Previewthe Centretruths eBook version of BETWEEN TRUTH AND ILLUSION
Op.
05
BETWEEN
TRUTH
AND ILLUSION –
A
Dualistic
Philosophy
Multigenre
Philosophy
Copyright
©
2011 John O'Loughlin
___________________
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION
PART
ONE:
ESSAYS ON A DUALISTIC
PHILOSOPHY
1.
The
Interdependence of Opposites
2.
The
Conflict of Opposites
3.
The
Necessary Illusion
4.
The
Legitimacy of Stupidity
5.
More
Positive than Negative
6.
Both
Positive and Negative
7.
Neither
Angel nor Demon
8.
No
Good without Evil
9.
Only
Partly Wise
10.
Perfect
or Imperfect
11.
Perfect
and Imperfect
12.
A
Necessary Doubt
13.
No
Sham Wisdom
14.
Only
Absurd Sometimes
15.
Not
Entirely Sane
16.
Not
Entirely Insane
17.
No
Happiness without Sadness
18.
Nothing
Superfluous
19.
Between Day and Night
20.
A
Mistake in Plutarch
PART
TWO:
LESSONS ON A DUALISTIC PHILOSOPHY
21.
Wisdom
and Folly
22.
Truth
and Illusion
23.
Good
and Evil
24.
Happiness
and Sadness
25.
Profundity
and Superficiality
26.
Certainty
and Doubt
27.
Reasonableness
and Unreasonableness
28.
Cleverness
and Stupidity
29.
Success
and Failure
30.
Pleasure
and Pain
31.
Love
and Hate
32.
Virtue
and Vice
33.
Strength
and Weakness
34.
Interest
and Disinterest
PART
THREE:
DIALOGUE ON A DUALISTIC PHILOSOPHY
35.
A
Dualistic Integrity
______________
INTRODUCTION
BETWEEN
TRUTH
AND ILLUSION signifies an attempt by me to return to
basics in philosophy and understand the connections and indeed
interrelations
of antitheses, polarities, opposites, and other such neat philosophical
categories in relation to the relativity of everyday life.
It is not an express attempt to expound the
Truth but, rather, a modest undertaking on my part to comprehend the
paradoxes
of the world in which we happen to live, and seek to unveil some of the
illusions and superstitions which make the pursuit of Truth such a
difficult,
not to say protracted, task. Hopefully
the result of this undertaking is a franker and maturer
approach to those very paradoxes which were the inspiration for this
work and
which led to some of its most striking contentions.
If BETWEEN TRUTH AND
ILLUSION cannot, by dint of its paradoxical nature, lay claims to being
The Truth,
it can at least be seen as the basis for a more realistic appraisal of
the
terms by which the pursuit of Truth is made possible.
John
O'Loughlin, 1977 (Revised 2006)
__________________
PART
ONE:
ESSAYS ON A DUALISTIC PHILOSOPHY
THE
INTERDEPENDENCE
OF OPPOSITES: Work and play, love and hate,
day and night, up and down, north and south, big and small, high and
low,
pleasure and pain, man and woman, sun and moon, yes and no, right and
wrong,
good and evil, health and sickness, in and out, hard and soft, hot and
cold,
old and new, war and peace, quick and slow, young and old, life and
death,
awake and asleep, rich and poor, tragic and comic, for and against,
truth and
illusion, etc.
The duality of life
would seem to be an indisputable fact, a condition not permitting any
serious
refutation. For what happens when we
isolate the word 'big', say, from the existence of its antithesis,
'small'? -
Simply that the word in question ceases to be meaningful.
By itself and totally isolated from the word
'small', our adjective is reduced to a sound, the simple basis of a new
word. We could speak of a big
bird, a big house, or a big garden but, not knowing
what 'big'
meant, we would be none the wiser.
Thus we can see how
absolutely interdependent the words 'big' and 'small' really are, how
they can
only serve a useful function when used in a mutual relationship. Once the polarities have been established,
however, it is then possible to conclude a bird 'big' in relation to a
speck of
dust but 'small' in relation to a man; 'small' in relation to a house
but 'big'
in relation to a moth, and so on.
It should therefore
follow that unless we accept the dualities of life as being
interrelated, part
of a larger whole, and even, in a limited sense, the key to the
metaphysical
nature of reality, we shall be perpetually deluding ourselves. In other words, without hate there can be no
love, without death no life, without sadness no happiness, without pain
no
pleasure, without evil no good, without illusion no truth, without
realism no
naturalism, and without materialism no idealism.
Thus it can be assumed
that a society which strives to remove what it regards as a detrimental
or
undesirable antithesis to a given ideal condition or concept ... is
inevitably
letting itself in for a lot of futile and pointless labour. A tolerable world isn't a place where things
don't go wrong or where conditions are always pleasant, people happy,
work
agreeable, and health unimpaired; for that, believe it or not, would
soon prove
to be quite an intolerable one. But in
order that people may
experience pleasant conditions, a degree of happiness, a sense of
purpose, and the joys of good health, a tolerable world will also
include
correlative experience of unpleasant conditions, sadness, absurdity,
and
sickness - to name but a handful of possibilities.
Hence when a person is
feeling sad, he ought to face-up to the reality of his situation by
accepting
its rightful place and thereby bearing with it as a sort of passport to
the
possibility of subsequent happiness.
Indeed, if he is something of a philosopher, and can
sufficiently detach
himself from his immediate sadness for a few seconds, he may even think
along
such lines as: 'Without this moment or hour of sadness, what happiness
could I
possibly expect today?' In doing so, he
will be acknowledging the validity of what might popularly be described
as a
means to a desirable end.
Naturally, I don't mean
to imply that people should
think like this when inflicted
with depressing circumstances, but simply that they should learn to
acquiesce
in their various uncongenial moods without vainly endeavouring to fight
shy of
them. For the trickery too often
advocated by people who foolishly strive to rid themselves of an
unhappy mood,
as though secretly afraid to 'pay their dues', strikes me as little
more than a
species of intellectual perversion. If
we were really supposed to lead one-sided lives, life would have been
considerably different to begin with, and it is doubtful that man would
have
conceived of the dual concepts of Heaven and Hell, concepts which, on a
more
concrete level, are clearly relative to life on this earth, and to a
life,
moreover, which prohibits man from ever dedicating himself to the one
at the
total exclusion of the other!
Therefore it can be
deduced from the aforementioned contentions that man's fundamental
nature is
typified by its capacity for experiencing seemingly contradictory
phenomena,
viz. happiness and sadness, good and evil, truth and illusion, which,
if he is
to do justice to both himself and his kind, should be accepted and
cultivated
according to his individual or innate disposition.
An author, for example,
who may well be 'great' by dint of the fact that he accepts himself as
a whole
man, should reconcile himself to the logical contradictions, cynical
statements, brash generalizations, callous accusations, superficial
appreciations, cultivated vanities, dogmatic assertions, etc., which
frequently
appear in his writings (and constitute manifestations of his negative,
or evil,
side), in order to safeguard his integrity as both a man and
a
writer.
THE
CONFLICT
OF OPPOSITES: My philosophy is neither optimistic nor
pessimistic but a subtle combination of both optimism and pessimism. Perhaps this respect for duality, this
acceptance of polarity, entitles it to be regarded as a metaphysics
drawn
primarily from life itself rather than imposed upon it by the whims or
perversions
of the human mind. Of course, its author
is aware that he may think optimistically whilst experiencing a good
mood and
pessimistically whilst in the grip of a bad mood. But
these
separate inclinations are well
suited to the purposes of this philosophy.
For example, if he
should one moment secretly pronounce, after the fashion of
Schopenhauer, that
life is inherently bad because there is too much suffering and not
enough
pleasure in it, he will subsequently reflect, when the time and mood
are
propitious, that his previous oracular pronouncement was largely
attributable
to the persistence of a bad mood and/or uncongenial circumstances; that
life
was only 'bad' because he had been in a negative frame-of-mind, had set
up a
chain of negative reactions and accordingly dismissed optimism in the
name of
suffering, thereby passing judgement in a thoroughly one-sided manner.
If, however, he should
sometime pronounce, after the fashion of Gide,
that
life
is inherently good and bubbles over with joy, pleasure,
intelligence,
etc., he will later reflect, doubtless when the time and mood have
shifted down
a gear or two, that his previous oracular pronouncement was largely
attributable to the prevalence of a good mood and/or congenial
circumstances;
that life was only 'good' because he had been in a positive
frame-of-mind, had
set up a chain of positive reactions and accordingly dismissed
pessimism or,
rather, affirmed optimism in the name of wellbeing, thereby passing
judgement
in a no-less thoroughly one-sided manner.
The claim that life is
therefore both good and
bad, according to the context of
the occasion or circumstances of the individual, is doubtless a
proposition
that most fair-minded people would be prepared to accept.
But to proclaim, like some philosophers, that
life is either good or bad is surely to misrepresent or slander it in
such a
way as to render oneself contemptible to the more realistic spirits of
this
world! Let it be hoped that we dualists
can see life on fairer terms than they did.
THE
NECESSARY
ILLUSION: Just as one must know one's truths if they
are to remain valid as truths, so one must remain ignorant of one's
illusions
if they are to remain illusions.
Whenever the spell of an illusion is broken one automatically
becomes
disillusioned, which is to say somewhat saddened by the realization
that what
one formerly took to be the truth wasn't really true at all but,
rather, a
misconception on one's part. Thus, by
way of compensation, the shattered illusion then becomes a kind of
negative
truth, in that one can now see through it and thereby establish a truer
opinion
on the subject. So, in a sense, one's
illusions are all sham truths until one becomes disillusioned.
But this realization,
this process of creeping disillusionment, doesn't automatically mean
that one
is steadily getting closer to absolute truth, that one is 'cutting
down' on
one's illusions and consequently converting the knowledge of their
fallacies
into relative truth while simultaneously safeguarding one's inherent or
acquired grasp of truth. For as
everything exists in polarity, so must the newly acquired
disillusionment
subsequently make way for other illusions which replace those one
possessed at
the time of becoming disillusioned with a particular illusion, in order
to
maintain the balance of opposites.
A philosopher who
categorically asserts his will to truth at any price, and thereupon
declares
himself to be the sworn enemy of illusion, is, unwittingly, the victim
of an
illusion which presupposes that truth can be acquired without a
constant
metaphysical price - namely of
simultaneously maintaining and acquiescing in illusions which must, of
necessity, enter into his work from time to time, thereby preventing
the
ultimate realization of his notably idealistic ambitions.
THE
LEGITIMACY
OF STUPIDITY: As each person retains his capacity
for truth and
illusion
throughout
life, so, likewise, does
each person retain his capacity for cleverness and stupidity. That this is a just condition hardly needs
proving; for were he not subject to the experience of both tendencies,
he would
have little or no prospect of maintaining either. Hence
his
illusion guarantees the continual
existence of his truth, his stupidity the continual existence of his
cleverness.
To lament, however, over
the realization that even one's favourite philosophers, novelists, and
poets
display periodic manifestations of illusion or stupidity is,
willy-nilly, to
display one's own illusion or stupidity, since these authors must also
be
subject to the metaphysical coercion of the human spirit and therefore
be
equally incapable of ultimately transcending its dualism.
Were a few of them to remain wholly
consistent with one's own mode of thinking, were even one of them to do
so,
there would surely be reasonable grounds for assuming that the
impossible had
come to pass, that one had come face-to-face with one's double and
somehow
acquired exactly the same truths and illusions as had previously been
recorded
by a man who hadn't so much as even suspected one's existence.
Consequently, it will be
no great surprise or hardship to an enlightened reader when he
eventually comes
to realize that his attitude towards each of his 'favourite' writers is
bound
to be ambivalent, to entail both agreement
and
disagreement, approval and disapproval, faith and scepticism. For as there has never been two people
exactly alike in the world, so it is inevitable that one man's meat
will
continue to be another man's poison.
Even the greatest
writers must, of necessity, be subject to the continuous prevalence of
antithetical
values, if they are to live as men and not degenerate into lopsided
monsters! The pernicious idea of
someone's being 'all too human' simply because he makes mistakes, acts
stupidly, suffers from ignorance, fosters certain misleading arguments,
etc.,
is clearly founded upon a superficial grasp of human reality (as though
the
person accusing another of being 'all too human' on account of such
failings
wasn't, in reality, 'all too human' himself for failing to detect their
ultimate legitimacy!). But being 'all
too human' is really an indication of human perfection rather than of
imperfection. For a man who never made
mistakes, never committed an illusion or absurdity to paper, would
be highly imperfect - a sort of computerized robot, and therefore no
man at
all!
MORE
POSITIVE
THAN NEGATIVE: If illusions are only illusions
insofar as man is basically unaware of their illusory nature, can it
not be
deduced from this that his real evil, stupidity, illogicality,
injustice,
etc.,
only come to the fore when he is basically unaware of the
fact, not when he wills it? In other
words, because the life-force is essentially positive, because
everything
arises in nature to fulfil itself, is not man's deepest inclination
likewise to
seek the positive rather than the negative, to aspire towards his
individual
truth, goodness, cleverness, profundity, logic, justice, etc. as an
inherent
inclination rather than towards their opposites which, being
negative, are
things that he is fundamentally unconscious of, i.e. in the sense that
one is
unconscious of an illusion until one becomes disillusioned with it?
Men aspire towards truth
while still besotted with illusions, towards goodness while still
fostered on
evil, towards social order while still subject to the chaos of their
individual
lives. They often think they are doing
the right thing when it subsequently transpires to being wrong; they
often
consider themselves to be acting justly when, to those upon whom they
have
acted, the consequences are manifestly unjust; they often imagine
themselves to
be doing good when, to those who are the recipients of their goodness,
the main
consequences are evil. It is only out of
ignorance that they act wrongly at all, but it is a necessary ignorance
which
ultimately transpires to being justified, a fact which may well explain
why the
dying Christ gave utterance to the words: 'Father, forgive them for
they know
not what they do', and why Nietzsche asserted: 'Man always acts
rightly'.
Thus man is largely
ignorant of his real evil, stupid, illogical, and superficial
tendencies
because his innate positivity generally
leads him to
treat every action as a good, no matter what its nature.
He doesn't attack others, whether verbally or
physically, simply for the pleasure of doing so but primarily because
he feels justified
in doing so, because, by a quirk of fate, context, experience, or
life-history,
he feels that to be the right thing to do under the prevailing
circumstances.
From the viewpoint of
the people he has attacked, however, his actions are almost certain to
be
condemned as evil. And for the very
sound reason that whenever someone acts cruelly to us it offends our
prevailing
sense of goodness, causes us to feel outraged, engenders negative
feelings, and
is automatically translated into an evil act.
Because it offends us we recognize it as an evil action,
instinctively
regard its perpetrator in a negative light, and straightaway succumb to
a
misconception, viz. that the aggressor is inevitably in the wrong. But even if it may appear so from our point
of view, this is insufficient to make it so from his and, consequently,
each
side acting according to their lights, the antagonism continues.
If, therefore, man
aspires towards goodness without ever becoming wholly good, whatever he
does
from ignorance or spite, wounded vanity or a sense of outraged
innocence, the
warrior impulse or self-defence, which can be interpreted as evil, can
never
make him wholly bad. And the same may be
held true of all the other polar attributes as well.
He will aspire to acquiring nothing but the
truth without ever freeing himself from illusions.
He will endeavour to boast of his cleverness
without ever managing to completely rid himself of stupidity. But let us not add to that stupidity by
bewailing the existence of these indispensable antitheses!
BOTH
POSITIVE
AND NEGATIVE: In speaking of antitheses we almost
invariably put the positive attribute first and the negative one
second, as the
following short list should serve to confirm: good and bad, truth and
illusion,
pleasure and pain, happiness and sadness, life and death, light and
dark, love
and hate, day and night, heaven and hell, man and woman, boy and girl,
rich and
poor, beautiful and ugly, high and low, yes and no, etc.
To say that man's nature is good would hardly
constitute the truth; for in order to have any goodness at all he must
have
sufficient evil from which to create it, he must have one tendency
balanced by
another.
Granted that man is
neither good nor evil but both good and
evil (which
should not be confounded with a combination of each), one can
nevertheless
assert that the positivity of goodness
generally
leads him to aspire towards the Good rather than towards its opposite
which,
being negative, can only take second place, as it were, to the 'leading
string'. Thus, as an inherently positive
phenomenon, life is geared towards goodness, but to a goodness which
can only
be maintained with the aid of evil.
Yes, Gide
was right to contend that man was born for happiness, in that man's
strongest
predilection is to aspire towards the positivity
of
happiness rather than towards the negativity of sadness.
Admittedly, this happiness ultimately depends
upon the intermittent prevalence of sadness.
But sadness can never become the 'leading string', or man's
principal
objective. For the essential positivity of our being does not induce us to
pine for
sadness when we are happy but, on the contrary, to immerse ourselves in
happiness as if it were a natural condition, as if we had found our
spiritual
home. And this same positivity
eventually goads us out of our sadness by causing us to pine for
happiness.
Now according to
Schopenhauer - who is virtually antithetical to Gide
- happiness is merely the absence of pain and thus a negative thing,
whereas
pain itself he saw as very positive, a thing upon which life mostly
depends. To follow Schopenhauer's
reasoning here isn't particularly easy, but it should be fairly
apparent to
most people that he was somewhat mistaken.
