawings, objects
d'art, etc., with his customary perseverance and, no less
importantly,
critical reserve.
No, much as facts may
compel this writer to recognize his own limitations, they in no way
invalidate
his contention concerning the overwhelming amount of serious art in the
world
and our relative ignorance of it - an ignorance of which no-one,
including the
most highly cultured, need feel ashamed.
Whether, in accordance with Nietzsche's prophecy of the
Superman, we
shall ever arrive at an age abounding in superaesthetes,
who
will
make today's leading 'culture vultures' seem comparatively
philistine,
remains to be seen. Though we can be
pretty certain that if we do, it will not be for some time to come! In the meantime, a majority of intelligent,
culturally-disposed people will doubtless continue to bruise their
brains over
the arts, without appreciably advancing their capacity to absorb and
appreciate
whatever the world has to offer them by way of cultural nourishment.
I have written at some
length on our ignorance of the totality of great art available in the
world,
and of the efforts various people make, according to their individual
capacities, to extend their knowledge of art as far as possible. At present, even the most cultured of us are
confined to a tiny fraction of the world's cultural resources. Now if this is staggering enough, how much
more staggering is it to think in terms of hypothetical cultural
resources on
other planets throughout the Universe and to contrast, in imagination,
the
totality of art on Earth with the possible totality of art elsewhere! If the mind boggles when confronted by the
vast amount of man-made art currently in existence, whether in
painting,
literature, music, or anything else, how much more must it do so once
we take
into account the possibility of advanced life elsewhere in the
Universe, and
the unbelievable quantity of cultural wealth the Universe could
hypothetically
contain!
Imagine for a moment the
possibility - and it is
possible - of millions upon
millions of other habitable planets, many of them far bigger than the
Earth,
upon which the arts have flourished, in one form or another, for
thousands if
not millions of years and, no less astoundingly, make the totality of
Earth art
(if I may be permitted such a precociously comprehensive term) seem but
a tiny
drop in the vast ocean of all art currently existing anywhere in the
Universe! A fantastic hypothesis, to say
the least, but not one that any man alive could seriously refute! For the hypothesis of man being the only
art-producing life-form in the entire Universe would seem far more
fantastic to
me than any hypothesis concerning the possible existence of alien works
of
art. Our rapidly-expanding knowledge of
the immensity of the Universe makes it increasingly difficult, not to
say
unreasonable, for us to consider ourselves to be the only advanced or,
at any rate,
intelligent life-form in existence, and now that we have arrived at a
more open
attitude concerning our relation to it, there seems to be sufficient
reason for
us to entertain the notion that other intelligent, evolving beings may
also
have produced - and still be producing - works of art which match, if
not
surpass, anything created here on Earth.
With such speculation, it soon becomes apparent that the
cultural wealth
of the Universe could be so great, so unbelievably vast, that not even
the most
advanced superaesthete would have as much
as an
inkling of its total extent. Floundering
in the accumulated wealth of Earth cultures, he would have to rest
content with
a vague intimation of the possible magnitude of creative endeavour
throughout
the Universe, and leave it to his descendants to acquire, step by step,
a
slightly more comprehensive knowledge of all the arts.
However, in returning to
the present, one might conclude that the objective of acquiring a
really
comprehensive knowledge of the totality of cultural achievements here
on Earth
still remains to be achieved, and will probably not be achieved for
some time
yet - if, indeed, it ever is. Lacking
time and method, we shall have to content ourselves, in the meantime,
with a
partial knowledge of our cultural heritage - a knowledge which even the
most
highly cultured of us must inevitably regard in relation to that
greater
ignorance which makes the acquirement of culture such a fascinating
and, at the
same time, continuous lesson!
URBAN
STERILITY
AND THE MODERN SOUL
The
real
tragedy of modern life is the overwhelming size of the
largest cities. A majority of people are
no longer in close or even regular contact with nature, with the
pulsating life
of natural phenomena, but are constantly surrounded by the man-made
lifeless
forms which constitute contemporary megalopolis. They
live
so close to concrete, steel, glass,
lead, rubber, aluminium, plastic, etc., that they are invariably
drained of a
great deal of their vital life-force, drained, if you like, of
spiritual
potentialities which their less-urbanized ancestors generally
experienced and
doubtless took for granted, as the natural property of mankind. Shut out from regular contact with natural
phenomena, with soil and crops and trees and flowers, they take on the
quality
of the sterile environments in which they live or, rather, exist,
becoming
increasingly like automata - soulless figures in a soulless world, that
of the
big city.
How painful it can be
for anyone with a knowledge of the biological necessity of one's living
in
close proximity to nature ... to stand on the pavements in one of the
more
built-up parts of a big city and note the absence of vegetation! There are streets in most major cities where
there isn't a tree or a bush or a flower in sight, where the inanimate
so
dominates the area that one seriously wonders how anyone can manage to
survive
there, so lunar is the resulting impression.
And even on streets where some effort has been made to
acknowledge
nature, where a few small trees or saplings have been planted at
regular
intervals along the edge of the pavement - how inadequate they usually
appear
when contrasted with the predominantly commercial or industrial
surroundings in
which, one can only suppose, they are doomed to fight a losing battle,
to
languish pitifully and painfully in the indifferent and sometimes
hostile
environment of concrete, steel, glass, petrol fumes, noise, etc., which
inevitably takes precedence over them!
How hateful to such a
person, a person keenly aware of man's current plight, is the spectacle
of
crazy paving in so-called front gardens, where the residents are either
too
lazy to tend the soil or too busy doing other things to have any time
for
gardening, and have accordingly capitulated to the tyranny of concrete,
abdicated their private right to stand-up for natural phenomena in a
society
whose ever-increasing preoccupation with the man-made, with artificial
phenomena, is bringing about its own downfall and inevitable spiritual
and
moral death. For how can life, human or
otherwise, possibly thrive in a society where the inanimate has come to
play
such a dominating role? Is it any wonder
that the great majority of long-term city-dwellers appear so washed
out, sickly
and mean, or that their feelings are so often apathetic, shallow,
callous, and
negative?
No, of course not! You cannot spend the greater part of your
life out-of-contact with the living pulse of nature and hope to remain
healthy. Sterility begets sterility,
and, by contrast to their more fortunate ancestors, the souls of a
majority of
contemporary people are most certainly sterile!
They may not be completely dead, but they are undoubtedly a long
way
from being fully alive! If they have any
feelings at all, such feelings either don't run very deep or are apt,
in the
worst cases, to turn negative. Their
possessors are too greatly the victims of their lifeless environments
to have
any real comprehension of or empathy with the soul, to be in a position
to
properly grasp the significance of the cultural life from which modern
civilization has irrevocably banished them.
As idolaters at the shrine of the intellect, they can only
concur with
Nietzsche that "God is dead" and marvel that churches should still
exist. For in relation to the maimed
state of their souls and the preponderance of the inanimate, those
manifestations of man's acknowledgement of the more-than-human - in
short, of
nature and that which presides over and also exists supernaturally
above it -
have indeed become anachronisms, scarcely to be countenanced by the
modern
mind.
