Op. 06
THE ILLUSORY TRUTH
Multigenre Philosophy
Copyright © 2013 John O'Loughlin
_________________
CONTENTS
PART ONE: APHORISTIC ESSAYS
1. The Philosopher as Man, Not Machine
2. Two Types of Thinker
3. Thinking Should Be Difficult
4. A Justification of Boredom
5. Ultimate Justice
6. No Escaping Evil
7. The Way it Has To Be
8. No Hope without Fear
9. Twenty Mistaken Ideas
10. Slightly Existential
11. Words as Our 'Reality'
12. Partly Our Creation
13. Truths but No Truth
14. Reality and Realities
15. Human Diversity
16. No Two Alike
17. Time Belongs to Man
18. Inevitably Unreasonable
19. Puppets of Life
20. The Negative Root
21. The Struggle for Happiness
22. Work and Play
23. No Freedom without Bondage
24. From Winter to Autumn
25. No 'Mother Nature'
26. Male and Female Pride
27. Against Folly
28. Suspended Judgement
29. Against Reincarnation
30. Superstition Universal
31. The End of the World
32. Art as Ideality
33. Great Art
34. No Health without Disease
35. Illness No Objection
36. The 'Plimsoll Line' of Sleep
37. A Wider View of Vice
38. Misused Concepts
39. Against Racial Inequality
40. The Transience of Death
41. Philosophy verses Insular Intolerance
42. Individual Wisdom
43. The Meaning and Purpose of Life
44. The Inferior Negative
45. Four Categories
46. Negatives Serve
47. Successful Failures
48. Positively Selfish
49. A Posthumous B.C.
50. Schismatic Christianity
51. Live Symbols
52. Interplanetary Equilibrium
53. Magnetic Reciprocities
54. Universe or Universes
55. Between Good and Evil
PART TWO: ESSAYISTIC APHORISMS
PART THREE: APHORISMS (MAXIMS)
___________________
PART ONE:
APHORISTIC ESSAYS
THE PHILOSOPHER AS MAN, NOT MACHINE: How often should a
philosopher actually allow himself to think, if he is to remain a relatively
sane, active, healthy individual, and not degenerate into some kind of
impersonal thinking machine? Should he
go out of his way to think objectively when there is no apparent necessity for
him to do so (as, for example, when he isn't officially working), to drive his
thought patterns over the bounds of moderation to such an extent that he defies
the urge to variety in life and is eventually consumed, like Nietzsche, by an
obsession with thought, becomes saddled, as it were, with a plethora of
intellectual superfluities?
Undoubtedly, a man who
regards himself as a thinker must think sometimes. But an over-fastidious approach to thinking,
an over-obdurate inclination to think at any cost could very soon render him
anomalous, foolish, trivial, stolid, boring, and unbalanced - to name just a
few things. For whether or not the most
thought-obsessed people realize it, there is more to life than thinking, and a
need certainly exists in people for adherence to a given physiological
situation - as, for example, in refraining from thought when the need to do so
is patently obvious.
If, therefore, a
so-called thinker is to avoid becoming an intellectual crank, he must respect
his periodically natural inclination to thoughtlessness and not endeavour, by
contrast, to continue thinking when the energy or requirement to do so is no
longer there. Otherwise he may
subsequently degenerate, if he doesn't suffer a mental breakdown, into some
kind of intellectual freak - in other words, into someone who imagines that he
ought to think as much as possible, no matter what the
circumstances, in order to remain a philosopher, a man of genius, a cut above
the common herd. Philosophy, however,
refuses to take such nonsense seriously!
For the true philosopher always goes his way as a man, not
as a thinking machine.
TWO TYPES OF THINKER: It is wrong to assume that a man obsessed
with thought is necessarily a thinker, a philosopher, a genius. For when a man is compelled to think out of
habit from fear of not thinking, of not appearing to be enough of a thinker in
his own eyes, there is a reasonable chance that he is less a philosopher than a
dupe of his own illusions, a slave of a mentality which assumes it necessary
for a thinker to think as much as possible, regardless of the subject or
context, if he is to remain a philosopher and not degenerate into an average
mind. The idea of thinking, in such a head,
is ultimately more important than what is
actually being thought about.
For it must be admitted,
from the converse standpoint, that a genuine thinker - a man, in other words,
who thinks not merely for the sake of flattering his ego or filling a vacuum
but, more importantly, in order to discover something new about the world he
lives in and the best methods of adjusting himself to it - will always stop
himself thinking beyond a certain length of time simply because experience and
common sense will have taught him that that is the best course to follow if he
is to remain relatively natural, sane, perceptive, lucid, and mentally
resilient. As a thinker, in this
context, he will know that his chief duty is towards himself, and not only for
himself but inevitably for the sake of other people as well; that his
intelligence should therefore be used to his advantage - as, unfortunately, is
rarely the case with the other type of thinker, a type who, obsessed by the
urge to think, is essentially a pathological phenomenon, scarcely a man of
wisdom. For philosophy should have
earnest connections, after all, with the art of living wisely.