For as the accepted antithesis to pleasure, not happiness, pain
is
really anything but a positive thing, since we aren't driven by our
essential
being to pain but to pleasure, so pleasure must be the positive
attribute and
pain the negative one. Not being content
to muddle these antitheses, however, Schopenhauer also saw fit to
reverse their
qualities and thus invest pain with a positive attribute - a thing
hardly
guaranteed to enlighten one or advance truth in this respect!
So do I therefore advise
people against reading Schopenhauer? No,
I don't, since there is much value to be gleaned from a serious perusal
of his
major works, including The
World
as Will and Representation. What
I do advise people against, however, is
being put off philosophers like Schopenhauer on account of their
logical fallacies. There
is
not
a philosopher on earth who could escape criticism for one reason or
another, since there isn't one whose integrity as a human being exempts
him
from error. Where one believes the
contrary, it can be assumed that one has been deceived by the mistaken
assertions of the philosopher concerned without in the least suspecting
the
fact. No man is born to tell the whole
truth and nothing but the truth. Yet no
man is born subject to nothing but illusions, either!
A man who is prepared to
give his favourite philosopher's principal target of abuse (Hegel in
the case
of Schopenhauer) a fair hearing or reading would strike this
philosopher as
more enlightened than one whose willingness to do so has been severely
compromised, if not completely negated, by too slavish an adherence to
him.
NEITHER
ANGEL
NOR DEMON: We are neither angels nor demons but that
compromise between them which is called man.
It is as impossible to prevent man from doing evil as it is to
prevent
him from doing good. Even those people
who imagine themselves to be what D.H.
Lawrence
described as 'lopsided on the side of the angels' are undoubtedly
deluded in
supposing themselves to be wholly good.
How can anyone living in this world be wholly good when our
metaphysical
condition requires that we function according to the dictates of polar
influences, and not degenerate into some kind of moral eunuch hardly
capable of
killing a fly?
Indeed, when one
realizes that not even the saints can have been wholly good, what
chance does
anyone else have of eliminating their evil tendencies and thereby
transforming
themselves into something which transcends our physiological coercion
to accept
both good and evil as equally important, equally interdependent, and,
above
all, equally inescapable? One might as
well try squeezing a camel through the eye of a needle.
But how, then, do I
define good and evil? Simply
by
relating
that which proceeds from positive feelings to goodness and,
conversely, that which proceeds from negative feelings to evil. Thus a genuine smile is a good, a genuine
scowl an evil. Pleasure is good, pain
evil. Love is good, hate evil. Hope is good, fear evil.
Incidentally, one is
indulging in evil every time one complains about anything, since the
tendency
to complain inevitably engenders negative feelings: anger, resentment,
fear, or
hate. One drops a hammer on one's foot
and one experiences pain. Pain is a
physical evil which causes one to curse.
Cursing is the inevitable mental evil which results from pain. One's evil is justified.
NO
GOOD
WITHOUT EVIL: Just take a look at the history of
philosophy, at the number of philosophers from Plato to Kant who have
designated men as either good or evil without apparently realizing that
a 'good
man' or a 'bad man' can never exist, never, that is, so long as men are
compelled to conform to their individual standards of polar exchange,
which is
to say so long as they live.
Naturally, certain men appear
good
compared with lesser men, whose basic intellectual limitations, social
hardships, and poor breeding lead them to commit actions which a more
fortunate
individual could only condemn. But this
is far from saying that those greater men are not susceptible to evils
themselves, and to evils, moreover, which conform to their class,
occupation,
age, and physiological coercion as men.
No man can call himself
good simply because his higher intelligence, better standard of living,
and
finer breeding enable him to refrain from what might broadly be
described as
the evil tendencies of a lower class. It
is not enough simply to avoid torturing or murdering people, openly
ridiculing,
cursing, raping, or fighting them; for one can usually do that without
too
great a strain upon oneself if one is of a sufficiently independent and
noble
turn-of-mind.
No, to become a 'good
man' one would have to give-up reading certain books, say, murder
mysteries;
give-up listening to certain albums, say, hard rock; give-up watching
certain
films, say, horror videos; stop thinking certain thoughts, seeing
certain
people, taking certain sides, having certain beliefs, saying certain
things,
feeling certain emotions, dreaming certain dreams, indulging certain
fantasies,
etc., and one would have to give them up and/or or stop them to such an
extent,
to such a point of exclusivity, that there would be very little left
one could
do!
But would this drastic
strategy for the eradication of personal evil in one's life really make
one
good, holy, saved? No, it wouldn't! For if one could
get rid
of all one's evil inclinations, there would be nothing good to fall
back on,
there would be no good left within oneself, since one's good
inclinations only
thrive with the assistance of their opposites, not without them! One would simply exist in a manner
approximating to that in which certain Oriental sages have
traditionally
aspired to existing: neither a good man nor a bad man but effectively a
thing,
devoid of life, sitting under the branches of a tree all day with the
imperturbability
of a rock.
Thus wherever the
healthy tendency of a will to life is concerned,
there
must always be varying degrees of good and evil. Conversely,
wherever
the unhealthy tendency
of a will to antilife (death-in-life) is
concerned,
there can be neither good nor evil but an existence betokening death -
a sort
of blasphemy against life.
ONLY
PARTLY
WISE: The world has never produced a single 'wise
man', since the world is not geared to wise men but to men, who can
only be
wise with the aid of their folly. In
order for a man to be capable of wisdom at all, he must also be foolish. For unless he is, there will be nothing for
him to create his wisdom from, since he will lack the polarity that
guarantees
it. Even Nietzsche, wise man that he
seems to have been on various occasions, was also a fool.
Do you disbelieve me,
you 'wise' ones, you who grew out of folly?
No matter, your disbelief will reinstate it.
I am foolish, you are foolish, we are all
foolish, but because of this we are all intermittently wise as well!
Indeed, whenever I see
men aspiring to be wiser than everyone else, men who are usually afraid
to live
... from fear that they should somehow transgress their wisdom, I see
them for
the half-fools they really are. They
would even go so far, some of them, as to pretend to having acquired a
victory
over folly, which, in reality, would also be a victory over wisdom;
though
they, being such half-fools, couldn't be expected to know that!
But there you are: that,
in simple light-hearted language, is fairly typical of the human
condition, of
that very logical condition which induces us to be wise intermittently
rather
than permanently, so that, to revert to D.H. Lawrence again, we can
avoid being
at 'a perpetual funeral'.
PERFECT
OR
IMPERFECT: What, in the final analysis, is the chief
distinction between a perfect and an imperfect man?
Is any man perfect at all, or is human
imperfection the eternal rule, the condition to which all men must be
reduced
if they are to survive?
Some people would have
us believe in the moral imperfection of man as though it were an
indisputable
fact, one derived from his 'sinful' nature and consequent need of
salvation.
Others would contend
that man is mentally imperfect, and that his frequent mistakes,
stupidities,
superficialities, illusions, contradictions, deceptions, etc.,
emphasize this
condition all too plainly.
Yet others, probably a
minority, would contend that man is usually mentally perfect, but that
only a
small number of men are ever permitted to actually realize their
perfection,
the rest of mankind being reduced, through economic and political
tyrannies, to
a state of spiritual, moral, intellectual, and social deprivation.
Finally, there would be
those who, whilst acknowledging that man is usually mentally and
physically
perfect, would contend that some men are either born or become mentally
or
physically imperfect: that a person with a spastic body, a crippled
limb, a
mental disorder, or a heart disease is undoubtedly imperfect when
compared with
somebody whose body and mind are hale.
Yes, this latter case is
probably more relevant to most people living today than are any of the
others. But let us take a closer look,
if only from curiosity, at what these other cases are saying.
To begin with, the
church in virtually all of its denominational manifestations, though
especially
the Catholic one, believes quite emphatically that man is a sinful and,
hence,
imperfect creature. The clerical servants
of the church believe in the imperfection of man, in what they take to
be his
perpetual backsliding into sinful habits like sex and alcohol. Through regularly confessing these sins to a
priest, a man may secure forgiveness from God.
But, if he is to be logically consistent, he must confess
everything,
not forget to mention anything or allow himself to overlook something
which he
might foolishly regard as trivial and therefore hardly a sin at all. For God, being omniscient,
can still see into his mind and will know if there was anything which
should
have been confessed to but which, for one reason or another, was
overlooked.
However that may be,
both the Catholic and, to a lesser extent, the Protestant clergy
believe in
man's imperfection and, thus, perpetual need of redemption. They have, it seems to me, a somewhat partial
view of man. They do not want to accept
him in the round but only in the part, with particular reference to his
'sinful
nature'. For if they once accepted the
dualistic integrity of man, their conception of his imperfection could
soon
dissolve under pressure of the following fact - namely that man can
only be
good because
of his intermittent evil, since his
sinfulness, whatever form it may take, is fundamentally the sole
guarantor of
his goodness.
But such an acceptance
of man's whole nature would not be to the lasting advantage of the
clergy! For if a man's good actions (those
stemming
from positive feelings) are fundamentally dependent upon the periodic
manifestation of his evil actions (those stemming from negative
feelings), how
can one possibly maintain that he should strive to eradicate as many of
the
latter as possible or, alternatively, confess what wrong he has done in
order
to be forgiven? Undoubtedly a ticklish
problem for the clergy to address, particularly since their
justification as
priests largely depends upon the contrary idea which, if pushed far
enough,
tends to divide a man against himself, making him hostile towards his
dual
nature.
However, it is not for
us humble philosophers to attempt to change their views, since that
would
certainly be to overlook the power of tradition and entrenched dogma. As a freethinker living in a country which
permits free thought, I shall simply put my case before the public
tribunal and
pass on.
Which leads me to our
second conception of man's imperfection - namely to the assumption that
his
periodic mistakes, stupidities, superficialities, contradictions, etc.,
are all
clear examples of it. Indeed, it is not
only clergymen who maintain this belief, but people from just about
every walk
of life. If they are figure clerks, then
a wrong addition or misplaced numeral is obviously, if regrettably,
another
instance of human imperfection. If they
are teachers, then an inability to trace a certain date, name, or
reference in
their memories may subsequently lead them to draw similar conclusions,
though
not in front of the class! If they are
philosophers, the assertion of a particular contention that they
imagined was
true, but which subsequently transpired to being false, will probably
trigger
off a similar barrage of self-condemnation.
In truth, the numbers of possible instances are endless, though
they all
point in the same direction - namely, the assumption that our
respective mistakes,
failings, delusions, etc., are conclusive proof of human imperfection.
But is man a computer,
we may object, that he should be exempted from error?
Is his evolution directed towards some future
mastery of himself, some grand epoch when the likelihood of a wrong
addition, a
memory failure, or a fallacious contention will be rendered impossible? If so, then I must confess to having serious
misgivings about man's future! I can
well appreciate his use and development of computers, but I do not
believe that
he should subsequently become computerized as well!
If a man makes
occasional mistakes, then let us at least have the insight to assume
that he
didn't commit them on purpose (for no genuine mistake can be made
intentionally) but, rather, that they happened in accordance with a
deeper law
of his being, which effectively proclaimed the justification of an
occasional
mistake as a means of maintaining his overall efficiency and general
ability to
avoid making mistakes at certain other times.
And the same may be held
true, I suspect, of his many other failings, each of which exists
primarily to
protect and maintain his overall efficiency.
So I do not believe that a man should necessarily be classified
as
imperfect because he makes mistakes from time to time.
Classify him imperfect if he never makes
mistakes, has no faults, is without stupidity, superficiality,
illusion, or
contradiction, if you like. But the
condemnation of his natural condition is something of which I do not
see the
sense.
However, let us now
progress to the third possibility which, as we saw earlier, concerns
the
alleged perfection of the Few and the imperfection of the Many. To some extent, it is of course fair to
suggest that most people are crushed or moulded by fate into a
particular way
of life which can only be described as constrictive.
They may be obliged to earn a living in
uncongenial circumstances. Their health
is gradually undermined, their imagination becomes increasingly
circumscribed,
their senses are dulled, their intellect becomes progressively more
stultified,
their opinions become stereotyped, their spirit atrophies, and their
willpower,
initiative, and self-confidence sustain an irrecoverable loss. Yes, it is probably fair to suggest that
these sorts of misfortunes have befallen a great many people; though it
is
probably also fair to suggest that a majority of them don't seem to
worry very
much about it. After awhile they take
their condition for granted, not really being in a position to do much
else.
Indeed, for some people
stultification of one degree or another isn't at all a bad thing; at
least it
prevents them from worrying or suffering too much in consequence of an
acute
awareness of their deprivation. But, for
others, it is virtually the end of the road, a ghastly horror from
which they
recoil, as from a poisonous snake.
Probably no-one can escape a certain amount of intellectual
stultification, dulling of senses, atrophying of spirit, etc., even
under the
best of circumstances. Yet there are
those who regard such a prospect or actuality with great dismay, much
as though
people were thereby rendered imperfect and consequently unable to live
as they
should. It is a great evil of society,
they claim, that so many people should be crushed down for the sake of
a
minority who are enabled to live to the maximum of their ability. It isn't right, they say, that a majority of
people should be compelled to live a sort of living death for the sake
of a
privileged few.
Undoubtedly, this is the
kind of viewpoint one would ordinarily associate with certain types of
communist revolutionaries and social agitators.
But I cannot personally grant it much credence.
It seems to me that those who think like this
are insufficiently aware of the temperamental, social, psychological,
and
intellectual differences between people.
A person who does what you or I might regard as a dull job isn't
necessarily worse off than one whose job is more exciting.
It depends entirely upon the nature of the
person concerned. For if one isn't very
intelligent to begin with, then a dull job is not only the best thing,
it is
the only
thing, and anything else would be unsuitable. But
if
one is
pretty
intelligent to begin with, then, conversely, a dull job would be
unsuitable. Now one cannot seriously
contend that a person born to a dull task has been deprived of an
opportunity
to realize his perfection through, say, one or other of the fine arts,
higher
sports, or professions, when it wasn't given him to realize his
perfection in
that way. Yet this is precisely what
certain communist revolutionaries and social agitators are apt to
overlook,
whether intentionally or unintentionally, when they speak in terms of
social
inequality.
Frankly, one cannot
really contend that a majority of men must lead imperfect lives for the
sake of
a lucky few, when the lives they lead are the only possible ones that
they
could lead anyway. Is a man to be pitied
because he wasn't born with the potential of a poet, musician, writer,
artist,
or philosopher when, by accident or design, he was born with the
potential of a
carpenter, builder, plumber, tailor, or car mechanic instead? Would you demand of car mechanics that they
become playwrights in order to realize their perfection to the full,
irrespective of the fact that they may prefer being car mechanics and
can
better realize their
perfection in that way?
No, nobody but the most
unreasoning of persons would demand any such thing!
For there are as many ways of realizing one's
perfection as there are people, and what would suit one type of person
could
well prove the ruination of another.
So I do not believe that
people who are unable to discover themselves in the more creative or
authoritative spheres of life should be considered unfortunate for
having to do
comparatively mundane or servile things instead. Each
man
has his own problems to live with,
whether he be a king or a beggar. Indeed, there is at work in this world a vast
levelling process which adds something here only to subtract something
there,
which renders every
occupation, no matter what its nature, subject to certain
drawbacks, limitations, or hardships, and no-one in his right mind
would really
pretend otherwise, no matter how unfortunate he thought he was, or how
many
uncongenial experiences accrued to his particular occupation. Even in the most boring office jobs one may
be able to converse with one's fellow workers on occasion - a thing an
artist,
writer, philosopher, or poet is seldom if ever in a position to do,
bearing in
mind his solitary circumstances. But
even boring work is better than no work at all, and most people would
rather be
bored at work than bored or, worse still, lonely and without purpose
from being
out of work.
Thus, in returning to my
original theme, I do not agree with the notion that society requires a
large
percentage of imperfect men in order that a small percentage of the
total
population should be able to develop their potential to the full and
thereby
realize their perfection. Where a man is
insufficiently intelligent or talented to do a highly skilled or
responsible
job, he has absolutely no business doing it.
Where, on the contrary, he is sufficiently intelligent
or
talented, then he will do his best to get himself accepted for it and,
eventually, he will probably succeed.
Whether he becomes a bookbinder, a sculptor, doctor, judge,
architect,
or novelist, whatever he does will be right for him.
There could be no question of coaxing him out
of it. For if all men
were born to do the same thing, the world would collapse in no time. A few billion artists would spell the
ruination of art, a few billion doctors the ruination of medicine, and
nobody
would be able to realize or even discover his perfection at all.
But that a man should
consider himself a failure because he is not a poet or an artist or a
musician
... is as stupid and illogical as, for the sake of argument, it would
be for a
tortoise to consider itself a failure because it is not a hare, or a
mouse to
consider itself a failure because it is not a cat!
Let a man do what he can do as well as
possible, let him live according to his capacity, and he will soon
discover his
true worth. A person can be as satisfied
in the humblest or lowest-paid job as dissatisfied in the most exalted
or
highest-paid one. It entirely depends
upon the nature and circumstances of the person concerned.
But let us now leave the
above aspect of the problem and turn, finally, to the more obvious
criterion of
perfection and imperfection: the difference, namely, between a person
with a
sound, healthy body and mind, and one, by contrast, who is afflicted
with some
serious mental or bodily deprivation.
Here we do touch upon the essential distinction, the glaring
inequality,
between the normal and the abnormal, the healthy and the sick.