As Spengler,
the
German
philosopher of history, so eloquently informed us, 'the
Civilization' of contemporary urban and industrial society is
essentially the
reverse of 'the Culture' of medieval and catholic spirituality, and
whatever
pertained to 'the Culture' can hardly be taken to heart in 'the
Civilization',
with its materialistic values. Truly,
the West is indeed on the decline!
Modern men are not the super-enlightened, anti-superstitious
people that
the liberal intelligentsia may prefer us to regard them as but, for the
most
part, unfortunate wretches who have lost or are in the process of
losing their
souls. They have simply been
transformed, largely through environmental changes, from predominantly
sentient
beings into predominantly existential ones; from creatures firmly under
the
sway of the divine life-principle to creatures increasingly coming
under the
domination of its diabolic antithesis, and, without a shadow of a
doubt, one is
less fortunate in the latter context than in the former!
It is better to be a soulful being in close
contact with nature than a veritable automaton who has lost proper
contact with
it, because the society in which he lives, in becoming the victim of
its
industrial and technological genius, has increased its population to a
point
where cities are so large ... that the artificial comes to predominate
over
nature and to dominate people's lives, obliging them to live a kind of
environmental blasphemy.
A kind
of environmental blasphemy? Yes
and no. 'Yes' because, objectively
considered, whatever sets itself up against the natural order of life,
and
thereupon forces people to pervert themselves, must be an irreverence,
a
profanation, a hubris,
in
which man pits himself against
the preordained nature of things through wilful disobedience and
inevitably
brings about his own downfall. Thus his
anti-natural confinements and lifestyles in large cities could be seen
as
constituting a species of practical blasphemy.
However, a society in
which, largely through the aforementioned reasons, "God is dead" ...
can hardly be accused of blasphemous activities, insofar as it has
ceased to
have any genuine relationship with God, having changed its scale of
values in
accordance with purely secular or materialistic criteria.
Such a society does not commit blasphemy when
it indulges in heart transplants, for example, because the heart has
ceased to
mean anything beyond being a muscle which pumps blood through the body. It has been reduced, through the
materialistic influence of urban civilization, to the literal status of
a pump,
which fights shy of any medieval, and hence cultural, associations with
the
"seat of the soul" or other figurative interpretations proper to 'the
Culture'. Where formerly the heart, to
all cultural purposes, was more soul than pump, it is now merely a
utilitarian
entity, subject to medical diagnosis, on a par with the liver or the
kidneys! The figurative interpretation
has been swept away to leave - what? A
very matter-of-fact conception which ceases to appeal to the
imagination but is
in perfect accord with the scientifically-biased tendencies of urban
man, who,
having sacrificed his soul to his intellect, will doubtless regard the
medieval
estimate of the heart as an unnecessary superstition!
Such is how matters
proceed on the temporal plane, where allegations of blasphemy would
seem to be
quite irrelevant. Shut off as it now is
in its own urban isolation from adequate contact with nature, modern
industrial
society will probably proceed, if time permits, to develop heart
surgery and
perhaps even brain surgery to a point where the Frankenstein myth will
become
reality, where the creation of human monsters will be hailed as one of
the
great achievements of medical science, and the propagation of such
monsters
duly be sanctioned by the state, presumably with law enforcement or
military
security in mind!
Fortunately, modern
society hasn't quite arrived at that point, but there can be little
doubt that
it is steadily advancing towards it with or without the guidance of
prognoses,
or symptoms, like Brave
New
World.
Divorced, as it largely is, from the moral-world-order implicit
in
nature, such a society must increasingly fall victim to the immorality
inherent
in any perversion of that order, and thus eventually reap
self-destruction. For much as it may
prefer to wallow in its urban isolation, the natural-world-order still
exists,
both within and without, and won't tolerate persistent abuse for ever. In the long-run, we pay for our crimes
against life, whether they have been inflicted upon us by society or
inflicted
upon society by us. Man is the ultimate
loser, not God. [ I should like to assure the reader that the foregoing
attack
upon city life is not indicative of a form of Manichean dualism,
whereby matter
is considered evil and only the spirit, by contrast, good, since I have
no
desire to consider Nature, or natural phenomenal in general, inherently
evil. On the contrary, if I regard the
man-made as evil it is only so in excess, not in moderation. Thus the vast scale of the largest cities,
with their detrimental effect upon the soul, compels me to regard them
as being
in opposition to Nature, and thus fundamentally evil.]
So what, if anything,
can be done to reverse this trend and restore society to something like
a
healthy state of soul? Not much, it
would appear. Having abandoned nature in
the development of our principal cities, we can't very well return to
it
again. The large populations which were
originally made possible by the Industrial Revolution have to be fed
and housed
somewhere, and so the necessity of people living in close proximity to
one
another in vast conurbations cannot reasonably be denied.
Whatever the immediate future holds in store for
us, we cannot possibly reverse the trend of 'the Civilization', to
revert to Spengler, and thereupon effect a
return to 'the
Culture'. Our buildings, populations,
industries, and technologies are the chief reasons for 'the
Civilization', and
they can only be accepted on their own terms.
Knowing why we are in the position in which we now find
ourselves may be
of some interest to us, but it cannot reasonably be expected to open
the way
for a return to former and intrinsically superior standards. If there is a price, materially and
spiritually, for everything, then Western civilization is no exception. The price we are paying, not only for our
industrial and technological advances but also for our social and urban
expansion, is a high one. It involves a
loss of soul which would have horrified our cultural ancestors,
accustomed as
they generally were to a less-urbanized and more freely natural
environment. The fertile 'Culture', in
which they lived and for the most part spiritually thrived, was sold
down river
for the comparatively sterile 'Civilization' of today.
Trapped, as a majority of us now are in the
great cities which technological advances made possible, victims of the
sterile
pavements, roads, and buildings which surround and imprison us on all
sides, we
can only live in accordance with the spiritual limitations such an
environment
inevitably imposes upon one, only react in a modern way to the cultural
riches
of the past.
Strange though it may
seem, even the greatest of our technological achievements are
inherently
inferior to the greatest cultural achievements of the past. The television, radio, gramophone, aeroplane,
rocket, car, train, computer, telephone, etc., may all be wonderful
inventions
and phenomena of which Western man can justifiably be proud. But by comparison with the greatest
paintings, music, poetry, literature, cathedrals, sculptures,
tapestries,
furniture, etc., of the past, they signify a secondary order of
achievement. Why? Because 'the Culture' takes precedence over 'the
Civilization'. Because the creation
of works in, and made
possible by, a largely natural environment is superior to the creation
of works
in, and made possible by, a largely artificial one.
Because the spirit is naturally superior to
the intellect, and works which testify to
spiritual
greatness can only take precedence over those testifying to
intellectual
greatness. Whether we like it or not,
the fact is that we live in an age which, no matter how great its
technological
achievements, is intrinsically inferior to the one that preceded it. We have shut ourselves off from nature to
such an extent that our souls, deprived of the nourishment they require
to
thrive, have generally atrophied and accordingly ceased to govern our
conduct. Handed over to the intellect,
as to a hangman, we have become increasingly like automata, bereft of
feeling,
enthusiasm, imagination, strong desire, real creative power. Our souls are still there of course, but,
like invalids in a sick ward, they function in a thoroughly thwarted
and
enfeebled manner.