THINKING SHOULD BE DIFFICULT: It is just as well that, for the
vast majority of people, so-called objective thinking is so difficult,
that even those of us who habitually regard ourselves as 'thinkers' are
normally compelled to fight and sweat for our deepest thoughts. Were this not the case, were we not the
hard-pressed slaves of thought, it is highly probable that thinking alone would
preoccupy us, and to such an extent and with such intensity that we would be
left with little time or inclination for anything else.
Indeed, those of us who
make a daily commitment to putting thoughts on paper are only too aware of how
difficult serious thinking really is, and consequently of how pointless it
would be for us to complain against this fact or to criticize ourselves for not
thinking well enough. Yet if work were
always easy, if brilliant ideas invariably came to us without any difficulty,
what challenge would there be in doing it?
And how many of us would really care to have above-average thoughts
flowing through our heads all day anyway, thoughts which never allow us to rest
but, as though prompted by a psychic conveyor-belt, continue to plague our
consciousness from morning till night?
If, as Bergson contended, the brain really is a limiting
device, an organ which, in addition to storing verbal concepts, usually
prevents us from thinking too much too easily and too continuously, then it is
just as well that it actually works, that we aren't subjected to an unceasing
barrage of brilliant and highly irrelevant ideas all day, but are forced to put
some effort into extracting any worthwhile thoughts from it. Was this not the case, I rather doubt that I
should have found either the time or the inclination to record such seemingly
gratified thoughts as these!
A JUSTIFICATION OF BOREDOM: If man is protected against his
thoughts by generally finding it difficult to think (by which I mean to think
objectively, constructively, and continuously - in other words, above the usual
plane of subjective considerations, incidental fragments, brief recollections,
disconnected words, casual street-sign readings, intuitive insights, etc., and
beyond the moods or situations when thinking of one kind or another comes most
naturally to him), then one might justifiably contend that he is protected
against too much mental and physical inertia by the intermittent prevalence of
boredom, that scourge of the idle.
To most people,
particularly the more intelligent ones, boredom is a distinctly disagreeable
condition, an emptiness usually leading to self-contempt, which suffices to
goad them into doing something absorbing, into losing and rediscovering
themselves in some preoccupation, some form of activity or stimulant. Now if boredom had absolutely no place in
their lives, if mere existence sufficed to content them (as appears to be the
case with a majority of animals), what do you suppose would happen? Do you suppose, for instance, that they would
really do anything, would, in fact, be capable of living at all? The prevalence of hunger, thirst, lust,
changes in the weather, etc., would doubtless oblige them to satisfy their
respective physical needs as quickly and efficiently as possible. But, having done so, what would they then
have to live for afterwards?
Without boredom there
would have been no civilization - no art, science, religion, politics,
philosophy, music, sport, travel, evolution.
In fact, without boredom there would probably have been nothing of any
consequence whatsoever. For boredom is
akin to an eternal whip!
ULTIMATE JUSTICE: Whenever something happens it happens for a good
reason. Once a cause is committed to an
effect there is no turning it back.
There is no such thing as an accident which should have happened but
didn't. A near-miss is a near-miss and
not an accident, even if the potential of an accident existed for a time. An accident which should happen will always
happen if the circumstances demand it.
Therefore whenever a
person secretly or openly condemns nature for its apparent injustice, for the
fact, let us say, that lightning struck a tree and killed someone sheltering
beneath its branches, or that a flood swept over a town and killed people and
damaged property, or that a volcano erupted and spilled molten lava down onto
some nearby townsfolk - whenever, I say, a person condemns nature on these and
similar accounts, understandable though his condemnation may be, he is
unwittingly turning his back on justice, on the justice of a world which would
seem to be saying: This cause is bound to have a specific effect; if people are
in the way of it, then that is their fault.
'A' must lead to 'B' whatever the consequences or, put mathematically, 2
x 2 = 4 and not 5, 6, or 7. If you
happen to be sheltering beneath the branches of a tree when lightning strikes
it (and the lightning couldn't help arising), then you must suffer the
consequences. If, by any chance, you
sometime happen to be in the path of oncoming lava, you must now accept the
fact that it wasn't necessarily destined to kill anyone but will only kill or
maim people if they are rash, unfortunate, ignorant, or brave enough to dwell
under a volcano's shadow. To suggest
that the eruption shouldn't occur would be as unreasonable as to suggest that
mutually attractive men and women shouldn't fall in love, or that 2 x 2
shouldn't equal 4, or that a poison berry shouldn't prove highly detrimental to
its eater. For whenever something
happens, it does so for a good reason.