The instances of human
imperfection are numerous, but they all revolve around severe mental or
physical anomalies. Schizophrenia,
mental retardation, and various forms of advanced insanity are typical
of the
former; blindness, deafness, deformed or crippled limbs, obesity, and
various
internal malfunctions are typical of the latter. But,
whatever
the anomaly may happen to be, there
lies the basis of human imperfection. It has nothing whatsoever to do with 'sinning
against the Light' (unless, however, one's 'sins' are of such a grave
and
frequent character that there is a strong justification for regarding
them as
the direct consequence of some mental or physical disorder). Neither does it have anything to do with
making mistakes (unless, however, one does little else).
Still less does it have to do with the type
of work one does (unless, however, one would rather not do any work at
all and
simply rot away in sordid isolation).
No, the phenomenon of human imperfection is always chiefly
characterized
by such anomalies as those to which I have referred, never or rarely by
anything else. For if
you are reasonably sound in body and mind, you are as perfect as you
need to
be. And a 'perfect man' isn't
usually the exception; he is the rule!
PERFECT
AND
IMPERFECT: You claim, my critical reader, that we are
not perfect because we make mistakes, commit stupid acts, suffer from
ignorance, succumb to the flesh, make war on others, twist truth into
illusion,
condemn others for things we sometimes do ourselves, fail to live up to
our
ideals, give way to sloth, contradict ourselves, forget what we ought
to have
remembered, and remember what we ought really to have forgotten. Why, then, do I pretend otherwise?
But I don't pretend, I know
otherwise.
I know, for example, that one cannot be good without also,
though at
other times, being bad, since one's goodness depends upon periodic evil
(irrespective of the fact that one may often be quite unaware of
exactly what
this evil is or what form it takes). I
know,
too, how important stupidity is in maintaining my intermittent
cleverness, how
profundity only thrives because of superficiality, wisdom because of
folly,
truth because of illusion. Without my
body I would have no spirit, and without food for this body my spirit
would be
sorely troubled; in fact, it would be sickly preoccupied with my body,
and
then, in a sense, I would be quite imperfect.
For spirituality only thrives with the aid of its opposite, not
without
it!
Oh, you say, but there
are ugly people, retarded people, spastic people, crippled people,
stunted
people, blind people, and many other kinds of unfortunate people who,
even
given your questionable criteria, are anything but perfect. What do I say to that?
Yes, I reply, you are
right. And that is precisely where real
human imperfection lies. It isn't so
much in what one does as in what one is.
A hunchbacked dwarf, for example, is clearly quite imperfect by
normal
standards, as is a cripple, a deaf-mute, or a spastic.
We are usually somewhat disturbed by the
imperfections of an ugly face or, alternatively, of a face covered in
sores,
boils, pimples, scars, etc., and, to be perfectly honest with
ourselves, we
have every reason to feel disturbed.
But, since most of us have some failings along these lines,
since most
of us can point to some physical malady or deformity which regularly
troubles
us in life, is it not evident that a majority of us are both perfect and
imperfect,
and that our perfections, far from being completely independent of our
imperfections, are dependent upon them for their continuous
participation.
But now I am confusing
you, I hear you object. First I speak of
human perfection, then of imperfection, and finally, to complicate
matters
still further, of perfection and
imperfection. Surely there is a
contradiction here? Surely there is some
fundamental misconception here?
No, not at all!
For if we have to pay for our truths with the
coinage of illusion, can it not be contended that, except in those
above-mentioned unfortunate instances where physical imperfection is
too
severe, our overall spiritual integrity, or perfection, must likewise
be paid
for with the coinage of physical imperfection, whether this
imperfection be
internal or external, transient or permanent, of the brain or of the
body? If one man has an ugly face, another
may have
a handsome one riddled with spots, boils, sores, etc.
If one man is short-sighted, another may be
long-sighted. If one man has greasy
hair, another may have greasy skin. If
one man suffers from his lungs, another may suffer from his heart. If one man is too thin, another may be too
fat, and so on and so forth. The
instances of physical imperfection are many, but they all seem to point
in the
same direction - namely the overall integrity of the spirit.
According, therefore, to
this contention we are both spiritually perfect and physically
imperfect. When one is both
clever
and stupid, wise and foolish, profound and superficial, logical and
illogical,
etc., one is spiritually whole, integrated, perfect!
When, however, one contemplates the anomalies
of the body (of which the brain is effectively a part), it is patently
obvious
that, in a majority of cases, the body isn't perfect.
For short-sightedness, B.O., greasy skin,
obesity, boils, warts, moles, cysts, sties, headaches, bone diseases,
bladder
trouble, and the thousand-and-one other things which constitute
physical
imperfection can't exactly reflect the same kind of integrity as is to
be found
in the duality of the spirit, and so, not being able to establish the
body's
perfection by the very fact of their existence, these imperfections
must
indirectly contribute to the perfection of the spirit as the legitimate
polarity to it.
So a 'perfect man'
should be one whose physical imperfections contribute to his overall physico-spiritual integrity, rather than one
without any
imperfections at all. It is only when
his physical imperfections are of such a magnitude as to detract from
his
overall physico-spiritual integrity - as,
for example,
in the case of spastics - that one is really justified in regarding him
as
'imperfect'.
A
NECESSARY
DOUBT: When a person says: 'We can have no
certainties, no-one can be certain about anything', he is unwittingly
displaying his tendency to illusion, ignorance, and stupidity. For were he not inclined to this kind of
self-deception, he would know that certainty and doubt are
antithetical, that
the one cannot exist without the other and, consequently, that there must
be a
degree of certainty in the world.
When I say: 'Mr Smith is
a man and Miss Brown a woman', I am absolutely certain about the nature
of
their respective genders. Even if I
didn't possess the concepts 'male' and 'female', I could still be
confident that
they looked fundamentally different, and that would constitute a
certainty. Similarly, when I say: 'The
sun provides the heat and light upon which the survival of natural life
on this
planet so heavily depends' I am again expressing a certainty. Were I to call it a doubt, other people would
have sound reason to consider me mistaken.
But there are, of
course, things about which it is impossible to be certain, like changes
in the
weather, who we will bump into on the pavement, what we will dream in
our
sleep, where we will be in ten years' time, how much money we will
waste over
the next six months, and so on. The
doubts we have about these 'uncertainties' effectively enable us to be
'doubtless' about the various certainties about which it is absolutely
imperative to be certain. Otherwise one
may eat the poison berry.
NO
SHAM
WISDOM: This philosophy would indeed be vain, stupid, and
meddlesome if, instead of putting me on the path to enlightenment, it
goaded me
towards a refutation of our natural tendencies, i.e. of being stupid,
deluded,
illogical, unjust, sad, evil, presumptuous, superficial, etc., when the
need or
inevitability of such tendencies was indisputably manifest. For me to set out on the path of endeavouring
to eliminate whatever idiosyncratic predilections for folly I may
possess would
be the height of folly! To imagine
myself on the road to profundity by making an earnest endeavour to
eliminate
what superficiality I may possess would likewise constitute a similar
absurdity, making me superficial rather than profound.
If knowledge is to serve
any useful purpose, it must free me from the constricting prevalence of
false
wisdom, render me increasingly aware of the obligations imposed upon a
healthy
life, and lift me above the intellectual fog invariably engulfing the
technical
nature of wisdom, morality, religion, politics, art, truth,
metaphysics, etc.,
which blinds so many people to the essence of reality.
It is all very well for a man to seek wisdom,
to require of philosophy that it teach him how best to live. But if that wisdom subsequently conflicts
with his deepest predilections as a human being and thereby transpires
to being
little more than a caricature of wisdom, a metaphysical
misunderstanding, an
inversion of terminology, a mere shadow play, a medicine where there
was no
sickness or, worse still, a sickness where there had been no
ill-health, then
it were better that he dispensed with philosophical formulae altogether
and
learnt to follow his natural inclinations again - the very inclinations
which,
in the final analysis, constitute the real sagacity of life.
ONLY
ABSURD
SOMETIMES: There are certain modern philosophers and
writers, not least of all from the so-called 'existentialist' school of
thought, who regularly conspire in contending life to be absurd and,
consequently, an imposition one would be better off without - a
contention
which does, in fact, engender sympathetic connotations when, under the
prevalence of various 'trying' circumstances, one genuinely feels
oneself
to
be
plagued by a farce and secretly longing for oblivion.
Regardless, however, of
the periodic validity and current prestige of this philosophy, it
nevertheless
occurs to me that one doesn't normally feel life to be absurd when, for
example, one settles down to listen to some choice record, read a
highly
engrossing book, eat a savoury meal, drink a delightful drink, watch an
exciting film, sleep an eventful dream, ponder a selection of
enlightening
thoughts, kiss a pretty woman, or take a well-earned rest.
For the mind is usually too preoccupied with
what one is doing at such times to be in any way seriously concerned
with the
then-largely irrelevant notion of absurdity.
As a standing maxim, one might conclude that when one is
content, the
notion of absurdity is strictly taboo!
But life does, however,
seem absurd sometimes and, whether or not we like this fact, it is
probably
just as well. For without the
intermittent prevalence of absurdity, how could one possibly be
expected to
take pleasure in life's reasonableness?
Without absurdity, there would doubtless be no reasonableness,
just as
without illogicality there would be no
logic, without
illusion no truth, and without sadness no happiness.
A book dedicated to the hypothesis of an
absurd existence would appear to be a somewhat one-sided and
essentially absurd
book. Indeed, it might even suggest a
distinct tendency, on the part of its author, to incorrect living!
NOT
ENTIRELY
SANE: Our sanity depends upon the regular support of
insanity. Why, you may occasionally
wonder, do we act as we do, rarely bothering to consider the essential
nature
of so many of our activities, but mostly pursuing them as though
blinded to
their consequences, unaware of their 'actualities', of how strange,
diverse,
and persistent they usually are? Clearly,
because we are insane as well as sane, because it is natural for us to
exploit
our insanity in the interests of our sanity, our unconscious mind in
the
interests of our conscious mind. How on
earth could we dare to call ourselves 'sane' in the first place,
without its
antithesis to support us and grant our sanity a reliable foundation? How could there possibly be
any sanity
in any of us, without the aid of its opposite?
A 'sane man' per
se can never exist.
Why, then, do we
classify certain people as insane if, to a certain extent, we are all
mad? Simply because we
are
largely ignorant of the matter? Possibly. But, more
probably, because we habitually associate insanity with notions of
incompatibility, irrelevance, superfluity, extreme eccentricity, unrelatedness, ostracism, delusions of grandeur,
etc. A person who talks to himself is
generally
considered mad because custom and common sense normally prohibit us
from
following suit, since it would make us conspicuously anomalous in a
world where
most people talk to others. When a man
persistently talks to himself in public places he not only draws
attention to
himself, whether compassionately or critically, but he makes it
difficult for
other people to communicate with him.
Thus he is regarded as a madman for having employed his
sanity/insanity
relationship in a manner deemed to be incompatible with society's
requirements,
instead of keeping it moored to an established norm like normal
conversation,
thinking, reading, writing, humming, whistling, etc., according to
accepted
standards of procedure. Yet the man who
talks to himself is probably no 'madder' than the one who thinks to
himself;
his 'madness' is simply more conspicuous on account of its audible
nature,
which might well indicate that the 'madman' in question is simply more
extrovert or less intellectual than the habitual thinker.
However, as for those
who generally do their best to 'keep in line' and remain fairly
consistent with
society's demands and standards, which includes the great majority of
people,
we shall continue to regard them as 'sane' without entirely believing
it. For if they are to remain sane in the
world's
eyes, they must continue to cultivate their insanity as before, i.e. by
taking
things more or less for granted and keeping uncritical track of social
requirement, as effecting and pertaining to both themselves and society
in
general.
As a sort of
afterthought to the above, it ought to be clearly understood that
insanity (as
represented here by an unusual arrangement of the normal duality) and a
mental
breakdown are two entirely different things, since a mind which
literally
ceases to function - as in the cases of Baudelaire, Maupassant, and
Nietzsche -
should not be confused with a mind which continues to function, albeit
in a
highly personal and irregular way - as in the cases of Swift, de Nerval, and Pound.
NOT
ENTIRELY
INSANE: What is
a 'madman'
if not a being whose sanity/insanity duality has ceased to be of any
use to
society and become a hindrance rather than an aid? That
we
are all mad to some extent is, I
trust, a proven if not self-evident fact.
For even the most heroic of us are regularly susceptible to
delusions, illogicalities, stupidities,
idiosyncratic anomalies,
obsessions, fears, perversions, passions, exaggerations, uncritical
obedience,
irrational conformity, etc., which rarely fail to puzzle or startle us
when we
regain our critical discernment.
Fortunately, however, we
usually learn to live with our individual oddities, just as we learn to
live
with their several manifestations in other people's lives, to regard
them as a
fact of life, to forget about them whenever possible, and to get on
with our
daily tasks not only as a means of securing a living and keeping
ourselves
preoccupied, but also of regulating our actions and keeping ourselves
on the
rails, as it were, of society's track.
The three things one doesn't do is to question their validity,
worry
about their consequences, or set about trying to regulate them in a
manner
guaranteed to disturb the natural polarity of sanity/insanity within. Living with the brakes on is like driving a
car too slowly and carefully. Sooner or
later there may well be a serious accident and a screaming neurotic
will be
dragged out from where, previously, there had been a stable, healthy
and normal
human being.
What, then, is
this
person who no longer is of any great use to society but must be kept
under
regular supervision or, alternatively, left to fend for himself
in a world where, at best, he can only expect to do very menial jobs? Is he someone who is all insanity and no
sanity, someone who has tipped the polar balance so far in favour of
insanity
that little or no sanity remains discernible?
Could any man be all of one thing to the total exclusion of its
opposite
under any
circumstances, that is to say under any permanent as opposed to
transient circumstances? No, I do not
believe so! For to be
all of one thing would be to destroy it, to cancel the polarity and
thereby
render the remaining side without definition, substance, or reality as
an
integral component in a dual relationship.
Thus if, as generally
understood, madness is essentially a question of degree, it is by no
means a
total obliteration of sanity but, rather, an expression of the basic
duality in
a manner deemed to be incompatible with average standards of behaviour. This, I believe, suffices to explain why
those deemed to be insane are usually unaware of their madness, take
matters
for granted, and are more inclined to consider others insane by their
standards
than to accept the standards which have been imposed upon them by
society at
large.
Consequently, to remain
sane in society's eyes one must play the game as broadly understood by
the
majority, no matter what that game may happen to be, in order to remain
intelligible within the confines of a given context and thereby pass
muster as
a being related to others. A surrealist
painter will be considered sane so long as he continues to function
efficiently
within his particular sphere of creative activity and doesn't foolishly
encroach upon other, unrelated spheres.
He may, for example, paint pictures of elephants with telephones
on
their heads, women with moustaches, beetroots with legs, or mice
wearing pyjamas. But as soon as he
seriously contends that
people should dress their pet mice, bankers order telephones for lunch,
or
office clerks stand on their hands all day instead of doing any work,
he is
likely to be judged insane for having stepped out of his professional
line and
made a public nuisance of himself.
Now if it is perfectly
natural to refer to a man who talks to himself or insults strangers in
the
street as a 'madman', it nonetheless ought to be understood that, in
the final
analysis, there is really no such thing as a mad man, any more than
there is
really such a thing as a sane man, a good man, an evil man, a happy
man, a sad
man, etc., since men are always a tension of polarities, a
meeting-point of
opposed though mutually interdependent tendencies, and therefore cannot
be
wholly one thing or another. Naturally,
we are compelled to simplify things, to define them in a way that will
be
intelligible to the vast majority of people at any given time. But from a philosophical standpoint, wherein
the mind is determined to make a conscious effort to get to the bottom
of
things, such pragmatic simplifications afford us a worthwhile vehicle
for
analysis - indeed, constitute the very justification behind our
attempts, as
philosophers, to investigate life in a more detailed, resolute,
sincere, and
profound manner. Consequently, we must
not take them at face-value, like the majority of people, but should
concentrate on digging beneath the objective surface of life, if only
because
we are intent upon 'unearthing' some unique revelation, lifting it
clear of
obscurity, and thereupon exposing it to rational investigation.
Now just as we contended
that a man cannot be wise without also possessing a degree of folly, so
we also
contend, in inverting our thesis, that he cannot be mad without
possessing a
calculated degree of sanity, since a mad man per
se is
more a figment of the imagination than a genuine reality.
NO
HAPPINESS
WITHOUT SADNESS: On the subject of happiness, I
believe John Cowper Powys, the exponent of what has been called 'elementalism', makes a serious mistake in
regarding
thoughts as highly as he seems to, both with regard to the struggle
against
sadness and the cause of its outbreak in the first place, as defined,
for
example, in The
Art
of Happiness, one of his most accessible books.
For is it not regularly the case that a
person feels sad without having particularly gone out of his way to
think
himself into it, or to involve himself in hostile circumstances. That he feels sad simply because our
metaphysical condition as men requires a degree of
sadness, in
order that we may remain integrated as human beings?
Now if this is so, how
much more so is it the case when a person feels sad because he has a
damn good
reason to, since he can point to the fact that the weather is
depressing, or
his financial circumstances are unfavourable, or his health is poor, or
his
hopes on a particular subject have been dashed?
Yet in a world where dualities, disparities, conflicts, and
tensions are
the very stuff of life, it would seem plausible to contend that sadness
plays
as legitimate a part in the birth of happiness as happiness in the
death of
sadness, and that we can no more aim for the one at the total exclusion
of the
other ... than hope to stay awake without getting any sleep!