Those of us who remain
loyal to the Arts, whose business it is to leave a cultural record of
the
times, are acutely aware of this, and whether the name be Bacon, Moore,
Beckett, or Tippett, the record left is
not one that
anyone with a healthy, well-nourished soul would care to witness! In an age when the soul is starved and
maimed, the most sincere artists have no alternative but to convey,
through whichever
medium they exploit, the prevailing spiritual condition, to offer a
protest on
behalf of the sick soul, and thus acquire for themselves
a relatively negative status. This is,
needless to say, a deeply regrettable situation! For
no
genuine artist wishes to convey
negative feelings and impressions if he can possibly avoid doing so! The greatest art is ever a highly positive
phenomenon, a record of spiritual wealth, a testimony to spiritual
wellbeing. Such it generally was from
approximately the
thirteenth to the eighteenth centuries, when cultural activities were
uppermost. But from the late-eighteenth
century a reversal of this trend increasingly began to set-in, as, with
the
expansion of his towns and cities, man grew progressively more
estranged from
nature and forced into an increasingly unnatural lifestyle. Not surprisingly, the artist, no less than
most other people, felt the impact of this environmental
transformation, and,
if he didn't attempt to flee from it by portraying imaginary realms of
the past,
and thus creating an inferior because largely irrelevant brand of art,
was
obliged to record its effects upon his soul and, by analogy and
observation,
the souls of the men of his generation or time.
Needless to say, the closer one comes to the present the more,
by a
corresponding degree, the true artist is obliged to convey feelings and
impressions of a lower, coarser, more
chaotic and
sickly nature. The genuine artist
invariably has to do this, since he must relate to the spiritual
context of the
age, not desert it for some historical or fantastic realm of
compensatory
illusion or, worse still, desert the realm and function of art itself
by
endeavouring to glorify that which is fundamentally antithetical to
art, that
which pertains exclusively to 'the Civilization' rather than to 'the
Culture',
and takes an overly materialistic form.
Thus there can be no
question of the genuine artist, the genuine painter, shall we say,
creating
works which glorify the machine, industrialism, technological advance,
large-scale
urbanization, science, etc., because such phenomena run contrary to the
domain
of art and are essentially inimical to it.
Art is for ever at the service of the divine ideal, the ideal
dependent
upon and stemming from nature, which treats of the life of the soul. Hence its allegiance to
religion, myth, people, and the feelings which these phenomena inspire. When the divine ideal is uppermost, as it
must be when artificial environments aren't too extensive, art attains
to its
greatest peaks. But as soon as this
ideal is threatened and eventually supplanted by the diabolic ideal ...
with
its priority on intellect, reason, technological advance, science,
etc., art
inevitably declines, being in legion with the soul.
As we have seen in recent decades, it can
decline to a very low level. But it
cannot disappear altogether, for the simple reason that nature and the
divine
ideal cannot completely disappear, even in the most materialistic of
societies. No matter how ugly a given
painting may be,
it is still art if it remains loyal to the natural foundations upon
which true
art is built. Inferior art it may well
be, but in an age which is hostile to the arts, where inferior art is
the best
that can be expected, it is still preferable to both anti-art and the
prospect
of no art at all.
Concerning anti-art,
there are, I believe, fundamentally two main kinds.
Firstly, there is the kind of production
which, in turning its back on the natural concerns of genuine art,
seeks to
identify with or draw inspiration from the machine, technology,
science,
urbanization - in sum, from those predominantly artificial factors
appertaining
the 'the Civilization'. A majority of vorticist and cubist paintings are undoubtedly
of this
order, reflecting a futile attempt at sex-change, so to speak, on the
part of
art. But just as a man will cease to be
masculine if he undergoes a sex-change, so art ceases to be art when it
abandons its legitimate role in support of 'the Culture' and goes over
to 'the
Civilization'. As far as art is
concerned, there can be no question of its identifying with or drawing
inspiration (sic) from science and technology!
Whatever seeks to do so is anti-art, which is intrinsically
inferior to
poor art.
Aside from this
manifestation of anti-art, however, which has more recently manifested
itself
in op(tics) and kinetics, there is a second
and
possibly more prevalent manifestation at large in the Western world,
which
usually takes the form of anarchy and destruction.
Perhaps abstract expressionist paintings are
the chief offenders here, though there are undoubtedly a great many
expressionist, dadaist, and surrealist
works which
are equally guilty of making war on art through their practitioners
either
failing to understand the true nature of art or refusing to accept that
art is
still possible. In this kind of
production, there may be a pleasure in destruction for destruction's
sake, with
a total disregard for the rules and principles of art carried out in a
thoroughly
anarchic manner. If art is no longer
possible, then one must do one's bit to illustrate this point by making
as
chaotic a mess of painting as possible.
Such, one feels, would be the credo of the purveyors of this
second kind
of anti-art who, not being genuine artists themselves, doubtless
cherish a
private satisfaction that circumstances enable them to do what they do
without
incurring widespread public disdain.
Lacking a deep sense of tradition, the anti-artists are
all-too-ready,
one way or another, to identify themselves with modern times, to turn
against
art with the kind of atheistic loathing one might expect from a
scientist or an
industrialist, and to produce works - if such they can be called -
which
probably appeal to these latter as being largely in accord with their
own materialistic
mentalities!
Fortunately to say,
there are still genuine artists to be found in the world, artists whose
work,
while not being particularly great by Medieval or Gothic or Rococo
standards,
is nevertheless preferable to anything the anti-artists might produce. Aware of the artist's function in society,
such men continue to grant allegiance to the soul, to the divine ideals
inherent in nature. Whatever the styles
they have adopted, the soul is portrayed as it is or appears to be in
contemporary life, portrayed in the abject condition to which it has
been
reduced by progressive industrialization and urbanization, and thus
portrayed
with an underlining implication of despair, dejection, outrage, horror,
etc.,
as the case may be, but never with either defeatism or acquiescence in
the
status quo! So far as our
spiritual/cultural life is concerned, things may never have been worse. But the genuine artist, if he can survive,
will not be one to throw in the towel, as it were, and go over to the
enemy's
camp. If he cannot be the good
conscience of the age, the recorder of positive feelings, then he must
be its
bad conscience and offer the world or the society in which he exists
the
distorted reflection of its starved and
maimed soul in the mirror of his art.
And offer it, moreover, in the most accurately reflective of
contemporary terms. For any painter who
is not also the critic of his age, whether positively, as in the past,
or
negatively, as in the present, is not really an artist at all, but
either a charlatan
or a traitor. Now what applies to
painters applies no less to writers, sculptors, and musicians, who must
serve
the cause of the soul in opposition to any mechanistic principles 'the
Civilization' may have put in their way.
Admittedly, where many
modern works are concerned, particularly in painting, it may be
difficult to
distinguish genuine artists from sham artists.