An earthquake, for
example, which has to occur because secretly engendered by some planetary
necessity which, unbeknown to man, simultaneously safeguards and maintains the
overall stability of the planet, is not by any means guaranteed to occur in
close proximity to human dwellings. But
if it does so, one ought to bear in mind that (1) it had to occur in
consequence of a combination of subterranean planetary influences; (2) the
people killed and/or injured by it will normally represent only a tiny
percentage of the total human population of the globe, a percentage which will
either die or suffer injury as a sacrifice, so to speak, for the overall
welfare of mankind in general; (3) these same people might not have been
afflicted by it had they built their dwellings elsewhere, or if technology had
evolved an efficient early-warning system which could pinpoint the anticipated
place of the quake and thereby give inhabitants there sufficient time to
abandon their dwellings and move to the nearest safety zone.
Like molten lava,
hurricanes, floods, typhoons, and lightning, the earthquake kills
indiscriminately, but it only kills what is in its way. Hideous as these things usually are, a
majority of us would probably prefer the occasional emergence of potentially
death-engendering planetary phenomena to the wholesale destruction of the planet
itself brought about by a gigantic explosion in the bowls of the earth. Large-scale explosions fostered by man are
undoubtedly dreadful enough. But
experience of a gigantic 'natural' explosion which ultimately tore the entire
planet apart would be far worse! For
where the elements rule, the elements decide.
If earthquakes,
typhoons, volcanic eruptions, etc., were not necessary, they wouldn't
happen. Admittedly, science can give man
the advantage of anticipating them and even of directing the force of various
outbreaks of natural violence into a particular area or spot, as with lightning
conductors. But a civilization which got
to a point of trying to prevent the emergence of such phenomena could
eventually find itself paying the price of frustrating a series of
comparatively minor disturbances by subsequently bringing upon itself the
horrendous devastation of a major one.
For sooner or later a phenomenon which has been frustrated or repressed
too long will explode with a force that would have made the force of its
previously unchecked explosion seem relatively harmless.
Now what applies to the
external world of nature doubtless applies no less to the internal world of the
psyche, where neuroses and psychoses are the price one must occasionally pay
for one's sanity.
NO ESCAPING EVIL: To a certain extent every age turns a blind eye
towards most of its chief evils. One of
the main reasons for this is undoubtedly helplessness, but others also include
indifference, laziness, societal hostility, class rivalry, moral hypocrisy,
ignorance, lack of imagination, and - probably most common of all - the inborn
inclination of a majority of people to take matters more or less for granted.
Knowing this to be the
case, however, one should nonetheless endeavour to attribute a reasonable
justification to this string of evils (whatever they happen to be and wherever
they happen to flourish). For not only
do they constitute a very common, perennial, and ineradicable
element in the life of a nation at any given time but, more importantly, they
also constitute a very worthwhile element in the protection of that nation's
psychic equilibrium, since without its evil side it would have nothing good to
boast of, and therefore be unable to exist.
Paradoxical though it may seem, it is important
to note that evils of one kind or another will always exist, no matter what the
gonfalon, for the good of the people.
The assertion, however, that they don't exist when it is patently
obvious they do, is in itself a clear example of a particular kind of evil
which is fairly constant among certain individuals and institutions in every
age.
Granted, then, that an
age may be justified in turning a 'blind eye' to most of its chief evils, in
pretending them not to exist and quite often in not knowing of their existence,
it nonetheless has to be said that under no circumstances would it be justified
in categorically denying their existence, in asserting them to be a
figment of the popular imagination, since such an absurd attitude would amount
to a veritable refutation of all life.
It would, in fact, amount to something gravely unjustifiable in a world
where antitheses are ever the mean!
The fact, however, that
society is relatively integrated in every age stands to reason. For no matter what the situation, no matter
how bad things may appear, good and evil must always co-exist in various
degrees and guises, according to whether a nation is at peace or at war, even
if a number of the standards concerning the respective criteria of good and
evil are constantly being changed or modified in order to meet the demands of
the occasion. What man ought to know, and too often
forgets (though this is probably just as well), is that nature is ultimately
wiser than he, that he is the product of nature and consequently is guided and
motivated by it in every age, irrespective of what the chief political, social,
religious, moral, economic, agricultural, or industrial priorities may happen
to be at any given time.
The endeavour to create
a perfect human society is inevitably a gross self-deception. For man can never attain to a society where,
presumably, everyone will be equal and all the assumed evil elements be
eliminated, when the essential nature of existence demands our acceptance of
and acquiescence in the continuous interplay of polar opposites: good and evil,
rich and poor, truth and illusion, ruling and ruled, noble and plebeian, etc.,
under virtually every gonfalon throughout history. Were mankind ever destined to arrive at such
a 'perfect society', it would undoubtedly constitute something distinctly
imperfect, anomalous, and insufferable.
In sum, one can only rob Peter to pay Paul.