Instead, therefore, of
waging an all-out war on sadness, as some people would seem only too
foolishly
inclined to do, would it not be wiser to accept the condition for what
it
really is - namely the obverse side of a dualistic coin and, hence, the
price
we pay for our happiness. 'Yes, I am
sad,' you say, 'but this sadness will subsequently give way to a degree
of
happiness which, through an unwritten law of my being, is largely a
consequence
of it.'
NOTHING
SUPERFLUOUS:
That everything is interrelated,
interdependent, interfused ... would
appear to be the
eternal rule of life, a rule which makes it necessary for us to despise
here in
order to admire there, to hate there in order to love here, to condemn
here in
order to praise there, to reject there in order to accept here, to
scowl here
in order to smile there, and so on throughout the entire range of human
experience. When one realizes that
everybody is a part of the whole, a consequence of the whole, and that
to
consider certain parts of the whole superfluous is effectively to turn
against
it, then one can only conclude the people, creatures, and things one dislikes
to be of significance in so far as they make it possible to maintain
the
people, creatures, and things one likes.
Similarly, if one values
admiration one can only conclude the people one despises to be of such
significance to the welfare of one's admiration that one would never be
able to
admire anybody without them; that unless one despised, one would never
be in a position
to admire in the first place, so that the despising is forever
justified,
forever sanctioned by the lure of admiration.
But this is the case, it
may be argued, for every single sentiment a man may have, a case which
ordains
the absolute legitimacy and necessity of his acting the way he does in
order to
maintain his opinions, his prejudices, his
predilections,
and, above all, his integrity.
Let him curse this or that as much as he likes; for unless he
does so,
he will never have anything to bless.
Even if you remove whatever he happens to be cursing, even if
you do
away with it altogether, don't let that beguile you into assuming that
you are
necessarily doing him a favour or improving his lot!
On the contrary, would he not then have to
find something else to curse, in order that he might continue to bless?
BETWEEN
DAY
AND NIGHT: Let us not delude ourselves into imagining,
as too many philosophers have done, that life is either difficult or
easy when,
in reality, it is both difficult and
easy, though,
admittedly, not usually at the same time.
Let us not delude ourselves either, in the manner of the most
pessimistic stoics, that life is both war
and
suffering when, in reality, it is both war and peace and
pleasure
and pain. Still less do we wish to
consider life an absurdity when we cannot help noticing its
reasonableness too,
and can only conclude those who can't to be either poor-sighted or the
victims
of rather serious mental aberrations.
No, we are not
worshippers of the moon, we dualists, and neither are
we worshippers of the sun! It doesn't
become us to serve the one at the expense of the other but, rather, to
serve
or, at any rate, acknowledge them both.
If we give a little more attention, as men, to the sun than to
the moon,
is it not because we are basically unable to do anything else, since
something
buried deep inside our dual natures responds to the ultimate
sovereignty of the
active over the passive, and thereby sets our bias in that direction?
Ah, but we do not
pretend, for all our natural inclinations, that the moon is unworthy of
our
attention. We aren't sufficiently
extreme, perverse, or deluded, in such matters, to suppose ourselves
capable of
thriving without them both, and, to be sure, we have never heard
anything from
either of them to the effect that we should.
But when we temporarily turn our faces away from the light of
the one,
is it not in order that we may better learn to appreciate the light of
the
other, that we may so shine ourselves, and in such a way as to do
absolute
justice to each? Truly, it is not for us
to detract from the positivity of the one
by
foolishly belittling the negativity of the other! There
are
quite enough misunderstandings in
the world already.
A
MISTAKE
IN PLUTARCH: For those readers who may be interested in
the possibility of my theory being mistaken with regard to the interrelativity and inevitability of both
positive and
negative antitheses within the individual, there is a strong attack on
such a
theory in Plutarch's dialogue The
Cleverness
of
Animals, wherein the character Autobulus,
cast
as
Plutarch's father, puts forward to his
old
friend Soclarus a refutation of the said
theory by
emphasizing what he takes to be the impossibility of two completely
contradictory elements within the same person.
Hence, according to Autobulus, the
rational
and the irrational cannot exist
side-by-side, since
the latter would eliminate the former or vice versa. 'If,' he goes on the say, 'to make sure that
Nature is not curtailed in any way, someone maintains that the part of
Nature
which has a soul must comprise both a rational and an irrational
element, then
someone else is sure to say that what has a soul must comprise elements
capable
of imagination and incapable of imagination, capable of feeling and
incapable
of feeling. The idea would be that these
opposites, these positive and negative antitheses about the same thing
should
be kept, as it were, in equilibrium. But
when we consider that all things which have souls must necessarily be
capable
of feeling and of imagination, it will appear absurd to go looking, in
this
class of living things, for antitheses between the feeling and the
unfeeling,
the imaginative and the unimaginative.
And in just the same way it is pointless to find in living
things an antithesis
between the rational and the irrational ...'
I have quoted the best
part of the paragraph under surveillance in order to make quite clear
to the
reader just how Autobulus' reasoning is
wrong. For, having come this far in my
theorizing
and placed more than a little confidence in the authenticity of my
argument, it
is not something that I would like to hide away, refer to obliquely, or
leave
myself in any doubt about, particularly in dealing with a master like
Plutarch. The mistake, then, clearly lies
in the
coupling of elements which are in no way antithetical but, with the
exception
of the rational and the irrational (which is paralleled by me in the
essays
entitled NOT ENTIRELY SANE and NOT ENTIRELY INSANE, as well as having
been
dealt with in considerably more detail by Carl Jung in his analyses of
the
compensatory relationship between the conscious and the unconscious
minds in
the totality of the psyche), distinctly contradictory.
Instead of forming durable antitheses, they
would spell the elimination of each other.
Thus to be 'capable of feeling and incapable of feeling' is
tantamount
to saying 'to be capable of truth and incapable of truth' or 'to be
capable of
love and incapable of love' or, again, 'to be capable of goodness and
incapable
of goodness' when, in reality, it is truth and illusion, love and hate,
good
and evil, which form the antitheses, not the direct
contradiction of the
positive element achieved through the total elimination of the negative
one!
So Autobulus'
reasoning,
although
it may seem feasible at first glance, is really specious,
in that it posits false antitheses as real ones. Rather than the refutation
of feeling by unfeeling, why not the coupling of sympathy and
callousness? We are all sympathetic
in some contexts and
callous in others, as well we might be.
PART
TWO:
LESSONS
ON A DUALISTIC PHILOSOPHY
WISDOM
AND
FOLLY: Where wisdom and folly co-exist, there, too, is
perfection; and you will see that every wise man is also a fool, every
fool
also wise. But how could it be
otherwise? A man always learns wisdom
from his folly and, just as often, folly from his wisdom.
Is it any disgrace, therefore, to know and
foster both of these qualities?
Beware, you wiser men,
the 'fools' who pride themselves on their wisdom, the 'champions of
wisdom',
quite as though they had transcended the human condition by securing a
permanent victory over folly! They will
not help you to understand yourselves.
If you tell them what you know for a fact, they will probably
take you
for a fool and either send you away or,
worse still,
attempt to reform you.
And beware also, you
wiser men, the 'fools' who mock man's wisdom and would reduce us all to
the
level of clambering apes if they thought they could get away with it! Avoid these 'champions of folly' whose
reasoning powers have succumbed to the tyranny of cynicism! They won't help you to understand yourselves,
either. Each of these types is too
extreme to be praiseworthy; they acknowledge either the sun or the
moon, but
never both! That is their greatest
misfortune, you wiser men.
But you need not be
ashamed of your folly or embarrassed by your wisdom.
They are not enemies but close partners in
the business of life. You are wise
enough to be realists and foolish enough to know why.
So see to it, you wiser
men, that your integrity doesn't desert you when it is most needed,
i.e. when
pitched against your
enemies
-
the
lopsided!
TRUTH
AND
ILLUSION: What is truth but the refutation of
illusion? And what is illusion but the
foundation upon which truth is built?
You truthful men, you
who hate nothing so much as self-deception, see to it that you develop
your
illusions as a means to new truths!
Beware, you truthful
men, the enemies of illusion, the pigheaded 'crusaders for truth', who
make war
on illusion as though from a sense of duty.
Often enough they are chasing their tails, but more often still
their
tails are chasing them and they are destroying their truths in the heat
of the
battle! For where one cannot respect
one's illusions, one sacrifices one's truths.
So see to it, you
truthful men, that you are not drawn over
to your
enemy's camp!
And see to it, too, that
you do not become a mocker and doubter of truth, a 'prophet of
illusion' and
the immateriality of the world. The
'illusions' of these people are every bit as obnoxious as the 'truths'
of the
others, and therefore should be avoided by all enlightened men.
But make certain, you
lovers of truth, that you do not neglect your
illusion!
GOOD
AND
EVIL: And what is the word 'good' without the word 'evil'
but a hollow sound without a meaning?
Beware, you good men,
the hollow sounds of the 'preachers of goodness', those sounds that
never ring
true when heard by a sound ear. There is
something false, cracked, lopsided, irresponsible, and spurious about
their
message, and more so about them. It is
not the calling of a good man to denounce evil, but to make use of it
for his
own benefit. Denouncing evil is
tantamount to renouncing good; for were it not for the existence of
evil, a man
would have no opportunity of doing good. But nothing can be got from a bell without a
clapper, and if a man isn't good, which is to say sound, healthy,
strong,
realistic, and honest, he can only be bad, or unsound, ill, weak,
unrealistic,
and dishonest, which is to say - spurious!
So beware, you good men,
the 'preachers of goodness'! They will
not help you to understand yourselves.
And neither will they give you a sound definition of evil; for a
sound
definition isn't something that comes from a cracked bell.
And beware, too, you
good men, the 'preachers of evil', lest you become pale and atrophied
like
them, and gradually wilt away in their winter negativity.
They are not strong enough for your goodness,
but would rather croak their frog-like evil from a swamp than climb
into the
light, where they could be seen by every eye.
Yet their 'evil', like
the 'goodness' of the 'preachers of goodness', is more a caricature
than an
actuality; a mean, sickly thing that pales to insignificance when
placed beside
the authentic life-giving evil which springs from necessity and not
from the
impoverished obsessions of a sickly dabbler.
For a man can no more be evil if he isn't also good, than he can
be good
if not also evil!
So beware, you good men,
both the 'preachers of goodness' and the 'preachers of evil', since
extremities
are equally fatal and it is not your fate to become either a cracked
bell or a
croaking frog. See to it that you remain
a man, and a good one, too!
HAPPINESS
AND
SADNESS: But you happy men, you to whom the word
'sadness' is an invitation to happiness, a bridge and not an obstacle
to your
subsequent happiness, a reprieve and a homecoming at the same time -
see to it,
you happy men, that you do not lose track of happiness in the jungle of
your
sadness!
Beware those men who
would have you cut back on your sadness to a point where you can hardly
discern
your happiness because there is all path
and no
jungle. They are very often the
'teachers of happiness', but their teachings are such that the man who
follows
them becomes sadder than he would otherwise be, and eventually loses
himself in
their complications. Instead of setting
out simple rules for the guidance of the student, they set his path
with tricks
and traps which only confuse him the more.
Instead of showing him the way to greater happiness, they bind
him to
formulae which prevent his discovering it.
Instead of making him happier, they teach him to cut back on his
happiness so that he may become less sad.
Such, my readers, is the wisdom of the 'teachers of happiness'!
But you have no need of
such lethal advice, you happy men, for you do not fear sadness and
neither do
you wish to escape it. You know that
without sadness there would be no happiness,
and that
he who wishes to be happy must first learn to accept sadness and not
foolishly
endeavour to escape it.
Sadness, you happy men,
is not the enemy of your happiness but its closest friend.
It is 'she', and no other, who gives you
happiness and then takes it away when you have had enough, in order
that you
may have more when you deserve it. It is
'she', and no other, who gives meaning to your happiness and, by
breaking it
up, prevents you from becoming bored with it.
It is 'she', and no other, who makes happiness possible, and
whom you
ought to thank for it. So what is a book
on happiness to you happy men, but an excuse for merriment at the
expense of
some dupe's illusions?
Be careful then, you happy
men, that you are not led astray by the 'enemies of sadness', else you
may
quickly lose track of your happiness as well!
It is not your fate to become a living corpse!
PROFUNDITY
AND
SUPERFICIALITY: Now you men of profundity, who
often strive after the core of things at the expense of the husk - take
care,
you profound men, that you do not forget how to be superficial, that
you do not
forget how to honour
the husk!
There are many so-called
profound men who absolutely abhor superficiality and, conversely, many
superficial men who abhor profundity, but one shouldn't pay them too
much
attention - not, that is, unless one is so superficial as to be
deceived by
them. For if a man is truly profound, he
will certainly know how to use superficiality to his own advantage!
So beware, you profound
men, the 'enemies of the superficial'!
And if a man is profound but still an enemy of the
superficial,
you can be pretty sure that his antipathy is a delusion, that he
certainly
knows how to be superficial all right, but doesn't know exactly when
he is
being so.
But 'the superficial'
themselves are your greatest threat; for although they are not
altogether
lacking in profundity, their profundity is almost invariably
incompatible with
yours. It is a profundity from which you
instinctively shy away, as from an immense hurdle or grisly nightmare. It is not a profundity you greatly admire
but, more often, something that strikes you as being akin to a coffin
in the
market place, so disagreeable are the cadaverous connotations which
rise from
it, like the foul stench of a putrid corpse.
So beware then, you
profound men, the profundity of 'the superficial', since it will not
help you
to understand yourselves! See to it that
you do not forget how to cultivate your
superficiality
in antithesis to theirs, lest you endanger the intermittent sovereignty
of your
profundity
as well!
CERTAINTY
AND
DOUBT: One never has doubts about
one's
certainties,
one
has doubts for
them. Without the intermittent prevalence of doubt,
what certainty could one be expected to
have?
Am I not certain that I
am a human being with two arms, two eyes, two ears, a nose, a mouth,
and walk
about on two legs? Yes, of course I
am! And do I not have doubts, from time
to time, about the future, the weather, my health, work, the nature of
my
dreams, etc. Yes, of course I do!
But there are those who
contend that we can have no certainties, can never be certain about
anything
since, according to them, certainties are merely illusory - a
contention from
which we ought to conclude that doubts are, too! Yet
isn't
the theory that we can have no
certainties fundamentally a certainty?
It definitely sounds like one anyway, even if it happens to be
false.
Whatever we hear,
however, no matter how fantastic, there are still many amongst us who
firmly
believe in the reality of certainty and in the equally pervasive
reality of
doubt. And if one is to retain one's
certainty, one must assuredly know how to doubt! For the latter is, after all,
the legitimate foundation upon which the former is built.
So see to it, you
certain men, that your foundations are secure, else the 'doubters of
certainty'
may uproot your doubts as well!
REASONABLENESS
AND
UNREASONABLENESS: Now you men of reason, whose
moderation becomes you in such an extreme age, I have read something to
the
effect that man is not
a reasonable creature but only capable
of reason
- a remark which didn't greatly impress me
when I first came across it but, nonetheless, one which has
since caused
me to speculate more thoroughly on the nature and extent of human
reason and,
if you'll forgive my saying so, to draw conclusions remarkably similar
to those
elicited by Jonathan Swift.
Indeed, it was a great
blow to my ego to suddenly find myself confronted by such an apparently
stark
interpretation of human life, all the more so since I had previously
been
assured by an author who happens to be humanist that man is a
rational
creature.
Yes, a great blow
indeed, but one from which I have since recovered, if you reasonable
men will
again forgive my saying so, to return to life with renewed zest!
Ah, what a liberation to
know that man is not
a
reasonable
creature but, as the aforementioned satirist rightly
contended, only capable
of reason!
And do you know why he
is not a reasonable creature, you reasonable men? Yes,
of
course you do! For you are
reasonable
men, not ignorant, uncouth, bigoted, narrow-minded, bad-tempered,
obsessed, or
extreme men, and consequently you know as well as I do that
reasonableness has
to be paid for with the coin of intermittent unreasonableness!
Yes, you know that well
enough, and that is why you are
reasonable
and not fantastic, like the 'preachers of reason'.
They would condemn your periodic
unreasonableness as a failing, a crime, sin, weakness, etc., over which
you
have total control but against which you refuse to struggle. Like all other lopsided creatures, the
'preachers of reason' have little respect for your integrity as men,
since
they
do not see man in the whole but only in the part, and that, you
reasonable men, is their chief unreasonableness. Instead
of
leading to an acceptance and
understanding of man, it inevitably leads to a condemnation and
belittling of him.
So beware, you
reasonable men, the insidious calumny of the 'preachers of reason'! See to it that you do not become like them;
for they are not even idealists, these lopsided creatures, but
misguided
realists of a pernicious disposition!
And beware, too, you
reasonable men, the unreasonable cynics of whose tribe Jonathan Swift
was
certainly not
a member. For they are
as great a danger to your metaphysical integrity as
the 'preachers of reason', and will do whatever they can to undermine
your
complacency and drag you down to the murky depths of their despair. These men will not help you to understand
yourselves, you reasonable men, and neither will they do much to help
you
improve your self-image. Those who
preach that man should always be reasonable are usually deluded types. But these 'preachers of unreason' are mostly
a low breed, and therefore should be avoided.
One doesn't become a
higher man, you reasonable men, by mixing with the low, so see to it
that your
reason doesn't desert you when it is most needed!
See to it, too, that, for
the sake of your reasonableness, you don't forget how to be
periodically -
unreasonable!
CLEVERNESS
AND
STUPIDITY: Now you clever men, you whose talents
scale the heavens, you whom the world recognizes as wise and competent
men, the
damnation of some and the salvation of others - see to it that you are
clever
enough to endorse your stupidity!