For the artist is obliged to record such a pitiful state of
soul, these
days, that his works are often as chaotic and repulsive-looking as
those of the
anti-artists who set themselves up against him in their glorification
of
materialism. In extreme cases, the
ultimate criterion must rest with the artist himself, who should know
whether
his work is a reflection of contemporary society or an abdication of
art, a
criticism, implicit or otherwise, of technological domination or an
unabashed
acquiescence in it. But, generally, it
should be possible for one to form a fair estimate as to which side of
the
cultural fence a given work is on - whether it is poor art or no art at
all,
according to the nature of the subject-matter (if any) and the way in
which it
is treated. Where no criticism of the
modern environment is apparent, as mostly transpires to being the case
with vorticist, cubist, op, and kinetic
works, one can be pretty
certain that one is in the realm of anti-art.
For the cold, mechanical objectivity and impersonality of such
forms
betrays an allegiance to the technological age from which they spring,
and
cannot possibly be equated with genuine art.
In terms of fidelity to the soul, even the most hideous or
pathetic-looking expressionist painting will be of a superior order of
creation
to the most intricate and aesthetically-arranged cubist painting, if it
corresponds to the artist's anguish of soul in the face of contemporary
materialism. Poor art it may be, but at
least it will be art, not a double-crossing, self-deceiving
identification with
contexts inherently inimical to the spirit and thus to art in general,
or, as
in the case of many less-representational works, an identification with
destruction for destruction's sake, or chaos for the sake of chaos, as
befits
the other kind of anti-art, of which dada is a notable example. If we do not perceive a protest on behalf of
the sick soul in an age which has turned against
the soul,
we do not experience an artist!
That the condition of
the soul he is reflecting is unlikely to get better but, on the
contrary, to
grow still worse, shouldn't prevent him from making his protest or
criticism
known. Doubtless, he will have to adjust
his interpretation of the soul's worsening condition in accordance with
the
degrees of its worsening, and we shall judge him on the basis of his
accuracy
in pinpointing those degrees, according to environment, and reflecting
our
actual state, not underestimating or overestimating it.
Irrespective of the fact that he has no
option but to produce poor art, the finest artist will continuously be
the best
diagnostician of the soul, even if, through no fault of his own, he
cannot also
be the doctor who cures it. If we do not
like his diagnosis - and it has to be admitted that a majority of
contemporary
people certainly don't - then we have no alternative but to accept it,
to see
it as a legitimate concern of his, and to treat that concern with due
respect. The temptation not to do so is,
however, very real, particularly since it casts such a poor reflection
upon
ourselves and is so painful to behold!
We needn't be surprised,
therefore, if the genuine artist is becoming an increasingly feared and
hated
member of society. For his frank
portrayal of our sickness is not the most flattering of achievements,
and by no
means the most conscience-quieting! No
wonder that so many industrious citizens should privately - and
sometimes
publicly - be of the opinion that artists ought to be done away with! Aren't they a luxury we can no longer
afford? Aren't they a damn nuisance,
what with their ugly and mean creations, their stunted caricatures of
upstanding people? What has become of
art?
Yes, but why not,
rather, what has become of our souls ... that artists should be obliged
to
portray us in such an ignominious fashion?
And what would become of us if we got rid of all artists, all
genuine
artists, that is, and thereby lost contact with the state of our souls
altogether, lost contact, that is to say with a record of the extent of
their
sickness? Surely it would be a more
unfortunate thing to blunder-on in the darkness of our technological
preoccupations, without anyone to remind us of the harm we are doing to
ourselves, than to have a record of it there right before our eyes,
like a bad
conscience, pinpointing the extent of our spiritual deprivation! Why don't we give the artist a welcome
opportunity to paint less disconcerting and possibly more agreeable
paintings,
by improving our standard of living, i.e. by reverting to a social
environment
less detrimental to our souls?
Alas, I think I made it
sufficiently clear, in the opening paragraphs of this essay,
that such a reversion was out of the question!
For we cannot do away with millions of people
and pull down thousands of buildings in order to bring nature closer to
us,
when these people and buildings are an integral part of our current
system, our
industrialized lifestyles. Yet it is the
very fact of our being so cut off from nature which has made for our
spiritual
sickness - such as it is.
No, social expediency
and common decency prohibit any drastic measures aimed at restoring our
souls
to a healthy condition! We have no
alternative, short of suicidal madness, but to accept things for what
they are
and resign ourselves to living in 'the Civilization', the age of little
feeling
and great intellect. Thanks to
industrial progress the human population of the West was enabled to
increase as
never before, and, consequently, the cities were obliged to expand as
never
before, to shut out more and more of the pulsating life of natural
phenomena,
thereby confronting the bulk of their inhabitants with the urban
sterility to
which we have grown so painfully accustomed.
No wonder that our souls began to atrophy and our minds to
become
increasingly atheistic! Isn't it
perfectly logical, perfectly inevitable?
Imprisoned in our concrete hells, we could no longer feel
God, no
longer relate to natural phenomena.
We had no option but to adjust to an inferior
lifestyle, to resign ourselves to the death-in-life which our sterile
environments were imposing upon us, and put our trust in the future of
the machine. Abandoning God, we entered
'the
Civilization', as upon an epoch of Hell, a few to become disillusioned
by the
course of events, many to fall victim to the great liberal delusion of
universal progress and enlightenment.
Progress? Yes, technological advancement there
certainly was and, needless to say, continues to be.
But personal spiritual
improvement? Not a hope! We progressively reduced ourselves to our
current state of enfeebled feeling and tyrannous intellect, and called
the
result enlightenment, an emancipation from
the soul, a
kind of liberation from life. And so,
having starved our souls of natural phenomena and maimed them amidst
all the
artificial phenomena which we either chose or were obliged to impose
upon them,
we managed to get along without religion.
For religion is an acknowledgement of life, more specifically
the life
of the soul, and when one no longer lives but merely exists in
existential
lunacy - ah! then there is no point in
religion, is
there?
No, none at all! Though we needn't be surprised or offended if
there are still priests of one sort or another to be found amongst us,
men who,
like genuine artists, are there to remind us that we still have souls,
if
rather maimed ones, and will doubtless continue to remind us of this
fact (even
if they cannot do anything to heal them), until such time as our
civilization
either destroys itself or is destroyed from without.
But let us not forget that priests, no less
than artists, are representatives of a higher and better kind of life,
even if,
like artists, they are generally looked down upon in this day and age
as
nuisances, madmen, and anachronisms.
Less soulful they may well be than their more fortunate
forebears, who
lived in healthier times. But if they
are true to their vocation, they will still know that a life governed
by the
soul is superior to an existence lived in the intellect.
For, as Christ said:
"What does it profit a man if he gains the world but loses his soul?"
I believe that we are in
a better position to appreciate the value of such a rhetorical question
now
than ever before, since we have first-hand evidence of what it means to
exist
in a world inimical to life. Thus
Spoke
Zarathustra, with its invocation
to "become
hard", may well be the leading testament of 'the Civilization', but it
is
somewhat inferior, in essence, to the leading testament of 'the
Culture', which
circumstances have largely obliged us to ignore. We
have
indeed become hard, even harder than
the negative theologian who invoked us to could have imagined or would
probably
have wanted. But in the cyclical
development of life, which Nietzsche himself endorsed, it is perhaps to
be
hoped that, if humanity can survive any future catastrophe which
science or
technology may have in store for it, a time will come when we shall
become, if
not exactly soft, then at least well-balanced again, when people will
know what
it means to live on the higher plane of their souls in close contact
with
nature, rather than on the lower plane of their intellects in close
contact with
all the life-denying forces of the big city.