THE WAY IT HAS TO BE: Every age contains its quota of horrors,
exploitations, superstitions, taboos, stupidities, illusions, crimes, diseases,
accidents, mistakes, etc., and the modern age is clearly no exception. Assuming the human kind are not eradicated in
any future world war, it is quite conceivable that the more intelligent members
of generations to come may look back in
dread, amazement, and even bewilderment at many of the circumstances which a
majority of people take for granted today, just as, in focusing their critical
attention upon a number of the (to them) most unacceptable aspects of the
Victorian Age, people today often tend to disapprove of child labour, slave
labour, the imprisonment of children, compulsory naval and military service,
birching, hanging, and the extreme levels of social deprivation which existed
among the very poor in relation to education, housing, sanitation, health, diet,
employment, and earnings.
But the more fortunate
members of a future generation - one existing, say, about a hundred years from
now - may well have sound reason to be shocked, surprised, bewildered, or even
amused by knowledge of the fact that a majority of late-twentieth-century
people lived quite complacently in an age of widespread pollution, excessive
noise, traffic congestion, overcrowding, cigarette smoking, drug addiction,
alcoholism, cancer, the five-day week, metropolitan loneliness, tinned food,
bottled milk, capitalist/socialist antagonism, the threat of nuclear war,
religious anachronisms, life-imprisonment, impersonal bureaucracy, dogs' mess
on pavements, regular strikes, widespread unemployment, redundancies, football
hooliganism, and spiritual deprivation.
However, whether we like
it or not, that is the way it has to be.
For the virtues of one age are almost invariably the vices of another,
the vices of one age the virtues of another, and no age is totally perfect.
NO HOPE WITHOUT FEAR: Every life is subject to the intermittent
prevalence of fear. When a man pretends
exemption from fear, it should be evident that he is almost certainly deluded,
ignorant, forgetful, superficial, or just a plain liar. For, in reality, no man can be exempted
from fear - not, anyway, while he lives anything approximating to a normal,
healthy, thought-ridden existence.
But let us take a closer
look at this matter and unashamedly draw up a fairly comprehensive list of the
most common fears, particularly those which regularly plague the male mind:
fear of losing one's job, of having an accident, of becoming dangerously ill,
of going deaf and/or blind, of being sent to gaol, of becoming impotent, of not
succeeding in one's work, of going mad, of being taken for a fool, of losing
one's intellectual powers, of being misunderstood, of being rebuffed by a woman
to whom one is attracted, of being exploited, of being trapped in an ungainly
situation, of losing someone one loves, of insomnia, of solitude, of idleness,
of disgrace, of heights, of flying, of neurosis, of drugs, of arousing the
hostility or contempt of one's neighbours and colleagues, of the unknown, of
bullies, of thugs, of making a woman pregnant against one's wishes, of crowds,
of changing one's habits too often, of certain authorities, of what people may
be saying about one behind one's back, of being made to look a fool, of being
late for work, of oversleeping, of too much responsibility, of violence, of
incompatibility with another person, of premature ejaculation, of having one's
creative work rejected, of being noticed by certain people, of nightmares, of
not appearing to be brave enough, of not meeting the right sort of people, of
meeting the wrong sort of people, of being completely alone in one's old age,
of being struck by lightning, of being mugged or robbed, of going bald, of
catching a cold, of being alone in the dark, of losing money, of missing an
appointment, of telling a lie, of the police, of strangers, etc.
From this fairly
generalized list of the most common male fears (though many of them will
doubtless be shared by females as well), one can see just how pervasive fear
really is in life. Not one of us who
cannot admit to having fears about some of the things in the above list and/or
to having previously overcome or outgrown certain other fears there. Not a day passes but either something in or
beyond the above list troubles our worry-strained minds. But could one imagine what it would be like
to live totally without fear? Not if one
is sufficiently human! For, as the
philosopher Hume indicated, without fear there would be no hope, and without
hope there would be no life.
TWENTY MISTAKEN IDEAS: As some modern philosophers have informed
us, there are always a large number of universally mistaken ideas to which many
people are grudgingly apt to cling, despite their proven fallibility. Here, for the sake of exposing some of them,
as well as perhaps following in the hallowed footsteps of Schopenhauer,
Nietzsche, and Bertrand Russell, I list twenty ideas which strike me as being
in this category:-
1. The
Universe consists of the solar system and the stars;
2. Space
is finite;
3. Man
is by nature purely rational;
4. Goodness
can exist independently of evil;
5. Man
is imperfect because he makes mistakes;
6. Man
can live without illusions;
7. The
proper sphere of art is truth;
8. The
sun revolves around the earth;
9. Population
in no way conditions human behaviour;
10. The most spiritual people are of necessity the least
sensuous;
11. Violence
is unnecessary;
12. Religion
is unnecessary;
13. Happiness
is the absence of pain;
14. The
survival of death is no mere hypothesis;
15. Life
is enriched by suffering;
16. There
is no moral-world-order;
17. God
is nature;
18. The
object of progress is to minimize pain;
19. Man
is immune to the influence of his external environment;
20. Solitary
people are invariably lonely.