I will not hear it said
of you that you have no stupidity, for such a callous accusation would
surely
detract from the indisputable evidence of your periodic cleverness. Genius, be it noted, is entitled to greater
mistakes than ordinary men, and for no small reason has genius
traditionally
been conceded the benefit of the doubt.
But men of genius have
often been ashamed of their stupidity, which is no small mistake. For it is stupidity which has regularly
convinced them that they ought not to tarnish their reputation for
cleverness
with stupidity, and it is stupidity which has so often turned them against
themselves. The unhappy genius, so often
a man who is not sufficiently clever - to himself!
Oh, but there is a
salutary lesson to be learnt from such unhappy geniuses, you clever
men, a
lesson that will not turn us against our stupidity. For even if we are momentarily angered by it
when caught unawares, even if we imagine ourselves succumbing to its
insidious
influence more often than we ought, even if we do or say certain things
in the
heat of the argument which, on reflection, we are later ashamed of, let
us at
least have the gumption, you clever men, to recognize it as an
indispensable
component in the human condition, the very justification of our
cleverness, and
therefore not something that ought to be entirely eliminated for the
sake of
our intellectual improvement.
Alas, how many of us
would actually be improved by the elimination of a component which guarantees
our
cleverness? Not very many, I will wager,
unless, however, there are some amongst us who see cleverness in the
inactivity
of a motionless 'sage' sitting under the branches of a tree all day.
But we who pride
ourselves on a daily activity, no matter how sedentary, can hardly
expect to
fare well in the world without maintaining a degree of cleverness, and
a degree
of cleverness, moreover, which is largely dependent, I tell you, upon
the
intermittent co-operation of our stupidity.
And yet, you clever men,
there is something about your competent, fastidious, deliberative,
methodical,
sober, and shrewd dispositions which has intimated to me that you are
not very
willing to acknowledge your stupidity, irrespective of what the latest
philosophical oracle may have to say on the subject, when, as far as
you are
concerned, there is very little evidence of stupidity to be found. You have grown weary of philosophical
presumption, you clever men, and now you doubt whether a philosopher
can still
be trusted, particularly when what he says has some truth in it, and he
is
therefore no less in danger than anyone else of succumbing to the
legitimate
influences of illusion or stupidity.
Very well, I concede you
the right of disputation, you sceptical men, since you have every right
to
believe what you consider to be of most relevance to yourselves. But it is still my
firm
contention that your cleverness and stupidity are interrelated, so that
the one
cannot exist without the other, and that, whatever you
may think,
you regularly succumb to stupidity without in the least being aware of
the
fact! Hence, you are naturally
disinclined to endorse a view which seems totally contradictory to your
various
activities - activities you mostly take for granted, in any case.
However, whatever the
final opinion of you clever men may happen to be, see to it that you
are not
undone, like the unhappy geniuses, by your
stupidity. There is surely enough
cleverness in you for
that!
SUCCESS
AND
FAILURE: But you successful men, you whose memories
are stacked with failure, have you ever considered how important it is
to you
and your successes that you should continue to experience failures?
Truly, there is hardly a
man amongst us who isn't regularly prey to some kind of failure, and
most of us
could certainly draw up a long list of our most memorable failures -
the very
ones which we are privately least keen to remember!
But what would we do,
you successful failures, if we had never failed in anything? Would we be able to boast of any successes?
Alas, I cannot see that
we would! For it seems that our
successes are fundamentally dependent upon the intermittent prevalence
of our
failures, and that without these failures, no matter how hideous or
demoralizing some of them were, we should be deprived of even the
faintest
intimation of success. But who would be
able to tolerate a life without some kind of success?
Who, with the possible exception of the most
unfortunate, would ever be in a position to know
what a
life without some kind of success was like anyway?
To be sure, one need not
be a celebrity to experience such a fundamentally common feature of
life. One need only get up at the right
time in the
morning, prove to be fairly competent in one's work, enjoy a good meal,
read an
interesting chapter of a worthwhile book, solve a particular problem,
maintain
congenial relations with one's associates, neighbours, friends, family,
etc.,
or win a raffle, to experience the essential feeling of success, a
feeling
which isn't restricted to only a 'privileged few', by any means!
So if you value your
successes, you successful men, see to it that you aren't ashamed of
your
failures. For they are not as great an
obstacle to your successes as you may at first imagine.
On the contrary, they are your greatest
incentive to leap ever higher!
PLEASURE
AND
PAIN: Without pain, you men
of pleasure, what pleasure could you possibly hope to obtain from life?
For is not the absence of pain somewhat
pleasurable to you and, conversely, the absence of pleasure somewhat
painful?
Naturally, you do not
care to speak very highly of pain, considering that you have hitherto
found the
subject rather painful and more like an obstacle to your pleasure than
a goad
to it. But you would not forsake your
pleasures all the same, you shrewdly pleasurable men, since you are no
fools
when it comes to knowing where your advantage lies.
For who, having just crossed the bridge which
leads from pain to pleasure, has ever cared to look back over his
shoulder to
survey the opposite bank - the bank of his pains?
Of course, pain is
a terrible
thing, a real monster to deal with. But
tell me, you shrewdly pleasurable men, how could we possibly flee from
it if it
were not so terrible, if its aspect were insufficiently disagreeable to
send us
shrieking to our advantage on the other side of the bridge?
Fortunately, it is far
too negative a monster to ever cross the bridge after us.
But, all the same, it is far too big and
crafty a monster for us to destroy. Yet
it knows its limits, this 'monster of pain', and it will not transgress
these
limits while the 'guardian of pleasure' sits beaming on the opposite
bank and protects
the
bridge. For it knows that the 'guardian
of pleasure' is ultimately the strongest, since it is to pleasure that
all
mortals daily aspire.
Just watch this 'monster
of pain' slink away into the depths of its pitiless jungle when 'the
guardian'
sits beaming on the opposite bank, his countenance radiant with the positivity of his
kingdom,
one in which the monster's negativity has no place.
For the 'guardian of pleasure' is no mean
host, and his guests know that they will receive a warm welcome, once
they
enter the kingdom from which all negativity is eternally banned.
But you men of pleasure,
you whom nature has endowed with a preponderance of the positive over
the
negative, you know well enough that you aren't wholly satisfied with
pleasure
alone, and that something deep inside your dual natures inevitably
calls you
back to the other bank, the bank of your pains and the longing
for
pleasure.
Yes, you would soon grow
tired of pleasure if you had no means of getting away from it, if there
wasn't
a bridge in evidence across which your wisdom could lead you so that,
newly
strengthened by your recent pleasures, you could once more enter the
kingdom of
pain and grapple anew with the monster from which you must eventually
flee.
But it is not for the
'monster of pain' to give you a warm welcome, you pleasurable men. For everything in its
kingdom is negative, everything subordinated to pain, and it knows you
for what
you are, for the born enemies of pain that you are.
It knows that you have only come back to use
it as a means to your subsequent pleasures and, having no pleasure
itself, it
mortally loathes this fact. For it is
secretly jealous of 'the guardian's' power over you and will do
everything it
possibly can to make this jealousy known, even though it knows itself
to be
forever chained to a secondary role, from which there is no escape.
And you won't hesitate
to do battle with this loathsome monster, you pleasurable men, once you
realize
that your future pleasure depends on it.
For you are shrewd and know where your advantage lies. And even while you are defending yourselves,
you will still cast an occasional glance back over your shoulder
towards the
opposite bank, the bank of your pleasures, to see if 'the guardian' is
sufficiently
radiant with the positivity of his kingdom
to warrant
your return.
Oh yes, I know you, you
pleasurable men, considering that I am also of your tribe and,
likewise, only
too willing to glance back to my advantage.
But beware the prophets
of false wisdom, the dead-and-dying prophets of the
all-pleasure-and-no-pain or
the all-pain-and-no-pleasure schools!
They will not help you to understand yourselves, since they are
akin to
one-sided creatures, and man is not, by nature, one-sided.
So beware all extremists
and false prophets, you pleasurable men, and see to it that you do not
give up
the fight with pain too quickly, before the 'guardian of pleasure' has
had
sufficient time in which to rejuvenate himself!
LOVE
AND
HATE: Although it is an odd thing to confess, I have
heard so-called men of love proclaim their hatred of hate without in
the least
being aware that they were still hating.
Yes, they have made it
their duty to hate hatred for the sake of love because, according to
them, to
love hatred would be to acquiesce in it and thereby tarnish their
reputation
for love. They do not see, these
'preachers of love', that hating hatred is still hate,
and that one cannot love without hating.
They would like us to believe that they are solely men of love,
but we
aren't really convinced. We shy away
from their doctrine of love when it outlaws hate, much as we shy away
from all
other crooked and one-sided doctrines.
And we do not take a man seriously when he proclaims one thing
and does
another!
But to whom am I
addressing myself if not to the natural, liberated, and honest men? Yes, it is to you natural men that I address
this message, since you are not so fantastic as to believe yourselves
capable
of outlawing hate in the interests of your love. Neither
would
you deceive yourselves by
imagining that a hatred of hate wasn't hate.
On the contrary, you are far too honest and strict with
yourselves to
allow that
kind of self-deception to take root in you!
But the others, the
hypocrites of love, are the ones against whom you will most have to
guard your
integrity, if you don't wish to become victims of their
love. For this love is a changeable thing, full of
multifaceted appearances, and many are the times when they have grown
so
accustomed to regarding themselves as men of love ... that they have
confounded
love with hate and termed this latter 'love'.
Just watch how their
love will
shine in their eyes, once you begin to criticize a doctrine that
excludes
hate! They will certainly know how to
love you then, especially when they perceive how much pleasure your
criticism
brings you. And if you then inform them,
you loving men, that their
love is often hatred in disguise,
be prepared to witness a 'bonfire of love' in their eyes from which you
may
well have to shield yourself, so great an emotional conflagration will
it
engender!
But everything that
flares up must eventually die down again, and their 'bonfire' is no
exception. They will soon go back to
loving you, once they see how incorrigibly unrepentant you are. For they won't have it said that they are
mistaken, once they have convinced themselves to the contrary!
And you loving men, who
are too strict to deceive yourselves on this issue, will know that they
aren't
really wrong in practice but only in theory.
For this 'bonfire of love' in their eyes is all the evidence you
could
need to judge of their practical authenticity.
It is only their theory which is spurious. They
have
set themselves a standard to which
they are unable to attain (though, between ourselves, that is just as
well,
since, if they could attain to it, we would soon be obliged to follow
suit!). But, in a majority of cases,
they are really natural men in disguise, men who are secretly ashamed
of their
humanity and would rather hide it behind a spurious theory. They are not honest enough to be like you,
because they aren't liberated enough to be that honest.
So beware then, you
loving men, the 'preachers of love', whose mendacious value-judgements
will not
help you to understand yourselves!
And beware also the
equally mendacious value-judgements of the 'preachers of hate', whose
basic
attitudes I do not even wish to discuss, since they are just as
one-sided in
their insistence upon hate as the others in insisting upon love, and
neither of
these types represent man as he really is!
But see to it, you
loving men, that you do not forget how to
hate what it
is necessary to hate, in order that you may continue to love!
VIRTUE
AND
VICE: There are in this world people who claim to be
virtuous by avoiding vice, a strange breed if ever there was one, but a
breed
which can be found in virtually every country on earth.
To be sure, there are
often among their number many virtuous men, but that is only because
the men in
question are not ashamed to indulge in certain vices which they
mistakenly
describe as virtues. Indeed, when it
comes to theorizing, they know only too well how to condemn vice as
they
understand it, which, in a world where one man's meat is often another
man's
poison, is hardly surprising!
But it is not enough, my
virtuous friends, to condemn the vices of other types of people, and
thereupon
imagine that one has condemned vice altogether, when one is still
apparently
virtuous enough to possess certain personal vices, and to find these
vices so
acceptable that they conveniently pass for virtues.
For the virtues of these rather priggish
individuals exist by dint of the vices of the other types, whereas, in
reality,
it is only by dint of their own
vices
that
they
have any virtues at all.
It is ignorance of the
exact nature of their personal vices which has gradually led them to
see virtue
in terms of condemning the vices, or assumed vices, of other types of
people. But this is a very limited view
and, if I may be so bold as to say, one which ultimately does a grave
disservice to the concept of virtue! For
virtues are seldom found in a person without any vices.
However that may be, let
us do what we can to cultivate our
vices, you
virtuous men, and see to it that the relationship between virtue and
vice is
maintained, in the honourable name of our most esteemed virtues, the
continuous
prevalence of which more than adequately attests to a well-balanced
partnership!
As, however, for those
'hypocrites of virtue' (though some of them are less hypocritical than
simply
deluded), I don't specifically intend to deprive them of the pleasure
they
evidently obtain from the vice of condemning other people's vices, but
I should
certainly feel that some progress had been made if they subsequently
came to
inquire a little more thoroughly into the nature and extent of their own
vices, in
order to safeguard their virtues all the more!
So beware, you virtuous
men, those lopsided creatures who would have you remove your vices in
the
interests of your virtues, believing that a man can be virtuous without
the
assistance of vice!
See to it that you are
not led astray by such men. For it is
not your fate to become fragmented, but to remain whole!
STRENGTH
AND
WEAKNESS: Were it not for his weaknesses a man would
be unable to boast of his strengths. Is
it clear to you exactly what is being implied by this statement, you
strong
men? Do you not see that boasting is a
weakness which enables a man to draw attention to his strengths?
Yes, of course you do,
and that is precisely why you are
all
boasters, you strong men, because you are insufficiently strong to be
able to
manage without your weaknesses.
But boasting is not your
only weakness, nor even your worst, and
some of you
boast far less than others, in order to cultivate different weaknesses
the
more!
Indeed, there are so
many weaknesses about you that it is often difficult for one to know
exactly
where a weakness ends and a strength begins. You fool others as much as you fool
yourselves, you strong men, and sometimes, at the height of an
unreasonable or
vainglorious mood, you are even audacious enough to pretend to not
having any
weaknesses - a foolish pretence if ever there was one, since your
strengths
aren't sufficiently independent to be able to manage without them!
But, even so, it is not
altogether surprising that your weaknesses should occasionally lead you
to
disown your strengths. For you are not
meant to be all strength.
And neither are you
meant to pay attention to those who would have you eliminate your
weaknesses
for the sake of your strengths, since such people will not help you to
understand yourselves, you strong men, and will probably make you
weaker than
you should be. They do not see, these
shallow 'preachers of strength', that man isn't meant to be all
strength, and
so every weakness they detect in another person is inevitably magnified
out of
all proportion, as though it constituted a real danger to strength.
But their refusal to
tolerate weakness is the only real danger to strength, you strong men,
so
beware the enemies of weakness!
And beware also the
enemies of strength, the self-righteous 'preachers of weakness', lest
they
cheat you out of your self-confidence and reduce you to the base level
of their
cringing servility! Man isn't meant to
live by strength alone, but neither is he meant to be entirely weak!
So see to it, you strong
men, that you remain both strong and
weak for
the sake of your strengths!
INTEREST
AND
DISINTEREST: But now, as a final contribution to this
series of lessons on a dualistic philosophy, it is time for me to
consider the
most interesting men alive, the men of interest, and to offer them some
timely
advice on the subject of disinterestedness, the key to their interest.
For I have lately heard
it said that men can only remain interested in a given interest for a
limited
period of time, as also for a limited time within each day, and that
they must
afterwards turn to fresh activities or, failing that, to no activities
at
all. And it was also said, not entirely
without justification, that they must turn their backs on many high and
worthy
matters for the sake of their
interest, in order not to
dissipate their daily quota of intense concentration on subjects less
than
relevant to their respective occupations.
Now this same wit, whose
words I easily overheard, was very much of the opinion that highly
cultured
people must often allow themselves to be taken for philistines by the
adherents
of a different culture or interest, since this wasn't only expedient in
terms
of the prevention of unnecessary argument but expedient, moreover, in
terms of
the maintenance of their respective interests as well.
For if, to cite this worthy logician, they
'aspired to being more interested in matters not wholly pertinent to
their
strongest predilections than they should, they could soon find their
natural
quota of sustained appreciation expended long before they were in a
position to
return to their real interests, to those matters formerly regarded as
virtually
sacrosanct'.
And this delightful wit,
who was also a sort of moral philosopher, admitted most frankly, and
with the
greatest relish, that he was 'not in the least ashamed to eschew all
the most
important art galleries, museums, concert halls, theatres, and cinemas
in the
world in the interests of [his] philosophy', but that he would
willingly be
branded a philistine 'ten times over' if it guaranteed him, during the
course
of each day, that he would always have 'the energy and inclination' to
return
to his 'beloved theorizing', the interest, par excellence, of his
cultural
life!
So take care, you men of
interest, that you do not forget how to cultivate disinterestedness for
the
sake of your interest. For your
culture
can only grow where there is sufficient indifference towards culture in
general, and your culture is more important to you than anyone else's.
Thus speaks the voice of
self-interest!
PART
THREE:
DIALOGUE
ON A DUALISTIC PHILOSOPHY
(A
Dualistic
Integrity)
PHILOSOPHER
(Addressing himself to his young interviewer):
So you have familiarized yourself with my latest philosophical
contentions, and
now you wish to ask me some questions concerning them?
STUDENT:
That
is correct!
PHILOSOPHER:
Well
then, what can I do for you?
STUDENT
(Consulting his notes): You have contended that a
man cannot be good without also being intermittently evil - in short,
that
goodness cannot exist without the aid of its opposite.