In the meantime, we can only persevere with our condition and at
least
try to get our facts straight. A knowledge of our plight is better than an
ignorance of it,
no matter how seemingly hopeless things may now appear.
THE
FALL
OF LOVE
Despite
all
the romantic poetry, romances, and love songs which
our cultural past has bequeathed to us, we live in an age when love,
signifying
a strong and lasting emotional attachment to someone, has virtually
become a
thing of contempt, an outworn sentimentality that, so we believe, only
the most
foolish or backward of people can be expected to take seriously. It is almost as though anyone who does manage
to fall in love with another person should be secretly ashamed of the
fact,
just as he should be secretly ashamed of himself if he undergoes a
conversion
to Christianity and thereupon discovers the reality of faith. Somehow he is living against the grain of the
age, which has declared emotional love to be an anachronism and
supplanted it
with free love - the backbone of our ostensibly promiscuous society. And yet, strange as it may seem, people do
still fall
in love and remain loyal to a given person over a lengthy period of
time, even
though the age may effectively disapprove of the fact and flaunt its
promiscuity. Love, despite the
derogatory connotations heaped upon it by the liberated practitioners
of free
love, continues to manifest itself in varying intensities, and even its
critics
aren't wholly immune to its influence.
Free lovers can become bound, just as bound lovers can
eventually become
free.
But why, one may ask,
has love recently become so suspect, so quaint and contemptible? Surely an experience which, if all goes well,
cannot be bettered in the here and now, is its own justification? Even if it doesn't compare with that eternal,
impersonal love appertaining to the higher mystical state, who,
having experienced it, could possibly deny its legitimacy?
Isn't it a manifestation of divinity on earth
translated, as it were, into temporal terms, a physical parallel to
that
ultimate spiritual love which, in any case, only a comparatively small
minority
of people are ever fortunate enough to experience?
So why should one look down on it as upon
something reprehensible, something to be avoided? Why
indeed?
I suspect the answer to
this question could be traced to the nature of our modern
industrialized
society, with its priority on intellect, cold rationality, business
efficiency,
scientific rigour, and all those other materialistic factors peculiar
to a very
technology-dominated, urbanized lifestyle.
Having abandoned the soul-based world in close and regular
contact with
nature for our technological advances in large cities, we inevitably
turned
against the emotional life, indeed were forced to turn against it by
our
environmental transformations, and thus came to regard love as a
hindrance or
threat to our mounting intellectual bias, a powerful spokesman, as it
were, for
the life of the soul which we had abandoned and could no longer take
seriously. Tending increasingly in the
anti-natural direction of modern life, which puts an ever-stronger
intellectual
clamp upon our emotions, we see love as an unpleasant reminder of that
other
life from which we are in the process of escaping, a life centred on
and
governed by the soul rather than the intellect, and are consequently
inclined
to denounce it. Not all of us, of
course! But, still, a great number,
perhaps the majority who, consciously or unconsciously, relate to the
general
mechanistic tendency of the age.
Yet love, whether or not
we endorse it, remains a fact of life, and nothing we can do to
strengthen our
intellectual stranglehold on life can entirely eradicate it. Deep down we don't really want to eradicate
it anyway, for our essential being knows well enough that there is
nothing to
compare with it in the here and now, and how wonderful an experience it
can be
to really love someone with "all our heart", even when we are victims
of the head. But, superficially, in
terms of the intellect and what we are doing to ourselves and what
contemporary
society is doing to us, we are ranged against it, as against a powerful
adversary who may usurp the domain of our rational control. For the past two-hundred years the intellect
has been steadily gaining control over us, becoming increasingly
powerful and
autocratic. It has not, however,
succeeded in becoming the complete autocrat, nor, unfortunate
exceptions
notwithstanding, is it ever likely to. But its progress in that direction is by no
means insignificant, and what it has achieved it shows no intentions of
relinquishing. Goaded-on by our
industrialized society, it is now more powerful than ever before and
accordingly much less inclined to tolerate competition from the soul.
A very notable example
of the modern fear of the soul is afforded by Arthur Koestler's
suggestion, in Janus
- A
Summing Up, that science should develop a special pill which will
correct
what he alleges to be an imbalance between the old and new brains, thus
providing the intellect with greater power over the emotions. Apparently, the ostensible lack of proper
co-ordination between the two brains signifies a biological mistake
that should
be rectified if man is to survive, since, so the argument runs, the
emotional-bound old brain is responsible for most of our irrationally
destructive tendencies, not the least of which is war.
In light of my own argument, however, one
might question the assumption that the old brain is still as powerful -
and
therefore problematic - as formerly. For
the very suggestion put forward by Koestler
would
seem to betray an allegiance to the mounting imbalance in favour of the
intellect, rather than constitute a valid objection to emotional
tyranny. If we need to fear or curb
anything, it is
surely the growing power of the intellect!
For it is primarily this part of our "divided house", to cite Koestler, that is responsible for the
sophisticated weapons
of mass-destruction now at our disposal.
The intellect wants to
be the boss, but it fully realizes that when love enters the soul it
ceases to
be the boss, since love is more powerful than reason and soon dethrones
it from
its false position. Love unequivocally
reasserts the sovereignty of the soul over the brain, the essential
spirituality of life, and this it is loathe to accept.
For contemporary society is geared to
technological advancement, and for this it requires brain rather than
heart,
intellect rather than soul.
Thus love, when it
comes, is a subversive threat to that society, being in direct
opposition to
the materialistic principles for which it stands. Love
pulls
in the opposite direction to
intellect, back towards the soul, towards religion, art, nature, and
everything
else we have abandoned for what Spengler
calls 'the
Civilization', the modern materialistic epoch par
excellence. Love belongs to 'the
Culture', is the essence of 'the Culture', and therefore cannot find
favour
with 'the Civilization', which has set itself up against all that is
natural
and soulful. When love enters our hearts
it does so stealthily, like a thief in the night, come to rob us of our
prize
possession - the intellect. What to
cultural
people would have signified a gain, a further increase in spiritual
richness,
is seen by us as a loss, a return to antiquated circumstances. And yet, in objectively non-historical terms,
it is still very much a gain, the best temporal experience that can
ever befall
us, even if our intellects, our cocksure minds, persist in opinions to
the
contrary. As victims of the
intellect-over-soul perversion our industrialized society has inflicted
upon
us, we have little alternative but to view such an experience
back-to-front,
upside down, and inside out. Yet, for
all that, the experience remains essentially what it always was - a
temporal
manifestation of the eternal fact of Divine Love, a nourishment
imperative to
the life of the soul, and therefore not something detrimental to our
individual
wellbeing.
But how many people
genuinely experience true love these days?
How many people fall deeply in love with someone?
Is it not evident that a majority of people,
accustomed to the soul-denying conditions and routines of city life,
either
experience love in moderation, which is to say, in a weakened guise, or
not at
all? Is it not evident that the maimed
and stultified condition to which we have reduced our souls through
confinement
in artificial environments has generally robbed us of our ability to
love, our
desire to love? For true love must have
the right environment in which to flower.