SLIGHTLY EXISTENTIAL: To acquire a contemporary understanding of
what Schopenhauer meant by the world 'as our idea', or what it means to be
living in a material world which is partly fashioned by man, one need only
endeavour to imagine how an animal or a bird would view its immediate surroundings
... how, for instance, an ordinary grey pigeon would see such inventions as a
pillar box, a telephone kiosk, a car, motorcycle, lamppost, statue, traffic
light, clock tower, or notice board.
Taken from what one
imagines to be a pigeon's point-of-view, one might suppose such human
inventions to be of relatively little significance, to be mere 'things' without
names or apparent significance upon which the pigeon can rest or about which it
must move. Whether, in fact, our pigeon
sees the pillar box as a large red 'thing' or not, one can be fairly confident
that it possesses no equivalent symbol for 'red', that it can only see the
pillar box as something describing a particular shape and hue which is
different from other shapes and hues, and which may or may not attract its
attention on that account.
Therefore the world
evidently presents a very different face to a pigeon than what it generally
does to a human being, and this difference, this conglomeration of nondescript,
nameless, purposeless, and possibly colourless 'things', lends an extra
dimension to what Schopenhauer meant by the proposition 'the world is my idea',
a world not only dependent on the peculiar nature of human consciousness and of
the relative distortion or subjectivity which that consciousness necessarily
imposes upon it but, in addition, one largely fashioned by man for the benefit
of men and having, on that account, no similar common reality for anything
else, be it pigeon, sparrow, mouse, cat, squirrel, or dog - other, of course,
than in the very basic and self-evident sense of presenting external 'things'.
WORDS AS OUR 'REALITY': In the human world there are 'tall trees',
'green leaves', 'blades of grass', and 'grey clouds', but in the animal, bird,
and insect worlds there are no such descriptions. Such creatures see the world openly, nakedly,
devoid of adjectives and nouns. From
their point of view cats do not lie in 'the grass', birds do not perch in
'trees', and bees do not pollinate 'flowers'.
What we have conveniently taken for their reality is only relevant to
ourselves, since to a cat there is no such thing as 'grass', to a bird there
are no such things as 'trees', and to a bee there are no such things as
'flowers'. Neither are they aware that
leaves are 'green' or clouds 'grey'. In
fact, they do not even know what leaves or clouds are, being so utterly
accustomed to living in a world without description.
But to ask ourselves a
serious question - do we really know what leaves or clouds are? Are we really in possession of ultimate truth
when we point to 'green leaves' or 'grey clouds' and thereupon claim additional
knowledge for ourselves? Let us confess,
my readers, that these descriptions, ingenious and
indispensable as they are, in no way penetrate to the essential core of
things. Let us confess to mostly being
unconscious poets who manipulate representative symbols without usually
realizing that a 'leaf' in no way explains exactly what a leaf is,
much less a 'green leaf'.
And so we, too, are
basically as unaware as the animals, birds, and insects as to exactly what we
are living with. We can never get to the
heart of the world we have metaphorically invented, and therefore must conclude
the ultimate truth of whatever confronts us in the natural world to be a refutation
of our illusions rather than the illusions, or symbols, themselves.
In other words, to
establish anything approximate to the ultimate truth about a leaf, one would
have to admit our knowledge of leaves to be relative and, hence, misleading, an
attempt to describe that which, in its natural essence, defies definitive
description. In sum, there are no
'leaves'; we have conveniently invented them.
And to the extent that we have named and thereby humanized such
existences, we have invented the rest of nature as well.
PARTLY OUR CREATION: What a strange moment it is in one's life
when one realizes that, ultimately, there is no such thing as a 'bumblebee',
indeed, that there has never been such a thing except in
relation to human cognition and imagination.
The world we have created generally suffices us. We believe quite firmly in the existence of
'bumblebees', a type of winged insect we can easily differentiate from other such
insects but which, in the world beneath man, is no closer to being a 'bumblebee'
than anything else. As a named creature,
it is both a truth and an illusion. As an unnamed one, a truth through and through. But we are of course unable to live without
illusions; we must give names to things in order to be able to differentiate between
them and, in doing so, fall into the trap of actually believing these named
things to be ultimate realities - something they in no sense are or ever can
be.
And so one day we
realize that, together with any number of other insects, birds, animals, fish,
etc., the 'bumblebee' is partly a figment of our imagination, a nameless
creature which in our world acquires a fixed position but which in its own
world - and doubtless in the worlds of numerous other nameless creatures - must
forever remain a truthful thing-in-itself, unknowable and unnamed.
With man, however, such
illusions (and I use the term in the special, if unusual sense, to which it
here applies) are of the greatest significance.
We need our illusions for the sake of our truths, so let us not
endeavour to undermine them. For what I
have just told you is, after all, a truth acquired at
the expense of an illusion.