How, then, do you differentiate between good
and evil in relation to people?
PHILOSOPHER:
Very
simply!
Whatever proceeds from positive feelings is good and,
conversely,
whatever proceeds from negative feelings is evil. Thus
when
you transmit the former you are
doing good to someone, you are making a person feel happier, as well as
making
yourself feel happier, whereas when you transmit the latter you are
making both
yourself and someone else feel less happy or possibly even sad, and are
therefore doing evil.
STUDENT:
So
every action committed in anger is evil?
PHILOSOPHER:
Yes,
because anger invariably engenders negative
feelings and thereby makes people feel wretched.
STUDENT:
Hence
we can always know whether we are doing good or
evil simply by taking account of the nature of the feelings that we are
transmitting at the time?
PHILOSOPHER:
Precisely! For
example, if you were a thief engaged in cracking open a safe somewhere,
you
would know yourself to be doing evil simply by taking account of the
way you
felt. You would probably feel very
tense, very 'on edge', very nervous in case
anything
went wrong. And if, by ill-luck,
anything did go wrong, like you were caught, say, in the act
of opening
the safe, you would probably either lose your nerve altogether and give
yourself up or panic and, assuming it was within your powers, attempt
to
escape. But the negative feelings would
give you away all the time.
STUDENT:
Yet
none of us can avoid doing both good and evil, even
though the evil needn't entail cracking safes?
PHILOSOPHER:
No,
we are made for both and, as such, we are
compelled to accept both. Try to imagine
a life without any negativity, a life without any worries, pains,
angers,
frustrations, doubts, aggressions, tensions, regrets, hatreds,
prejudices,
disparities, etc. I rather doubt that
you would be able to live such a life under normal circumstances.
STUDENT:
Yet
Christ taught men to 'resist not evil', which,
broadly speaking, means to 'turn the other cheek', to ignore the evils
of
others, to live and let live, to resign oneself to the ways of the
world and
not offer any opposition to one's enemies or potential enemies, so that
one can
remain calm and continue to experience 'eternal peace', or the 'Kingdom
of God'
within the self. That was what he taught
and also what he demonstrated during the final days of his earthly
life, when
he showed an apparent indifference to his fate and allowed himself to
be pushed
around from hand to hand without making any attempt to defend or
justify
himself.
PHILOSOPHER:
Yes,
that is perfectly true. But
comparatively few men are permitted to
lead a Christ-like existence, especially when, not being itinerant
philosophers
or religious preachers, they are obliged to earn a living in such a
highly
competitive and potentially hostile world as this one!
Unfortunately, there is often a marked lacuna
between a philosopher's teachings and their actual applicability to
daily
life. It is all very well for Christ to
preach particular doctrines, for he slots into the world as a preacher,
he earns
a living by preaching, whereas the vast majority of those to whom he
preaches
aren't really in a position to follow suit, to abandon their respective
tasks
and lead a similar life. So they are
inevitably compelled to ignore or, more accurately, fail to live-up to
certain
of his teachings. The only true way to
lead a Christ-like existence would be to become a wandering,
self-employed,
self-responsible, self-styled preacher.
But what do you think would happen if everybody 'down-tooled',
as it
were, and followed Christ's example?
STUDENT:
There
would be far too many preachers in the world,
leading, ultimately, to chaos.
PHILOSOPHER:
Yes,
chaos is indeed an apt description! If
everybody led a Christ-like existence,
there wouldn't be anyone left to preach to and the human kind would
quickly die
out. Without butchers, bakers, farmers,
fishermen, builders, shop assistants, clerks, doctors, etc., everybody
would be
dead within a few weeks or, at most, months.
So without intending any disrespect towards the messianic
vocation, one
can see how absolutely imperative it is that a majority of people
always refrain
from
following in Christ's footsteps too literally.
And if they must refrain from doing so on the grounds that a few
billion
preachers would ultimately lead to chaos, they must also refrain from
taking
some of Christ's teachings too seriously - a thing which, as history
adequately
attests, has never proved too difficult for them anyway, Ghandi-like
exceptions
notwithstanding. Therefore, in returning
to this problem of good and evil, it is not wise, in my opinion, to
resist too
much evil. For unless one is someone who
has purposely gone out of his way, like Christ, to preach that kind of
thing,
or is part of a vast crowd of people who can bank on the strength of
the finite
number of club-wielders eventually running out, one could easily become
a
living corpse pushed hither and thither by all who have more strength,
audacity, willpower, or authority than oneself.
Yet for a time, as you well remarked, Christ virtually made a
living out
of being pushed backwards and forwards from hand to hand.
But it seems quite obvious to me that a
majority of us certainly couldn't make a living out of it, so one must
learn to
stand-up for oneself and be natural too, you know!
People often resign themselves to a kind of
death-in-life after they have been seriously disappointed in some way.
STUDENT:
How
do you mean?
PHILOSOPHER:
Well,
when one lives fully, vigorously, naturally,
impulsively, and adventurously, there are always a correlative number
of dues
to be paid. Usually, the more one lives,
as opposed to just exists, the wider becomes one's spectrum of
emotional
involvement on both the negative and
the
positive
sides
of life, and it is this latter fact in particular which
generally proves an immense stumbling-block to such people as I am
alluding. When one settles down, as the
saying goes, one is usually curtailing one's spectrum of activity to a
level or
degree that won't unduly disturb one, won't cause one to suffer too
much but,
on the contrary, permit one a sort of Buddhist imperturbability. In short, the more one lives, i.e. the more
vigorous and adventurous one is, the more suffering will have to be
accepted as
the inevitable price one pays for one's pleasures.
Now if, because of various personal problems,
you don't wish to suffer beyond a certain point, you must endeavour not
to live
beyond a certain point, though the point in question will depend upon
the
nature of your personal circumstances. I
mean if, for example, you are used to a hectic life and then suddenly
switch to
a slower one, it will probably bore you to tears because of the
contrast. You will probably suffer more
from the slower
one, to begin with, than ever you did from the hectic one previously!
STUDENT:
Yes,
I seem to recall a similar experience myself, and I
was terribly bored. But, tell me, is
there really no way of avoiding boredom?
People are always complaining about it, no matter where you go.
PHILOSOPHER:
It
is virtually impossible to entirely escape from
the intermittent prevalence of boredom, and altogether futile to
attempt such
an escape, in any case. Boredom has a
very legitimate place in life as the opposite of excitement. Now perpetual excitement, assuming it were
possible, would be an insufferable hardship for even the most excitable
of
people. It would either wear them out or
wear thin eventually. But, fortunately,
there is always boredom to fall back on, to act as a reprieve from
excitement
and, conversely, from which to create
excitement
afresh after one has grown tired of it.
So if you value excitement, I am afraid that you must learn to
accept
boredom. For the one
is as important as the other, and they are inextricably linked together
throughout the course of your life.
There is no defeating boredom by a determined attempt to escape
into
excitement when the latter isn't justified, hasn't been paid for, as it
were,
by a sufficient preliminary degree of boredom, whether that boredom
takes the
form of manual work or intellectual work or, indeed, no work at all. People who attempt to cheat themselves out of
boredom very often become bored with what they foolishly imagine will
excite
them, thereby defeating their objectives.
They may be excited for a time with whatever they happen to be
doing,
but such excitement soon pales to insignificance, and even though they
carry on
with their respective pursuits they will really be bored to tears.
STUDENT:
You
sound very wise.
PHILOSOPHER:
Don't
believe it!
Perhaps I seem a little wiser than others because I have more
time in
which to think. I spend the greater part
of my day thinking, teaching, and writing, whereas a majority of people
have to
do an office job, a factory job, a shop job, or a service job. But they aren't necessarily less wise than
me! If a man doesn't want to write and
speak these kind of thoughts, what would be the point of his doing so? He would be a fool, wouldn't he?
Oh no, everybody has his own tasks to attend
to and, as such, everybody is as wise as he needs to be!
If I have any wisdom at all, it should
prevent me from imagining a philosopher's task to be the highest, the
one and
only task to which a man should aspire if he wishes to regard himself
as an
intellectual success. But, naturally,
there are
philosophers who pride themselves on such an arrogant
attitude; men who fatuously consider most other people to be either
superfluous
types or failures, which, if my wisdom counts for anything at all, they
are
very unwise to do! Indeed, one may be
excused for assuming that an element of envy enters into their
attitude, that
it may be a form of unconscious compensation for the fact that they
find their
philosophical tasks so difficult, and therefore aren't altogether
convinced of
their own personal or professional superiority.
But God forbid the establishment of a world exclusively geared
to the
production and aggrandizement of philosophers!
Truly, there is much to be said for an attitude of mind which
knows how
to be ruthlessly selective in its choice of reading matter! For not everything that goes between the
covers of a book passes for wisdom or truth.
There are many so-called serious writers, thinkers, poets,
prophets,
etc., who imagine that they are writing wisdom or truth when, in
reality,
nothing could be further from the case!
And one is sometimes fooled by these pernicious influences, is
one not?
STUDENT:
Yes,
I'm afraid so!
Thus you are cautious as to the extent and authenticity of your
own
wisdom as well?
PHILOSOPHER:
Up
to a point.
For what I would particularly like to impress upon you is a
knowledge of
the fact that no-one can be wholly wise, and hence a 'wise man', least
of all
those who generally purport to being such.
One becomes wiser on various issues primarily on account of
one's folly,
so, fundamentally, it is the folly that guarantees one's wisdom. In other words, without being intermittently
unwise one could never hope to be wise at all.
Consequently one can never be really wise except in the sense of
also
knowing oneself to be a fool. Yes, that
is a true wisdom - knowing oneself to be both wise and foolish
without
ever standing a chance of becoming exclusively either.
Therefore I shall permit you to refer to me
as a 'wise man', though only on the condition that you also privately
take me
for a fool. Is that acceptable to you?
STUDENT:
You
embarrass me slightly.
PHILOSOPHER:
My
dear friend, there is absolutely nothing to be
embarrassed about! Learn to see me as a
person rather than as a repository of ultimate wisdom or truth. I do not wish to be regarded as an infallible
philosopher, still less a guru. Don't
put me on a pedestal, even if it brings you a certain amount of
pleasure. It is better that we converse as
man to man
rather than as god to man, isn't it?
STUDENT:
Yes,
you are doubtless right there! Although it is
pleasurable to have someone to admire. It
seems
to be a natural tendency in man.
PHILOSOPHER:
Then
disregard my foolishness and continue to admire
me, if that is what you want. I shall do
my best to bear with it and not disappoint you.
I shall allow you a degree of pleasure at my expense, just as
you allow
me a degree of pleasure by being both my interlocutor and student. For all tutors require students if they are
to remain relatively sane. So I respect
you as my student.
STUDENT:
And
I respect you as my tutor.
PHILOSOPHER:
Well
then, is there anything else you wish to ask me?
STUDENT
(Consulting his notes again): Yes, as a matter of
fact, I am deeply intrigued by your theory of insanity, which I would
like to
explore in greater detail. Why is it
that, according to you, we can never go entirely insane?
Surely life provides ample proof to the
contrary, as any lunatic asylum would demonstrate.
PHILOSOPHER:
I
must have been partly insane to have contended such
a thing in the first place! But,
curiously, that is really the fact of the matter. You
see,
we are all partly insane from the
time of our birth to the time of our death.
If we weren't insane as well as sane, life would prove
more
insufferable than it generally does. As
beings of polarity, we contain elements of sanity and
insanity
within us throughout our lives. Thus if
one is already partly insane, it is quite impossible to actually go
insane. All one can do is cultivate the
normal polarity to a point of incompatibility with majority standards. Take the case, for example, of James Joyce's Finnegans
Wake. An average
person would surely be tempted to
consider Joyce insane on account of the obscure style and eccentric
nature of
much of its content. It is extremely
difficult for even the most literate of people to understand, and
proves
virtually unintelligible to anyone not well-acquainted with a variety
of
European languages. Yet Joyce is
generally regarded as sane and, in my opinion, rightly so.
Notwithstanding the extraordinary fact that
the novel took him some eighteen years to complete, due in part to his
failing
eyesight and numerous eye operations, he kept to the task and
consequently
remained intelligible to people within the context of writer.
STUDENT:
But
if you contend that we are both sane and
insane, why do you now contradict yourself by considering Joyce sane?
PHILOSOPHER:
Ah,
but I was speaking on the world's terms rather
than on my own, in order to remain intelligible within the framework of
a wider
context! The world treats sanity and
insanity as entirely separate phenomena which, under the prevailing
circumstances, it is perfectly entitled to do, since one must be able
to
communicate generally as well as particularly, in terms intelligible to
the
non-philosophical generality as well as in terms engineered by the
philosophical individual. The 'sanity'
to which I was alluding has its analogue in the 'wisdom' of the
foregoing
conversation. It is a sanity of one's
being more or less compatible with majority standards, rather than a
sanity
which wholly excludes the possibility of a concomitant degree of
insanity being
involved in one's life. Thus Joyce's
'sanity' can be established on the basis of the fact that he remained a
writer
and eventually had Finnegans
Wake
published. Had he destroyed
the typescript instead of having it published, there would of course be
a real
case for considering him insane, though, once again, only on the
world's terms.
STUDENT:
This
is all rather confusing! However, I
think I'm just beginning to
understand you, even though I am by no means convinced that you are
right. I mean, isn't the eccentricity of Finnegans
Wake, coupled to the fact that, even with
serious eye trouble, it took Joyce so long to complete, sufficient
indication
of insanity - at least in the world's eyes?
Surely no-one would have spent so much time on the creation of a
work
which, if memory serves me well, is not even 600 pages long.
PHILOSOPHER:
Not
unless he was both highly individualistic and
virtually blind. But, even so, is it
really any stranger or 'madder' to dedicate oneself to writing a
certain book
for eighteen years than to work in a peanut factory for as many years,
to teach
simple arithmetic to junior-school children for several
years, to give a few thousand performances of
a particular play in a variety of theatres, to give as many
performances of a
given piece of music in a variety of concert halls, or to drive a bus
around on
the same route for several years on-end?
When one begins to consider the vast number of human activities,
their
apparent eccentricities, and the number of times or years people carry
on doing
them, there would seem to be sufficient grounds for considering
everyone partly
insane, not just the comparatively small number of eccentric writers,
musicians, or artists one happens to know about. Indeed,
why
should we not regard a
mathematician, an acrobat, a clown, a comedian, a priest, a politician,
a
racing-car driver, a footballer, a soldier, a pilot, or an actor to be
just as
crazy or eccentric as Joyce - assuming we were disposed to regarding
Joyce in
such a light anyway? For instance, can
you imagine Joyce preaching about Biblical miracles all his life?
STUDENT:
No,
I don't think the mumbo-jumbo or occult side of
religion would have greatly appealed to him, if books like Ulysses
are anything to judge by!
PHILOSOPHER:
Indeed
not!
And he would have been as justified in assuming the preaching of
miracles to be a waste of his time as, say, a priest would be in
assuming the
writing of a novel that took eighteen years to be a waste of his
time,
considering that, to some extent, everyone seems foolish to everyone
else. But one must stick by one's habits
if doing
so makes life more tolerable, if not enjoyable.
Most people are incapable, in any case, of being highly
individualistic,
of being a writer or an artist, because too much of their own company,
too much
solitude, and too great a demand on their personal initiative would
sooner or
later lead them to worry about their sanity, about the possibility of
their
slowly going insane without anyone being there to help them. For a time even I worried about this, when I
first started out on a writing career.
But it gradually dawned on me that, provided one kept at it and
didn't
become too lazy or careless, writing fairly intelligible information
all day
wasn't really any weirder than doing particular clerical duties all
day, or
teaching infant-school children to read, or working on a newspaper
team, or playing
professional cricket every day. What
really matters is how one feels about doing
it! Yet it is truly amazing how a majority
of
people will cope with just about any task so long as they have
colleagues,
co-workers, mates, or whatever who do similar things and thus keep them
company. Then it appears that they feel
protected against themselves, against the responsibilities of creative
individualism.
STUDENT:
So
it no longer worries you, as a writer and teacher,
that you are now going your own way?
PHILOSOPHER:
Occasionally
it still worries me, though not as much
as before. When I feel self-doubts as to
the validity of my work or the nature of my calling, I generally
console myself
in the knowledge that it takes more courage to 'do your own thing' than
to 'run
with the herd', and that I must be mentally brave to be doing what I
do, rather
than something which can only be done in the company of others and, as
often as
not, under their command. Then I
consider the nature of the many things which various other people
either have
to do or choose to do. Yet they don't
normally consider themselves going mad on account of the nature of
their
respective occupations. Far from it! It is the occupations which prevent
them
from
imagining
that they are on the verge of insanity, even though what they
do may
well be less sane, or rational, than what I
am doing
... judged from an individualistic point-of-view. However,
the
important thing is to remain
preoccupied.
STUDENT:
So
Joyce was evidently preoccupied with the creation of Finnegans
Wake for some considerable
period of time?
PHILOSOPHER:
As
a matter of fact, he became increasingly
fastidious in his approach to writing. For as Ulysses
will confirm,
fastidiousness had long been a major concern of his. So it doesn't particularly surprise me that
he brought this concern to a veritable head in Finnegans
Wake. Someone who had arduously read-up
on Joyce
once informed me that on average he was writing a line a day, but a
line
replete with subtle puns, symbolic innovations, hybrid words, and
complex
intellectual connotations - in short, a very pregnant line! So his creative fastidiousness had brought
him to that peak of perfectionism or professionalism or eccentricity or
extremity or foolishness or brilliance, or whatever else the voice of
your
personal judgement would like to call it, to the utter astonishment of
the many
less-individualistic natures. Had he
lasted beyond his fifty-ninth year, and thus started work on another
book, we
may be forgiven for doubting whether he would have lived long enough to
complete it, so deeply engrained would his fastidiousness have become
by
then! One can imagine an 83-year-old
Joyce half-way through a potentially 300-page tome, a tome of such
arcane
complexity as to appear utterly unintelligible.