It must be cultivated like a rare and delicate plant, nourished
in the
right soil. It cannot grow in an
infertile soil, one deprived of proper, regular, and sufficient
nourishment. But if our souls, as the
soil of love, are not only insufficiently nourished but maimed and
poisoned,
moreover, by the artificial environments in which we are obliged to
live, how
can they be expected to produce a passion worthy of the name love,
which will
endure for years with an intensity beyond mere infatuation?
Accustomed to what is
imposed upon them, our souls are unable to produce that flower of
flowers
which, in temporal terms, is their chief justification for being, but
are
reduced, instead, to the arid production of weedy sentiments, silly
infatuations, and empty pleasures which quickly bore or exasperate us. No wonder, then, that love becomes
increasingly suspect, and the tributes paid to it by sensitive poets,
novelists,
and musicians of the past appear to us as gross exaggerations of
romantic
sensibility! How can one know what real
love is with a sick soul, a soil (to return to our horticultural
analogue) in
which only emotional weeds and thistles can grow? How,
then,
can one be expected to take love
seriously? Away with all this nonsense
about the nobility and purity of love!
Down with all those sentimental fools who mistake their weeds
for
flowers! Let us make do with free love,
for at least that can be indulged in without sentimentality, without
the consent
of the soul, and, no less importantly, without emotional attachments! Who needs strings now that everyone can be
free to live and work as he pleases?
Away with all emotional attachments!
Thus speaks the voice of
'the Civilization', in which the intellect parades its victory over the
soul in
the guise of spiritual freedom. Love,
religion, art, nature: these are no longer relevant, no longer
meaningful. Only their substitutes will
now suffice, of
which sex is the most important. Sex is
love without a soul, and love without a soul is free love - in a word,
'fucking' or 'bonking'. Bodies are there
to be exploited, and the more bodies one exploits, or 'fucks', the
freer one
becomes. So one had better set to work
as quickly and ruthlessly as possible!
Eventually one may become so free that one can dispense with
bodies
altogether and either depend on what is left of one's imagination or,
failing
that, utilize pornography instead. And
after that, well, why do anything at all?
The truly free being ceases to live.
He becomes a machine.
Yes, unfortunately, the
modern definition of freedom does indeed point in that existential
direction. For the more we turn against
the soul in our preoccupation with the intellect, the more we abuse it
in our
technologically-dominated urban society, the more do we come, in
consequence,
to resemble the machines which are not so much our salvation as our
undoing as
human beings! (In this respect we
needn't be surprised if it transpires that never before have people had
such a
capacity for or ability to tolerate solitude as today.
For true friendship depends on the workings
of a properly-nourished soul, and the more the soul is starved and
maimed, the
less need we have of friends. Our
predilection for solitude is largely a consequence of this mechanistic
condition.) We make love like a machine,
like a mechanism that has been programmed to do a certain thing but to
do it
without any feelings, including feelings for the other person. Mechanical sex comes to replace love sex, and
the latter is looked down upon as something for which an enlightened,
emancipated humanity has no need. One
travels a lot faster without it. Indeed,
one needs to travel a lot faster because the loss of emotional
commitment has
to be compensated for by a greater physical commitment, by a more
frequent,
violent, and varied physical commitment to offset the tedium, as far as
possible, that sex without love inevitably entails.
It is the example of Van Norden
in Tropic
of
Cancer rather than Mellors
in Lady Chatterley's Lover which the industrialized world must
follow,
accustomed as it is to the domination of the machine.
And sex must not only be indulged in as often
as possible but, under the prevailing circumstances of our inability to
experience genuine love, be rendered as exciting as possible, which is
where
recourse to all manner of sexual stimulants, aids, aphrodisiacs,
perversions,
and fetishistic accoutrements comes in;
though no
amount or combination of them can ultimately compensate, it seems, for
the loss
of spiritual content which has made them necessary in the first place!
Alas, even with the most
up-to-date and erotic of sexual paraphernalia, mechanical sex remains a
very
inferior affair to love sex, and will doubtless continue to remain
such, no
matter what people endeavour to do to make it less so!
Deprived of the emotional raison
d'être which both enhances and ennobles sex, there will simply be
more and
more chaos, sterility, and absurdity in the sex lives of a majority of
modern
people who, having lost vital contact with their souls, are reduced to
the
level of beasts, to the level, one might say, of automata.
No wonder, therefore,
that marriage becomes an increasingly meaningless institution for so
many of
them. For what is marriage, after
all, if not a testimony to the bond of love which has sprung-up between
two
people and made them desirous of living harmoniously together and of
propagating their kind? There can be no
doubt as to the validity of marriage when the souls of the couple
concerned are
alive and well, and nourished on the most intense passion known to man. For how could either of the lovers possibly
tolerate being estranged from each other, or tolerate the intervention
of a
third party into their sex lives?
"What God has joined together, let no man pull asunder" reads
the matrimonial injunction. Yes, but
where true love is concerned, how could
any man
or woman not party to that love really be expected to pull it asunder? True love is its own master, against which
external physical forces are doomed to labour in vain, if labour they
dare. It testifies to the sovereignty of
soul over matter, a sovereignty which will remain unimpaired no matter
how many
other people the lovers may come into contact with or, no less
significantly,
how many miles should separate them.
Admittedly, if and when it subsequently wanes, there is perhaps
a
slender chance that the hitherto inseparable recipients of its bounty
may be
exposed to the temptation of infidelity or even of divorce. But whilst it remains at full-strength, so to
speak, there is next to no possibility of this happening.
Indeed, its duration should cover the period
of time sufficient for the propagation and rearing of offspring, after
which
there is no real need for its continuation in the same form or degree,
and no
real need for the establishment of other sexual relationships either. For sex, after all, centres around the
propagation of offspring, a duty which should use up a man's best years
and
take care of his sexual needs while they are at their strongest, which
is
compatible with the intensity of his love and the virility of his
physique. After this time has elapsed,
sex becomes progressively less important, less meaningful, and less
wholesome,
so that the formation of other sexual relationships is rendered
unnecessary, if
not downright ridiculous!
Such, at any rate, is
how matters stand between people who have known true love and found it
sufficient unto their needs. Strictly
speaking, there is no substitute for it, and the chances of one's
experiencing
it more than once or twice in life are, frankly, pretty slim. It isn't a phenomenon that is here today and
gone tomorrow, a brief interlude in one's life that may be sloughed off
at
will. On the contrary, it is a very deep
and lasting experience which cannot be replaced or repeated on a
regular
basis. One either loves deeply or not at
all. For how can an experience which is
intended to lead to propagation and the rearing of offspring possibly
be
shallow? How can one enter into the
difficult and responsible task of rearing a family on any but the
deepest, most
solid foundations? Is not love the very
justification for the production of offspring, the divinely-inspired
mediator
which guarantees the couple concerned that whatever they produce has
been
sanctioned and authenticated by its presence?
How, therefore, can one hope to produce anything worthwhile
without the
sanction of this mediator from 'On High'?