TRUTHS BUT NO TRUTH: The fundamental reason why we can never
arrive at 'the truth' about the world is that there is no single truth, i.e.
human truth, but an infinity of truths which, in their
various manifestations, correspond to the different life-forms contemplating
them.
Thus we can divide earth
truths, as it were, into human, animal, reptile, bird, fish, insect, microbe, and
vegetable, and then again into the 'truths' appertaining to each individual
species within the overall pattern; though the 'truths' of the seven kinds of
life beneath man will be correspondingly smaller and more restricted, as befits
organisms with a much narrower range of knowledge. Then, of course, one must bear in mind the
possibility of diverse kinds of life existing on other planets, if not in this
solar system then at least in solar systems that we presume to exist both
elsewhere in the Galaxy, of which our sun is only a minor star, and in the
thousand million or so other galaxies currently known to man via the world's
most powerful telescopes.
Hence the universe of
natural truths is potentially so great, diverse, and exclusive ... as to
completely defy any attempt man might make to establish a categorical criterion
of 'the truth' based solely on the limited and necessarily partial perspective
of human cognition. For truth, as we
here understand it, is eternally relative, not absolute, and thereby confined
to being a record of the human mind.
REALITY AND REALITIES: When once one has understood that there are
as many worlds as separate species, one will begin to comprehend how diverse
the so-called 'real world' actually is, to comprehend its diversity in terms of
numerous realities, as opposed to just a single human reality compounded of
specific shapes and manifestations of life.
Thus one can speak, for
example, in terms of cat reality, mouse reality, pigeon reality, frog reality,
shark reality, wasp reality, owl reality, etc., in addition to human reality
which, in its legitimate desire for world-wide integration and strict
categorization of all existing phenomena, regularly overlooks the various
realities confronting other creatures in order to maintain and safeguard its
own perspective.
Finally, however, one
must break the realities of the different species down into the tiny fragments
which correspond to each particular life, thereby arriving at individual
reality, the world within a world or, more specifically, the reality within
realities.
HUMAN DIVERSITY: Training people to do individual tasks is akin to
turning them into different creatures, insofar as one man becomes the rough
equivalent of a horse (taxi driver), another the rough equivalent of a fox
(politician); one man becomes the rough equivalent of an ox (labourer), another
the rough equivalent of a chameleon (actor); one man becomes the rough
equivalent of a sheepdog (foreman), another the rough equivalent of a sheep
(worker); one man becomes the rough equivalent of a spider (shopkeeper),
another the rough equivalent of a wasp (soldier); one man becomes the rough
equivalent of an ant (builder), another the rough equivalent of a squirrel
(banker), and so on.
As they become more like
their respective tasks, so they become less like each other, the outcome
ultimately being that human society comes to resemble a very subtle, if
artificial, version of the animal kingdom, wherein one type of creature preys
upon another to the end of its days.
NO TWO ALIKE: Might one not be correct in contending nature to be
more hard-pressed to create two beings exactly alike, exactly alike, that is,
in every respect, than to create four or five billion beings all
different from one another? In fact, one
could conceive of eight billion, twelve billion, an infinite number of beings
which nature would be in no way prepared to replicate, not even where the
instances of so-called identical twins were concerned.
But how inexhaustible
must be the human face and frame! No two
people exactly alike, not even if you took everybody that had ever lived into
account! And no two
ants exactly alike, either. What
- no two ants? But isn't that a patent
exaggeration? Don't all ants look
alike? Yes, of course they do. But only to human eyes, to eyes that are not
required to see ants as individuals but only
collectively 'as ants'.
As for the ants
themselves, however, one might well be correct in assuming that they can
differentiate between one another. And if they can, why not sparrows, pigeons, flies, bees, and wasps? What is there to suggest that these other
species wouldn't be able to differentiate between themselves as well?
But, my dear reader, you
know what that implies, don't you? No
two living creatures exactly the same, neither at any time nor anywhere! Now that really is stretching the
imagination!
TIME BELONGS TO MAN: Not only does man differ from other life
forms in terms of appearance, language, and custom, but also in terms of the
fact that he alone lives in a given time, whereas animals, reptiles, birds,
fish, insects, etc., live in the timeless eternity of nature, and can therefore
be said to exist negatively.
What, for example, can a
pigeon, cat, or dog know of the minute of the hour, the hour of the day, the
day of the week, the week of the month, the month of the year, the year of the
century, or the century of the millennium?
There is no regulative system by which other life forms could be obliged
to live in strict accordance with twentieth-century procedure, for they have no
criterion which could enforce any such obligation.
Indeed, the fundamental
ignorance of other life forms as to the establishment of a timescale permits
them a degree of naturalness unknown to man, a naturalness which exists,
moreover, in direct opposition to the positivity of
created time. For man, the creator of
unnatural or artificial criteria, can never wholly escape his consciousness of
being in a given century or of living from Sunday to Saturday in a certain
month, and is thus forever obliged to live outside of natural eternity. In a sense, the only eternity known to him is
that which is granted through intense preoccupation - the transient
forgetfulness of the burden of time as induced by excitement, whether physical
or mental, though especially the latter.