STUDENT:
Have
you ever felt yourself slipping into a tendency
towards such fastidiousness in your own work?
PHILOSOPHER:
Nothing
comparable to Joyce, I can assure you! Though I have found reason
to criticize myself on occasion.
The only remedy for such a tendency would, I suppose, be to give
oneself
over to something comparatively slapdash, that is to say slapdash
according to
one's own exaggerated standards rather than by general or, so to say,
journalistic standards. Such
fastidiousness is probably one of the main reasons why certain authors
are
always so dissatisfied with their writings.
For instead of cultivating a fairly readable and spontaneous
style of
prose, they become bogged down in a swamp of self-criticism which, in
any case,
is probably irrelevant to their requirements.
STUDENT:
You
mean a writer may coerce himself into becoming so
self-critical, with regard to his work, that the habit gradually
overrides his
natural pride in and enjoyment of it until, in becoming a sort of
obsession, it
causes him to lose faith in himself.
Instead of being there to serve his work, the critical sense
becomes so
over-developed as to become a hindrance to it, and a kind of madness is
the
illogical result.
PHILOSOPHER:
Yes,
that may well be the case. For
nothing will satisfy him so long as the
critical sense remains intrusively
paramount. But if one doesn't at least
enjoy one's work to some extent, how can one possibly expect other
people to
enjoy it at all? A writer in that
situation ought either to give-up writing altogether or learn to
cultivate a
less self-critical approach to it until, eventually, he can strike a
balance
between the two fatal extremes - that of the over-fastidious and the
slapdash. If he loses a little pride
over the reformed nature of his style, he may gain some additional
pride on the
strength of his subject-matter, which should be meaningful to him. No-one requires an over-refined style of
writing these days, though it has to be said that very few people would
care to
wade through something so perversely slapdash as to be totally devoid
of either
artistic professionalism or meaningful content.
The greatest and most accessible works are usually found
somewhere in
between the two objective/subjective extremes.
However, if memory serves me well, I believe we were discussing
the
paradoxical relationship between sanity and insanity,
weren't we?
STUDENT:
Yes,
and I was somewhat puzzled by it actually. If
I
have understood you correctly, it would
appear that one can go insane in the world's eyes but not, apparently,
in
yours, seeing that one is already partly insane in consequence of the
intrinsic
dualism of life. Yet despite this, you
are prepared to accept both attitudes, depending on the context, as
equally
applicable.
PHILOSOPHER:
You
have understood perfectly mon
ami and,
as such, I must congratulate you! For
what one has to do, in this regard, is to forget the world's
classification of
insanity and concentrate upon the dual concepts of sanity and insanity
within
the individual, which is more or less tantamount to concentrating upon
the
theory of the regulative relationship between the conscious and
unconscious
parts of the psyche as defined by Carl Jung in various of his writings,
as well
as perceiving in the distinction between, for example, traditional
theology and
modern science a cleavage in the psyche between irrational and rational
predilections, the latter somewhat more evolved than the former. Naturally enough, this will also lead one to
forget the world's classification of sanity ... centred, as it usually
is, on
the relationship of the individual to society and the degree of his
integration
within it. For a being composed of both
tendencies can hardly be described in terms of one or the other, can he?
STUDENT:
Not
unless you remain consistent with your teachings and
call a man 'sane' in view of the fact that sanity is the positive, and
hence
principal, attribute of his dual integrity.
In other words, there is more sanity than insanity to life
simply
because the latter attribute, being comparatively negative, is
eternally
destined to play the secondary role, like the Father vis-à-vis the Son,
or, for
that matter, illusion vis-à-vis truth, evil vis-à-vis good, and sadness
vis-à-vis happiness?
PHILOSOPHER:
Excellent! So
now you are getting closer to the truth of why, for instance, it is
impossible
for a man to be wholly sane, rational, good, happy, etc., on account of
the
necessary interplay of their contrary polarities, and therefore why the
world
is what it is - i.e. apparently without sanity, reason, goodness,
happiness,
etc., when you happen to be in an insane, unreasonable, bad, or sad
mood and,
often enough, when someone else is, too!
Quite apart from the fact that without insanity there would be
no
sanity, one must give insanity its due as a means to making life
tolerable,
since without it one would virtually be unable to do anything.
STUDENT:
You
mean insanity makes it possible for us to take so
many things for granted, to go about our daily lives without all the
time
wondering what in God's name they're all about?
PHILOSOPHER:
Yes,
to a certain extent. I mean, just
look at yourself, at some of the
things you do, at many of the activities that you take for granted
without
particularly questioning them or waking-up to the realization of their
inherent
absurdity. I needn't run off a whole
list of them, but there are certainly enough things in this category to
keep us
talking for some time to come! For
example, take those musicians who play an avant-garde style of jazz on
their
saxophone. Now some of the sounds they
make with that instrument are so
disagreeable and
disjunctive as to cause one to doubt their sanity or integrity as
musicians. In fact, if a
state-registered lunatic was actually released from an asylum one day
specifically to play sax or piano or guitar in one of the more
avant-garde jazz
bands, do you imagine that he would sound any weirder or madder than
most of
his officially sane colleagues? No, a
wholly sane creature would be unable to live as a normal man. One needs a certain degree of insanity in
order to live at all. But in order to
live wisely, shrewdly, and 'sanely', one must keep the essential
duality of the
psyche in line with society's demands at large, not condition oneself
to
becoming a public nuisance by allowing one's irrational tendencies to
become
too concentrated around a single theme or context at the expense of
one's
overall psychic economy. Needless to say,
there are
many such public nuisances who, despite their strange behaviour
and even stranger opinions, are regarded as relatively sane in the
world's eyes
or, at any rate, in particular sections of it.
But that is quite another story, and one which we can safely
postpone
for another time. I trust, now, that you
will have something else to ask me? Or
perhaps I should ask you? For instance,
are you by any chance interested in getting rid of your fears?
STUDENT:
Yes,
I am actually!
But I don't honestly see how that can be done.
PHILOSOPHER:
Neither
do I. For
a man who deliberately strives to get rid
of his fears is as stupid as one who strives to rid himself of his
hopes. You will never succeed in doing so,
even if
you occasionally kid yourself, during a spell of apparent good fortune, that you did.
However, you have doubtless succeeded in outgrowing certain
fears and
replacing them with others?
STUDENT:
Yes,
I have to admit to that
fact. Though these
other fears
seem every bit as bad as the earlier ones.
PHILOSOPHER:
That
is only to be expected. For in order
to become fears at all, they
have to attain to a certain intensity of emotional effect.
So, in the long run, one fear is going to be
pretty much like another. But fears have
their use, all the same, since they help keep us in line.
STUDENT:
What,
exactly, do you mean by that?
PHILOSOPHER:
Simply
that they generally prevent us from doing
something extremely rash, like, for example, throwing oneself under a
car,
jumping out of a tenth-floor window, swearing at strangers in the
street,
breaking shop windows, throwing all of one's money away, or murdering
one's
neighbours. If you weren't secretly
afraid of what could happen to you, were you audacious enough to follow
one or
more of these regrettable courses, it is highly doubtful that you would
be here
today. You would almost certainly be
dead or, at the very least, in gaol.
Fortunately, however, you fear various things and situations as
much as
anyone else, and thereby safeguard yourself
against the
possibility of experiencing them. One
might contend that, except in exceptional cases or circumstances, fear
keeps us
fairly orderly and ensures that we do our best to keep others fairly
orderly as
well. As a singer in a rock band, for
instance, you would endeavour to sing as well as possible, in order to
win the
audience over and keep it on your side.
Fear of ridicule, in the event of a poor performance, would be
an
important consideration in that context.
So you would behave in an orderly fashion, in accordance with
the high
standards of the better rock bands, and sing well.
STUDENT:
Supposing
I am afraid of not fully satisfying a
particular young woman's sexual desires.
PHILOSOPHER:
Fear
of not satisfying her will motivate you to make
sure you do satisfy her, as well as satisfy yourself.
Without this fear regarding a particular
female, you might become over-complacent or sexually lazy, and lose her
to
somebody else.
STUDENT:
Then
I won't strive to eradicate my fears - at any rate,
not those kinds of fears which we have been discussing!
PHILOSOPHER:
You
will never succeed in doing so anyway, especially
with regard to that kind of fear which arises from an unforeseen
situation and
has absolutely nothing to do with any rational preconceptions one might
have. Like boredom, fear is one of those
things which, in all its manifold guises, we have to live with for our
own
good, since without it there would be no hope.
STUDENT:
And
without sadness?
PHILOSOPHER:
How
could one ever expect to be happy? In
reality, there is no more any such thing
as a 'happy man' per
se than a 'sad man' per se.
Throughout life man is inevitably both happy and
sad, for he would never know what happiness was unless he also had
regular
experience of sadness. Admittedly, some
people may seem happier than others and, conversely, some people sadder
than
others, since such distinctions often depend upon the individual's
temperament,
intelligence, beliefs, circumstances, profession, and facial
characteristics. But to pursue happiness
by attempting to
eradicate all sadness as a matter of policy, the way certain
philosophers would
have us do, is sheer folly, and only results in self-deception. We must accept them both, which, in any case,
is what most people do, considering that
they have
little or no choice in the matter.
Circumstances are continuously changing, and so, too, are our
respective
moods and opinions. When one is angry,
depressed, frustrated, bored, tired, or frightened, i.e. in the grip of
an evil
condition the negative vibrations of which are all too apparent, one
cannot
very well be happy, can one?
STUDENT:
Of
course not! But
then the evil condition passes after awhile and one generally feels
better
about life, particularly in the evening.
PHILOSOPHER:
True,
and from knowledge of this fact I have often
found it expedient to push oneself into
doing
something, even though one's mood doesn't really ordain or encourage it
at the
time, so that, with a little luck, one will be fully committed to this
activity
by the time one's mood changes for the better.
STUDENT:
Give
me an example.
PHILOSOPHER:
Well,
I may force myself to take a walk
somewhere. I leave home feeling somewhat
dejected at the prospect of having to catch a bus to another part of
town in
order simply to walk around the streets there for an hour or two. In this glum mood it occurs to me that I
haven't really got anything else to do;
that the bus ride is relatively expensive and takes me through a
dilapidated part of town; that I haven't got anyone to meet when I get
to my
destination; and that I know the streets there too thoroughly to be
greatly
thrilled by the prospect of traversing them once again.
It may even be overcast or drizzling as well.
Thus I leave home without feeling any real
enthusiasm for this excursion.
STUDENT:
What
time is this?
PHILOSOPHER:
About
6.00pm.
Prior to then I have been struggling to get my philosophy onto
paper all
day, so it is necessary for me to rest my eyes and brain, escape from
the
intellectual life in the oppressive atmosphere of my room, get some
exercise,
and just relax a little. So I set out
for this other part of town, which is usually more interesting to me
than the
part where I live, and when I eventually reach my destination, some
thirty
minutes later, it occurs to me that my glum mood is slowly changing for
the
better, since the new environment is beginning to work its spell on me
and I,
for the most part, am beginning to respond to it in a positive manner.
STUDENT:
So
you enjoy your walk.
PHILOSOPHER:
Precisely! If
the weather isn't particularly disagreeable, and I have acquired a
fairly
complacent conscience from a good day's work, I find that the new mood
made the
trip worthwhile. So I begin to enjoy
life again. Now if, by contrast, I had
set out in a good mood, there would have been a fair probability of
things
turning out the other way, that I would have reached my destination
only to
experience a negative mood. But such is
life, and what I have just been saying may in itself
be transmuted into yet other possibilities, some of which would
entirely
contradict it. As the
old adage goes: 'What one gains on the roundabout, one loses on the
swings.'
STUDENT:
Yes,
all this sounds very much like my experience too,
since the moods keep on changing. Yet
the irony of it all is that one can sometimes be quite happy walking
around in
the rain, provided that one was due for a positive mood change.
PHILOSOPHER:
To
be sure, which only goes to show
that weather and environment aren't always the principal reasons for
determining the nature of one's mood.
One can be as sad in the best of environments as happy in the
worst,
depending on the circumstances.
STUDENT:
Personally,
I'm not sure that I wouldn't be happier in a
medium-sized town blessed with clean streets, pleasant gardens, and
easy access
to the country, than in a gigantic city cursed with excessive traffic
pollution, overcrowded pavements, and graffiti-ridden walls! Surely there is something about the influence
of environment which transcends the transient prevalence of our various
moods?
PHILOSOPHER:
Of
course there is!
But it largely depends upon what one has been accustomed to,
what one
views as the golden mean or ideal, and the subsequent psychology
established in
consequence of the tension - or lack of it - between this ideal and the
reality
confronting one. For example if, as a
provincial, you are thoroughly convinced that the big city isn't for
you, then
you would be quite foolish to remain in it.
Yet this problem depends so much on the individual, as on
individual
circumstances, that it is really a matter for him to decide for himself. Let no-one trick you into believing that what
is good for one person is necessarily just as good for another! If you seriously believe that moving to a
smaller town will make you happier overall, I can see no reasons -
apart from
the obvious material ones - why you shouldn't do so.
But living in a big city can be as much fun,
if not more so, than living in the most picturesque town or village,
and, once
one has grown accustomed to living in the city, it is unlikely that one
would
ever want to move down to some less artificial environment which, by
contrast,
could well appear extremely boring.
However, now that we have dealt with another subject, is there
anything
else I can do for you?
STUDENT
(Consulting his notes afresh): In point of fact, I
had intended to ask you this earlier but we or, rather, you jumped the
gun, as
it were. Do you believe in sexual
equality or, put more bluntly, in the notion that men and women are
equal, or,
in light of your dualistic philosophy, is it simply a delusion which
has been
taken too seriously in recent decades?
PHILOSOPHER:
I
suppose if you were an old-fashioned misogynistic
male, it could seem such. But I can't,
in all honesty, believe that to be the case since, in attempting to
answer your
question obliquely, I assume that a majority of young women usually
refrain
from being unduly competitive with men in the interests of their
intrinsic
femininity. When women are pretty, they
have a natural predilection for the decorative and supportive role
which, in
accordance with the fundamental nature of their sex, is only proper to
their
psychology and interests as women.
For the world is always geared to men on account of the positivity of the male in relation to the
negativity of the
female, a fact which will still remain the same whether you endeavour
to turn
the world upside down in theory or not, since it is ruled by practice. So, with few exceptions, it is usually the
male who plays the leading role and the female the secondary one. Now if attractive young women ran the risk of
becoming less attractive as women from taking too much power
and
responsibility upon themselves, I am quite convinced that, in nine
cases out of
ten, they would reject it and revert to charming or seducing males
instead. As a rule, it appears to be the
older or less attractive women who are more willing to compete with men
in the
world of professional responsibility, whether in business, law, the
arts,
medicine, or whatever. Though there are
always exceptions to every rule.
STUDENT:
Therefore,
according to that theory, which didn't fully
answer my question, a majority of the really influential women in
literature,
art, music, business, politics, the civil service, the armed forces,
the
police, the teaching profession, etc., are likely to be less attractive
as
women than their less ambitious counterparts?
PHILOSOPHER:
In
general.
Though perhaps the really powerful women are closer to being
female
hermaphrodites than might at first meet the eye! I
mean,
just as some men are effeminate and
rather subservient, so there are women who are manly and domineering to
a
degree which makes them more powerful than the weaker men.
The modern world is amply stocked with such
paradoxically androgynous cases, and it is a well-known fact of Jungian
psychology that, after they have passed their middle years, people
become
increasingly like the opposite sex to which they literally belong, both
physically and mentally. However, to
answer your question more fully, the evidence of the senses would
indicate that
men and women aren't literally equal, or the same.
But I don't see why that fact should
necessarily preclude women from being granted equal employment
opportunities to
men and paid a similar wage, relative to age and experience, for a
similar
day's work. Discrimination in such
matters is largely obsolete these days, though there are still some
employers
who, for one reason or another, openly discriminate against women in
slavish
deference to male traditions. Naturally,
there are some things which women can't do as well as men on account,
primarily,
of their slighter builds - like playing football, rugby, and cricket,
or boxing
and wrestling, or throwing the hammer and putting the shot, or playing
drums,
electric guitar, electric bass, and certain other instruments in a hard
rock or
modern jazz context, or manipulating heavy weapons, lifting heavy
weights,
driving heavy vehicles, and doing various other kinds of heavy or
dangerous
manual work. But even so, there are
probably very few heterosexual men in the world who would prefer women
to be
capable of doing all or most of these sorts of things at the expense of
such natural
endowments as beauty, elegance, and charm.
So a supportive role would still appear to be the prerogative of
all
those naturally attractive young women who, even in an age of rampant
materialism, are more interested in becoming wives and mothers than in
advancing their careers.
STUDENT:
Therefore,
though men and women are physically unequal,
they should be treated as socially and professionally equal?