Truly, there can be few
greater misfortunes than to be born to parents who were not in love
with each
other! For how could the child of such
parents be legitimate, legitimate in the profoundest sense of the word? Even a child born out-of-wedlock would, I
contend, be relatively authentic if the couple responsible were deeply
and
genuinely in love. He might be
technically a bastard on the strength of his progenitors' unlawful
relationship, but he would still be more fortunate than a child born to
a
married couple who were no longer or had never really been in love, and
therefore weren't strictly justified in producing offspring. Whatever the physical strength or
intelligence of a person brought into this life 'illegitimately', in
the
absence of love, there can be little doubt that he will be a freak of
nature who
is likely to cause more trouble in the world than anyone sanctioned by
love. He may not be a spastic or a
victim of mental retardation, but he will certainly be unfortunate by
comparison with those whom God or nature or true love, as you prefer,
has provided
with an authentic soul. Perhaps it is
simply this fact that distinguishes the children of light from the
children of
perdition, of which the world is always composed in varying degrees? Whether one is of God's or the Devil's party
in life would seem to be determined from the moment of conception,
whether the
egg of a future child was fertilized through love or lust, soul or
flesh. Thus no amount of careful nurturing
subsequent to this moment could really transform the fundamental nature
of the
'illegitimate' child's soul, which would remain fundamentally what it
had been
fashioned as throughout the remaining years of his childhood and into
adulthood. For children inherit either
the graces or the sins of their parents, and the way they are brought
up is
likely to reflect this fact.
Consequently, the victim of loveless parents is unlikely, in any
case,
to receive the most loving of upbringings.
But any loving
upbringing, even one conducted in the humblest of circumstances, would
be
preferable to one in which love had not played a part, no matter how
wealthy
the parents may happen to be. There is
no substitute for genuine love, and, as such, there is no real
justification
for loving couples deciding to postpone a family commitment until they
can 'afford'
it. Unless they are without any means of
support whatsoever, they should take advantage of their feelings for
each other
while those feelings are at their peak, and thus produce offspring in
accordance with nature's prompting. For
what is the point of being in love with another person if one is not
intending
to start a family? One doesn't fall in
love simply for the sake of love. And
any procrastination of procreation is not only the thief of valuable
time, it
is a base concession to materialism, to the opinion that children
should only
be brought into the world at the dictates of the pocket rather than of
the
heart. Procrastinate too long - if
procrastinate one can - and the strength of one's love may be reduced
in
intensity to a very mediocre level, may even disappear altogether, so
that one
might subsequently be obliged to propagate in cold blood, as it were,
in a
context not altogether conducive to the formation of legitimate
offspring. For those who are in love but
do not take
full advantage of it to start a family are inevitably their own worst
enemies. The consequences of their
procrastination will be visited, if they subsequently decide to
propagate, on
their offspring and, through their offspring, on them personally.
But perhaps I have said
enough about the role of love in relation to happily-married
'traditional'
couples to permit me to return from the conventionally idealistic platform upon which I have stood, during the last
few
paragraphs, to one closer to the decadent realities of the present,
with its
lack of genuine love and consequent breakdown of marriage.
Ideally, then, one falls in love at the best
possible time in one's life in order to get married and have children. There is little need, as a rule, for divorce,
because the love is so intense that it keeps the couple together, even
after it
has waned and their children grown up.
Love fulfils a necessary function in maintaining the survival of
the
kind on as legitimate a basis as possible.
One is not properly mated until one is in love.
So far so good! We shouldn't
quibble with the laws of nature,
which testify to the workings of a higher mind.
They were not put there as a punishment but, rather, as an aid
to our
spiritual wellbeing.
However, even in times
more conducive to our essential wellbeing, it has to be admitted that
many
people weren't able to take full advantage of them.
Falling in love with someone isn't guaranteed
simply because one lives in close contact with nature.
One has to be fortunate enough to meet someone
with whom it is possible to fall in love, with whom the formation of a
life-long relationship is desirable.
Obviously, many people don't have that good fortune and
therefore have
to settle for something less, for a relatively loveless and
predominantly
sexual relationship such as would more likely result in the propagation
of
'illegitimate' offspring and the continuation, thereby, of unhealthy
souls. Judging by the God-bound nature
of our past culture, however, we may suppose that such 'illegitimate'
offspring
were formerly rather more the exception than the rule.
For it seems that love and marriage were
taken more seriously in the past than at present, because the soul of
Western
man, being in regular contact with nature, was in a much stronger
position to
experience true love then than now.
Consequently, such love flourished and marriage was upheld as a
sacred
gift, not to be treated flippantly or regarded as an unnecessary
imposition. Once the bond of love was
formed, it had to
be honoured. There could be no question
of divorce.
But, subsequently, with
the development of the industrialized society he inherited from the
nineteenth
century, Western man's capacity for love began to wane, in consequence
of which
the role and importance of marriage became questionable, and the
institution of
the family duly threatened. Cut off from
nature, his soul grew progressively weaker as his intellect mounted in
strength, imposing on his value-judgements an entirely new attitude to
love and
marriage, an attitude which we are only too familiar with in light of
our
cultural decline. For marriage rests on
the bond of love, and where that bond is weak or, worse still,
virtually
non-existent, it ceases to have any real significance.
Hence it must be disposed of, though not all
at once. There are stages to everything,
and the disintegration of marriage is no exception.
The restriction to small families, say, one
or two children, is a good beginning and leads, via extramarital
infidelities,
to divorce of an ever more frequent order, culminating, one can only
suppose,
in the demise of marriage altogether and a return to pre-cultural
patterns of
free love, or sexual relations akin to those of our very distant,
savage
forebears. For a
return to barbarism is the only possibility in store for a declining
civilization, and we are rapidly heading in that direction. Fortunately, we haven't yet entirely disposed
of marriage. One still finds people who
aren't completely destitute of love or the desire to have and raise
children. But it has to be admitted that,
under the
circumstances of our diminishing capacity for love, the number of
successful
marriages are steadily declining in proportion to the number of
unsuccessful
ones.
Indeed, it would seem
that we have now arrived at a point essentially the reverse of the
cultural
norm. For if the propagation of
'illegitimate' children, in the rather paradoxical sense in which I am
here
employing that term, was the exception in those centuries when Western
man
could love deeply and lastingly, it has now become the rule, as more
and more
children are brought into this world through parents who were unable to
love
each other or to love each other sufficiently deeply to keep their
marriage
together. The relative ease and
frequency with which so many modern marriages break up testifies to
this tragic
fact all too poignantly, and goes some way towards explaining why the
world is
becoming an increasingly meaningless and even hateful place in which to
live. For the children of light, the
children
whose souls were legitimized by the presence of true love in their
parents, are
growing fewer and fewer as the parental incapacity to love grows ever
more
firmly entrenched under the domination of our technological society,
which
continues to develop along lines inherently inimical to the soul. Small wonder that each generation tends to be
more violent, callous, and destructive than the previous one! That vandalism and juvenile delinquency
continue to mount! How could it be
otherwise, when love is becoming such a rare commodity, when the soul
has been
maimed to such a deplorable extent, that all but a minority of parents
are
incapable of achieving love and thus passing it on to their children? Alas, our age is so tragic that we don't even
comprehend the real nature or extent of its tragedy!