INEVITABLY UNREASONABLE: Every man will at some time or other be
shamelessly unreasonable towards some other section(s) of society in order to
maintain his reasonableness where it is most required, i.e. in respect of his
personal welfare. Hence he will
consciously or unconsciously adopt a superficially condemnatory view of
particular people or types of persons simply because, as a human being subject
to dualistic impulses, he has no other choice, since his metaphysical integrity
demands that he so acts in order to remain true to himself.
Thus this periodic
unreasonableness is, on a profounder level, a manifestation of his overall reasonableness, insofar as he respects himself as a being
who must follow certain prescribed inclinations or limitations irrespective of
the criticisms he may receive, in consequence of appearing unreasonable, from
other differently-oriented 'reasonable' people.
PUPPETS OF LIFE: In theory, though rarely in practice, I do not
condemn a man, no matter how obnoxious he may seem, for being what he is, since
I cannot understand how a man with an acquired obsession - and we all acquire
obsessions - can possibly be expected to act in a way contrary to the dictates
of that obsession. In other words, a man
who is the inevitable consequence of a combination of former influences is in
no way qualified to ignore them.
Thus, with regard to the
individual, I do not condemn a tyrant for being a tyrant. I may disapprove of him, but reason compels
me to acknowledge tyranny, in all its manifold guises, patriarchal as well as
political, petty as well as great, as a fact of (dualistic) life, one of those
disagreeable facts like nightmares, earthquakes, wars, famines, and diseases,
against which there seems to be no ultimate deterrent.
For whatever a man does,
he does because he is basically unable to do anything else. We cannot entirely shake ourselves free from
the diverse contexts and circumstances which have made us what we are. To a large extent we are all puppets of life,
ingenious marionettes who dance on the strings of our respective experiences
and occupations.
THE NEGATIVE ROOT: Whatever exists naturally exists negatively,
which is to say in direct opposition to a positive quality which has sprung
from it, viz. silence in relation to sound, space in relation to matter,
eternity in relation to time, woman in relation to man, illusion in relation to
truth, barbarism in relation to culture, evil in relation to good, sadness in
relation to happiness, dark in relation to light, competition in relation to
co-operation, immorality in relation to morality, etc., so that whatever exists
positively, by contrast, exists to a certain extent unnaturally, or by dint of
a degree of effort. Truth has to be
struggled after, whereas illusion costs us no great effort, being everywhere
the basic clay from which truth is moulded.
Goodness likewise has to be struggled after, whereas evil, the primal
source from which all goodness springs, proves less difficult of attainment,
being everywhere the more natural state-of-affairs. And happiness, despite superficial
appearances to the contrary, is not our natural condition but one to which we
must daily aspire with a fresh resolve which, if successful, will temporarily
free us from the gruesome clutches of that all-pervading sadness.
Yes, just as surely as
the predominantly positive man springs from the predominantly negative and,
hence, more natural woman, so do all the other positive entities known to us spring
from a like-source of negativity, as though in defiance of the root substance
or nature of things. But one must not
suppose this arrangement to be in any way reprehensible! For it is only by springing from and being,
as it were, enmeshed in the negative ... that man can aspire towards the
positive at all. How could it be
otherwise? One cannot have a positive
base at the bottom of nature, life, and the universe, a base from which
negativity sprang, for the simple reason that, properly considered, a negative
attribute cannot spring from anywhere, but must always 'give birth' to a
positive one.
Admittedly, the world is fundamentally
an evil place, but if it were not so, if it wasn't rooted in negativity, there
would be no aspiration towards or attainment of the good. Indeed, there would be no cause
for the good. Hence the intrinsic evil
of the world finds redemption in man.
THE STRUGGLE FOR HAPPINESS: If one didn't have to fight for one's
happiness on a daily basis, if, by some remote chance, happiness was 'handed to
one on a plate', there would be little or no free choice left in the world,
little or no incentive for innately happy people to do anything, so greatly
would the intrinsic happiness of human existence content and preoccupy them. It is only, however, because our natural
condition is one of sadness that we are regularly goaded out of it by the
desire to acquire happiness, since no man can struggle from the positive to the
negative because the positive would be all-sufficing and thus unable or
unwilling to instigate any such procedure.
Hence it is ever man's
fate to struggle from the negative to the positive, from sadness to happiness,
in accordance with his thoroughly admirable desire to escape from what is
disagreeable. And yet the positive can
only be sustained for a limited period of time, after which it must again make
way for the negative, in order that the phoenix of happiness may subsequently
rise from the ashes of sadness and thereby permit man his individual freedom. But man, as already remarked, never struggles
from the positive to the negative. On
the contrary, he merely subsides or relapses into it.