PHILOSOPHER:
Providing
the circumstances warrant it, I don't see
why not. For, although men and women are
made of different stuff and have predilections relevant to their
respective
sexes - men being the positive and hence impregnating pole of a dual
integrity,
while women are the negative pole which is imposed upon with due regard
to its
wishes - they are equally important to the survival of mankind and
shouldn't be
regarded as existing in an inferior/superior relationship.
When you fall in love with a woman you aren't
thinking in terms of inferiority then.
Quite the contrary, you absolutely adore her, and would be more
inclined
to regard her as a sort of superior creature to yourself than vice
versa. Admittedly, you may, as an
individual, have
cogent reasons for being a misogynist or even a homosexual, but it is
altogether doubtful that you will ever have cogent reasons for
considering women
biologically inferior - other, that is, than in the strictly
philosophical
sense whereby they form the negative pole in a duality where the
positive one
will usually dominate. Strength,
however, isn't everything, and neither is beauty! If
we
are superior to them in certain
respects, we are quite inferior to them in certain others.
And if they have any talent for charm, it is
obviously in their best interests to dedicate themselves primarily to
the art
of being a woman, which, for a majority of them, has never proved too
difficult
anyway. In all probability, the really
attractive women will stand to gain more from being relatively unambitious, both commercially and
professionally, than
they would otherwise gain by competing with men. For
arduous
competition can quickly detract
from a woman's natural charms, you know, turning her into someone who
is
anything but attractive, and thus preventing her from properly
fulfilling
herself as a woman. However, we
have discussed sexual equality long enough and must not allow the fact
of
social equality between the sexes in terms of employment, housing,
democratic
rights, etc., to blind us to the personal inequality which exists
between men
and women - and, indeed, men and men as well as women and women - in
both
physical and psychological terms. But
perhaps we can talk some more tomorrow?
*
*
*
PHILOSOPHER:
So
what can I do for you today?
STUDENT
(Consulting his notes): I would like to know what
you consider to be the main evils of the philosophical life?
PHILOSOPHER:
Well
now, there are undoubtedly quite a few! Though
I
suppose one of the most common
'evils', as you somewhat harshly put it, involves one's committing
thoughts to
paper without really paying that much attention to their essential
nature.
STUDENT:
Can
you be more specific?
PHILOSOPHER:
Oh,
endeavouring to escape from boredom, unhappiness,
the outside world, self-doubts, emotional conflicts, etc., through a
relatively
superficial because over-spontaneous employment of words.
This is a grave and common danger to all who
wield the pen, especially in philosophical terms, since, as we both
know, the
pen can be mightier than the sword in its long-term effects on society.
STUDENT:
I
wish I could believe that!
PHILOSOPHER:
Well,
mistaken thoughts have still been the ruination
of many an earnest intellectual, politician, soldier, teacher, priest,
and
artist, to name some of the more prominent categories of human
endeavour.
STUDENT:
Do
you sometimes commit words to paper without having
thought very carefully about them and weighed the possibility of their
being
misleading, simply because you, too, are anxious to set the pen in
motion and
thereby escape from the tedium of a physically inactive existence
through the
medium of a degree of practical philosophical preoccupation?
PHILOSOPHER:
To
be honest, I sometimes do. Though I am
also shrewd and knowing enough to
revise my writings fairly extensively, in the interests of a more
credible not
to say professional presentation. If,
during the course of your intellectual travels, you have heard the
teaching
profession described as a necessary evil, it may not surprise you to
learn that
philosophers sometimes think of themselves in such terms as well;
though,
between ourselves, there is little reason for us to suppose that other
types of
writer are necessarily any better. As
beings of good and evil, truth and illusion, reasonableness and
unreasonableness, cleverness and stupidity, profundity and
superficiality, wisdom
and foolishness, strength and weakness, etc., we are all prone, in
varying
degrees, to similar failings. The
philosopher, with his love of wisdom, is simply more intellectually
conspicuous
than most other men. He sticks his neck
out in the honourable names of truth, knowledge, wisdom, and reason,
but if
these qualities also involve him in a recognition and, within limits,
an
acceptance of man's intermittent capacity for illusion, ignorance,
folly, and
irrationality - then so be it! One will
see that his 'truth' is more comprehensive, and even compassionate,
than the
lopsided truths of a majority of his philosophical precursors.
STUDENT:
Ah,
this sounds remarkably similar to what you were
arguing yesterday, about the wise life incorporating an acceptance of
both
wisdom and
folly, and therefore not being a futile exercise in one's vainly
striving to eradicate the latter.
PHILOSOPHER:
Yes,
my 'truth' is also double-barrelled, so to
speak. It incorporates an acceptance of
illusion, i.e. the necessity of one's having illusions for the sake of
one's
truths. Now although I am essentially
geared to truth, on account of the positivity
of its
relationship within the illusion/truth dichotomy, I have as many
illusions as
truths, of that you can rest assured.
STUDENT:
Such
as?
PHILOSOPHER:
Oh,
but a man can't really know all his illusions,
since he would then become disillusioned with them and not disposed, in
consequence, to maintaining them as illusions any longer!
STUDENT:
Then
what kind of illusions do you suppose
you are
likely to have, if that is not too hypothetical a question?
PHILOSOPHER:
Well,
I may have a false opinion of myself on various
issues. I may think more of my
intellectual abilities than I really should, in view of a variety of
intellectual shortcomings which I am either loathe or unable to
recognize. I may imagine a particular
talent in myself
which, in reality, isn't really there. I
may consider myself to be a better philosopher than various people who
are
really better philosophers than me. I
may be entirely wrong to consider myself a serious philosopher in the
first
place. I may make statements which seem
perfectly true to me but which, in reality, are really quite false. I may have a false opinion of someone
else. I may be inclined to overrate the
talents of certain artists, musicians, actors, or writers, and,
conversely, to
underrate those of certain other artists, musicians, actors, or writers. I may be inclined to denounce the theories of
various other thinkers simply because one of my 'favourite'
philosophers did,
without fully realizing that that is really all I am doing. I may be inclined to imagine myself a
worthwhile artist when, in reality, I lack the necessary ability, and,
conversely, I may be wrong to imagine that I lack the necessary ability
to be a
worthwhile artist. I may think that I am
better-looking than I really am or, by contrast, that I am worse
looking than
is really the case. I may think a
certain woman doesn't like me when, in reality, she does and,
conversely, I may
think a certain woman likes me who, in reality, holds rather an
unflattering
opinion of me. I may consider myself to
be less intelligent than I really am or, by contrast, to be more
intelligent
than is really the case. I may imagine
myself to be a victim of someone's malevolence when there is no clear
evidence
of it and, conversely, I may imagine myself to be the recipient of
someone's
benevolence when benevolence was the last thing on his/her mind. I may have a mistaken notion as to how a
certain
foreign word should be pronounced and, conversely, I may think I am
wrong to
pronounce a certain foreign word the way I do when, in reality, I am
pronouncing it correctly. I may
accentuate a word one way which should really be accentuated another
way and,
by contrast, I may find myself criticizing someone for accentuating a
word
differently from how I believe it should be accentuated when, in point
of fact,
he is accentuating it correctly and I am simply deluded.
I may think it is easier to get published in
this country than in fact it is and, conversely, I may imagine
publishers to be
more unwilling to publish certain types of books than in fact they are. I may think I am spelling a certain word
correctly when, in reality, I have spelt it incorrectly, and so on....
I
suppose the list could continue to flourish for some time, were
I seriously to set about confessing to all of my potential or possible
illusions! Yet these tendencies are
often dependent upon the nature of the mood one is in at any given
time, the
particular context in which one lives, that is to say whether alone or
in
company, the psychic changes one undergoes, the state of one's health,
the
nature of one's daily pursuits, and one's powers of analysis and
introspection,
so it is quite impossible to ever entirely master them, to know them
for
illusions and then foolishly strive to eradicate them ... doubtless
under
pressure of another illusion. But we all
suffer throughout life from our illusions, just as we likewise suffer
from our truths,
and whether our 'truths' are sometimes illusions or our 'illusions'
sometimes
truths, there is no altering that fact.
If you could get rid of all your illusions, you would quickly
lose all
or most of your truths. So consider
yourself fortunate that you can't!
STUDENT:
Therefore
people are wrong to consider themselves
imperfect because of their faults or hypothetical faults, such as
illusions,
stupidities, fears, doubts, and superficialities?
PHILOSOPHER:
They
are philosophically wrong to consider themselves
spiritually imperfect on account of the intermittent prevalence of such
negative attributes, because these attributes aren't isolated obstacles
to
human perfection but the very things which guarantee
the
intermittent prevalence of one's positive attributes - namely truth,
cleverness, hope, certainty, profundity, etc. - and thus constitute an
overall
part of one's psychic integrity.
Whenever you hear a so-called well-educated or enlightened
person
bemoaning the apparent fact that none of us is perfect, you should
dismiss him
as a deluded ignoramus, since he is undoubtedly ignorant of our
spiritual
integrity. In general, a man is
spiritually perfect and, to varying extents, physically imperfect. If you have faults, in the proper sense of
that term, they are fundamentally physical.
But they are not superfluous, since, by their existence, they
guarantee
our spiritual perfection.
STUDENT:
Because
body and spirit are antithetical, the one is
imperfect and the other perfect! To be
sure, you are no sham teacher, but a great enlightener!
PHILOSOPHER:
Personally,
I don't think too highly of the
sycophantic arts, since I have my own negative attributes to live with,
including stupidity, superficiality, illusion, etc.
When a man comes to realize his dualistic
perfection, he also comes to accept his darker side, or shadow-self,
and this
side duly informs him that his perfection will lead him to make
mistakes, tell
unconscious lies, mislead people, and commit much folly over the years. So be on your guard against me, my young
friend! I have taught you to be cautious
of philosophers, to regard them as men rather than gods.
Perfect but not infallible - a paradox if
ever there was one!
STUDENT:
You
remind me of Nietzsche when you speak like that.
PHILOSOPHER:
To
be sure, Nietzsche was a great teacher, a
tremendous intellect, a courageous spirit, and a philosophical
revolutionary. But he was no more
infallible than you or I or anyone else.
There are many mistaken assumptions and contentions in
Nietzsche's
works, and you would certainly be led astray if you allowed yourself to
be
fooled by them. In a sense, he was as
perfect a spirit, prior to his collapse, as ever lived, but a great
spirit and,
like all such spirits, capable of propagating worse mistakes than
lesser
men. Do you disbelieve me, you who are
still a prey to the lure of great philosophers and not yet your own
philosopher?
STUDENT:
No,
I don't disbelieve you. Though
I find it rather
difficult, in view of my admiration for Nietzsche's immense
philosophical
achievements, to be overly strict with myself here.
But you are doubtless correct to advocate a
certain amount of caution, since Nietzsche's writings have been
shamefully
exploited and corrupted, to the ultimate detriment of European man. One need only think of the Nazis.
PHILOSOPHER:
To
be sure, Nietzsche may have been of some use to
them in terms of stirring-up a glorification of war and struggle. But as for such concomitant factors as the
'Master Race' ethos, anti-Semitism, imperialism, occultism, state
worship, and
the systematic undermining of advanced culture, it is altogether
doubtful that
the Nazis could have derived much encouragement from him at all! Didn't Nietzsche declare himself to be an
enemy of the Germans time-and-time again?
Certainly, he was an enemy of the German imperialism of his own
day, the
gradual ascendancy of the Prussian-dominated Bismarckian
state, with its mounting preoccupation with industrialism, militarism,
nationalism, politicism, etc., to the
detriment of
higher culture. It would indeed be a
grave mistake to assume that Nietzsche had a profound influence on the
policies
of Nazi
STUDENT:
And
weren't such writers as James Joyce, D.H. Lawrence,
John Cowper Powys, Knut Hamsun,
Henry Miller, Hermann Hesse, and W.B.
Yeats also
deeply influenced by him?
PHILOSOPHER:
So
I believe, though I would hesitate to regard them
as socialists. For the most part, they
were much too preoccupied with individual, spiritual, moral, and
literary
values to justify any such political description. However,
it
often happens that an author
receives a label for a particular work or stance which he subsequently
grows
out of, only to discover that he is still popularly associated with it
in later
years.
STUDENT:
An
unpleasant discovery, I shouldn't wonder.
PHILOSOPHER:
Indeed! Although every
occupation has its drawbacks, including the literary
one. An author acquires a
reputation, let us say, for a given philosophical contention, like the
interdependence of opposites, and then a fair proportion of the reading
public
continue to identify him with it even after he has modified or outgrown
it some
years later. You write something which
seems quite credible to you at the time, only to look back on it with
horror or regret,
at
a later
date, that you could have committed such a flawed idea to paper in the
first
place.
STUDENT:
Presumably
because you have evolved in the interim and
acquired a deeper or truer perspective in consequence?
PHILOSOPHER:
Precisely!
Because you have 'woken up' to the fact that you were previously
asleep
to something you blandly took for granted, and have accordingly become
disillusioned with it. We are probably
asleep together now, because we allow ourselves free play in this
discussion
and aren't unduly concerned by the likelihood that such an event may
cause us a
degree of mutual embarrassment or even bewilderment in the future. Perhaps, by then, you will be through with
the whole idea of interviewing philosophers and I shall be through with
the
idea of allowing myself to be imposed upon in such a way.
Maybe you will have stopped reading
philosophy and I shall have stopped writing or speaking it. We will both have 'woken up' to new
possibilities and, having changed, we shall then be in a position to
return to
sleep again.
STUDENT:
You
amuse me.
PHILOSOPHER:
I
am glad to hear it, since philosophy has too often
been an extremely glum affair, like the philosophers themselves. There have been too many weeping
philosophers, too many stoics, ascetics, cynics, and pessimists of one
kind or
another since the dawn of philosophy.
But we don't need another Heraclitus
now, nor
another Marcus Aurelius, Epictitus,
Pascal, Spinoza,
Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard, Spengler,
Sartre, or what
have you! God knows, Nietzsche was right,
for all his faults, to be exuberant! At
least he doesn't bore one. Philosophy
requires a certain amount of humour and ironic self-detachment now more
than
ever. In fact, I think Plutarch, Montaigne, Emerson, Carlyle, Nietzsche, John
Cowper Powys, Bertrand
Russell, and Albert Camus are the kinds of
philosophers the intellectual world has greater need of, if it isn't to
sink
further under the insupportable burden of depressing philosophy!
STUDENT:
Perhaps
that is one of the reasons why philosophy is generally
so little read these days?
PHILOSOPHER:
You
may be right, though I rather think that the
complexity, obscurity, obfuscation, compartmentalization, and
esotericism of so
much of it is really more to blame for this lamentable state-of-affairs
than the
absence of humour. Like poetry,
philosophy has tended to be a minority and even an elitist pursuit,
which, in a
way, is rather a regrettable situation.
But if society requires people to stand over machines in a
factory all
day, to dig trenches in the road, punch holes in tickets, sweep the
streets,
deliver milk, file letters, or put peas into cans, then you can't
reasonably
expect them to show much interest in the works of Locke, Kant, Hume,
Berkeley,
Heidegger, Bergson, or Jaspers in the
evening. What is good for one man,
remember, isn't
necessarily good for another! We may
live in the age of 'the herd', the great democratic collectivity,
but, without it, there would be no higher culture at all.
Noble and plebeian - an indispensable
antithesis! To be sure, anyone who
condemns 'the herd' unwittingly condemns himself as one who has
transcended it,
been fostered on its shoulders, and thereby exists, in his relatively
noble
integrity, because
of it, like a flower growing from the earth. There
are
no superfluous men because,
irrespective of what Nietzsche may have had to say on the subject, all
men have
a task relative to their capabilities and, as such, they slot into the
framework of society as a whole. Nietzsche
probably knew this as well as anybody, deep down, but that didn't
prevent an
irrational prejudice from obscuring the light of truth from time to
time. For man, remember, is not
a
reasonable creature; he is only capable of reason!
STUDENT:
So
if you are into the notion of superfluous men in consequence
of having read books like Thus
Spoke
Zarathustra,
there is every chance that you have been led astray by one of
Nietzsche's
fallacies concerning 'the many-too-many'.
PHILOSOPHER:
Yes,
but don't forget, my good friend, that fallacies
of whatever sort contribute, fundamentally, to our overall perfection
as human
beings. We may disagree with Nietzsche
on a variety of issues, we may even be able to prove him wrong, but
that
doesn't give us the right to condemn him out-of-hand, since to do so
would be
to turn our backs on the metaphysical legitimacy of fallacious
reasoning and to
seek the impossible - namely, the faultlessly lopsided.
This is what I have to teach you, this is
what I want you to understand. No longer
imagine that a philosopher has failed for not having sufficiently
adhered to
reason, truth, goodness, etc. He has not
failed! No longer imagine that a
philosopher is imperfect for having committed a given number of
unintentional
fallacies or sophistries to paper. He is
not imperfect! If the fallacy lies
anywhere, it lies with you for expecting the impossible - an illusionless truth, all truth, and nothing but
the truth,
when you are just as incapable of achieving that as anyone else. Naturally, your mistaken viewpoint is just as
legitimate, in the final analysis, as the fallacious contentions of the
philosopher under scrutiny. For how can
I not expect you to be as spiritually perfect as him, and thus entitled
to your
fallacies? But perhaps, in assimilating
all this information, you will allow your foolishness, ignorance,
malice,
superficiality, etc., free play elsewhere, becoming wiser on this issue
and
simultaneously less wise or even more foolish on certain other issues? That, however, is something about which I
cannot be absolutely certain. But if you
have really understood what I have just said, then it isn't altogether
impossible. After all, you have all the
makings of a 'perfect' philosopher!