If we are not gulled by it, like most of the
liberal intelligentsia, we're more inclined to criticize and condemn
it, to
point out the absurdity or fundamental evil of so many of the
anti-social
activities in which various people regularly indulge, such as rape,
vandalism,
drug abuse, mugging, theft, etc., in a spirit which would suggest that
such
activities could be done away with, if only the people concerned would
change
their ways for the better.
Alas, if only they
could! If only it were possible for
people to transcend the materialistic influence of the environments
which
have imposed such absurd or evil
activities upon them, and thereupon revert to lifestyles and principles
akin to
those of their more fortunate ancestors!
Yes, if only! But, unfortunately,
it isn't possible, as anyone with any real intelligence must inevitably
realize. It isn't possible to discount
the detrimental influence of our industrialized and urbanized society
on the
health or strength of the soul, and accordingly expect people to behave
in a
more soulful and, hence, responsible manner, clearly able to
distinguish right
from wrong. It isn't possible for people
who were put into this world without genuine love to behave other than
in the
callous way they do. We must bear the
consequences of what we have brought upon ourselves, and the spiritual
consequences of large-scale severance from nature can be nothing if not
extremely grave.
Liars, fools, and
hypocrites will doubtless have their own opinions about this. But they are hardly opinions which anyone
with the slightest degree of moral integrity need be expected to take
seriously. The truth of modern life may
not be very flattering to our egos, but it is no less of a truth for
all
that! For, knowingly or unknowingly, we
live in an age which worships sterility, which has turned its back on
the life
of the soul in the name of the love-denying, soul-destroying forces of
the
city, and there is little we can now do to reverse the mechanistic
trend of
'the Civilization', to revert to Spengler
again. Love may not be completely dead but
it is
sadly on the wane, not, except in rare cases, entering our souls with
anything
like the same intensity as it did in the heyday, as it were, of 'the
Culture'.
Thus arises
the modern tendency to free love, to sexual promiscuity rather than
emotional
fidelity. And thus arises, too, most of
the sexual perversions of which our age is rife, including the
widespread use
of pornography. For what is pornography
but another indication of the triumph of the intellect over the soul,
the brain
over the heart, the mind over the spirit?
The intellectualization of sex, against which the
soulfully-oriented
D.H. Lawrence wrote so vehemently, is nothing more than a consequence
of our
technologically-dominated age, in which the intellect continues to grow
stronger at the expense of the soul and thereby, to cite Nietzsche,
"revaluate all values".
Needless to say, sex should not be a thing of the mind. But under the prevailing circumstances of our
mind-dominated civilization, one cannot be surprised if it should
increasingly
become so. And neither, curiously, can
one be surprised if pornography should paradoxically indicate the
triumph of
the body over the soul. For the
voyeuristic contemplation of photographs of nude bodies necessarily
rules out
soulful commitment, and simply testifies to Western man's growing
allegiance to
the merely physical aspect of things.
Like the practitioner of free love, the porno enthusiast can
indulge
himself in one body after another, one photograph after another of
different
models, because there is no emotional commitment, and therefore no
lasting
fidelity to any given female.
Unfortunately, so long as Western society continues to pursue
its
technological and industrial bent, there is unlikely to be a decrease
in
mind-oriented attitudes to sex. On the
contrary, we can only expect a rapidly growing allegiance to this
further
manifestation of anti-soulfulness, which also manifests itself in sex
films,
wherein the never-ending routines of mechanistic copulation continue to
hypnotize millions of sex-crazed eyes and to fill millions of vacuous
minds
with lurid images of sexual depravity.
If this is yet another example of free love, then it is the
freest
Western man has thus far evolved for himself - free love at a
voyeuristic
distance!
But there is, it must be
admitted, a more radical manifestation of the triumph of the intellect
over the
soul currently in progress in the world which, if it catches on (as
there seems
to be every chance of its doing), will doubtless hasten our downfall
and bring
about the total destruction of morality, or fidelity, in other words,
to the
preordained natural order of things. I
am referring to the idea, commonly associated with the latest eugenic
developments, of deposits of sperm - previously stored in deep-freeze
'sperm
banks' - from males with allegedly high I.Qs.
being introduced into the wombs of suitable
females via
artificial insemination, with the express intention of producing a
'master
race' of technological geniuses. If both
the donor and recipient are highly intelligent, then the offspring of
such a
procedure should, so the argument runs, also be highly intelligent, and
consequently better equipped to aid the nation or cause or whatever in
its
struggles against political, scientific, religious, or other external
threats.
Yes, we can see the
intellectual side of this argument plainly enough.
For it usually transpires that parents with
high I.Qs. produce
intellectually superior offspring. But
what of the spiritual aspect of the thing, the aspect we generally
prefer not
to consider these days but which still persists, like the dark side of
the
moon, in existing and exerting an attractive influence, no matter how
feeble or
perverted, upon us? Isn't it evident
that love is the determining factor in deciding the spiritual status of
a child
- whether it is legitimate or otherwise - and that, without love
existing between
the parents, there can be little hope for the spiritual authenticity of
the
child? Is it not therefore evident that
this latest eugenic strategy for producing higher intelligences can
only result
in the propagation of still more 'illegitimate' children, and children,
moreover, whose spiritual illegitimacy will be even more radical, if
anything,
than those who are currently the victims of 'conventionally' loveless
parents,
given the enhanced impersonality coupled to higher intelligence?
Truly, one shudders for
the future of humanity, a future in which an ever-increasing number of
moral
cretins will be let loose upon the world to further the Devil's cause
in
opposition to the spiritual needs of mankind!
For how can a woman who elects to accept a donor's sperm in such
an
impersonal manner possibly be expected to experience love for him, on
the basis
of the scant information conveyed to her?
And how can the donor be expected to feel love for the
recipient, whom
he may never even have seen, let alone met?
If we are given sufficient reason to feel concern over the
growing
difficulty which couples who live together generally have in
experiencing
genuine love for each other, how much greater reason do we have to feel
concern
over a strategy of propagation which takes this problem one stage
further away
from the individual and endows it with a collective impersonality one
stage
closer to the cold, mechanical aridity of Brave
New
World! Does it not seem that
Huxley's nightmare
vision of the future is becoming more of a reality every day,
especially now
that methods of artificial mating are being taken so seriously in some
quarters?
Alas, there would seem
to be little we can do to alter the direction in which we are heading! For we cannot now return
to
the centuries of soulfulness in which love and marriage flourished. Shut out from nature in our giant cities, we
can only press-on in the dismal course originally set for us by the
Industrial
Revolution and accept the destruction of traditional values as an inevitability. But
we
need
not pretend that sex-for-sex's sake or free love or pornography or
'sperm banks' or any of the other destructive aspects of modern life
which now
confront us in ever-more brazen guises mark an improvement on those
traditional
values which 'the Civilization' is denying us.
On the contrary, if we are perfectly honest with ourselves, and
courageous enough to face-up to the truth of the situation, we will
know only
too well that true love cannot be bettered, and that it is a real
tragedy of
our time that, unable to experience such love properly, so many of us
should be
obliged to regard it with superficial disdain.