WORK AND PLAY: I do not believe the man who tells me that he
doesn't have any play because his play blends-in with his work and thereby
forces nothing but work upon him. To
hear this is almost to be told that the man who says it doesn't really have any
work either since, in the final analysis, one cannot have a life which is
either all work and no play or all play and no work. Somehow, one has to accept that one cannot
work without play or play without work, even if one chooses to pretend or
imagine otherwise, since one would then have forgotten what the true feelings
or nature of work and play actually were.
No, I do not go along
with the man who is or, more accurately, imagines himself to be a self-styled martyr of work without
really being such. If his play isn't
completely separate from his work, then his work will ultimately be bad for
him, whatever he happens to think of it.
In fact, work and play
are so interdependent, and yet so radically different, that, unless one keeps
them apart, one will never get the most out of one's work, its being understood
that there is no surer way of weakening one's impulse for work than to cut down
on one's play or, as some people would have it, blend the one with the
other. For the good worker, the man
whose work means more to him than just a wage, is ever
the good player, the man who plays to the maximum of his ability for the sake of
his work. But if one wishes to cut down
on one's play, why not cut down on one's work or, better still, give-up working
altogether.
NO FREEDOM WITHOUT BONDAGE: Freedom is merely a temporary release
from bondage, by no means a permanent one.
It is the negative antithesis to the positive bondage, a reprieve from
that which should normally be the predominating influence in a person's
life. Without bondage there can be no
freedom, without freedom no bondage.
Whether your particular bondage be in writing, painting, reading,
lecturing, clerking, washing, printing, sweeping, typing, building, driving, or
anything else, the essential thing is that you should be living as a freeman
for the sake of your bondage rather than as a bondsman for the sake of your
freedom. For to live as a bondsman for
the sake of your freedom is to live negatively, to aspire from what may be
termed the negative-positive to the positive-negative, rather than from the
negative to the positive as one should normally do. After all, it isn't so much the kind of work
one does ... as to how one feels about doing it that
really matters. One can live just as
positively by being a clerk, a typist, a shop assistant, a car mechanic, etc.,
as by being an artist, a manager, a teacher, or an army officer. It depends entirely on the type of person one
is.
But if one is doing one
thing and genuinely desires to do something else - ah! that
is when one is living against the grain, living as a freeman-in-bondage rather
than as a bondsman-in-freedom, and should therefore do something to alter
it. For in a predominantly positive
life, a life that identifies with its work and can properly express itself
through that work, the freedom acquired once one's work is finished for the day
is always legitimately negative. The
individual concerned can afford, if needs be, to spend time chatting casually
to various friends and/or acquaintances, or watching a rather frivolous film,
or leisurely reading an inconsequential book, or going for a lengthy stroll, or
just idling somewhere by himself without feeling even the slightest need to get
down to some serious work, the kind of work he might otherwise feel that he
really ought to be doing in order not to waste any valuable time. But the man who
cannot 'waste' any time, after his official work is over for the day, isn't
living as well as he could be. In a
sense, he isn't really living at all!
FROM WINTER TO AUTUMN: If, in maintaining our established
terminology, we are in accord that winter is the negative season of the year
and summer, by contrast, the positive one, then I deem spring to be the
negative-positive and autumn the positive-negative. Hence we find the seasons following the
sequence: negative, negative-positive, positive, positive-negative, with the
two divisible seasons, viz. spring and autumn, progressing to their respective
consummations in summer and winter.
Since the positive always arises from the negative, we find its earliest
manifestation in spring, its consummation in summer, and its gradual decline in
autumn; the winter, or root season, being the eternal negative from which the
process of growth and decay must again proceed.
Strictly speaking,
however, there are only two (not four) divisions to the year, viz. winter and
summer, in accordance with the fundamental dualism underlining the activity of
all life on this planet, the transitional periods, as it were, of spring and
autumn being an inceptive extension of summer and winter respectively, and
granting us a useful analogy with the half-light states before dawn and after
sunset, which we term twilight.
NO 'MOTHER NATURE': Nature has often been referred to as 'Mother
Nature', a notion which suggests a feminine or negative character when, to
speak metaphorically, it is neither feminine nor masculine but a subtle
combination of each. For nature's only
feminine season is the winter, whereas summer is, by way of an antithesis,
distinctly masculine, and autumn and spring are a reverse combination of, in
the one case, a declining masculinity and an ascending femininity and, in the
other case, a declining femininity and an ascending masculinity.
Thus the notion of
'Mother Nature' is only valid insofar as it represents half the truth, not the
whole truth. For nature is effectively
androgynous.
MALE AND FEMALE PRIDE: A beautiful woman is usually delighted by
the admiring attentions of the good-looking men she happens to encounter in
life. She takes much of her pride and
happiness from the fact that such men find her attractive and therefore worthy
of their admiration. Her face often
betrays her self-satisfaction, the knowledge that she is desirable. Thus her pride is direct; it is rooted in herself and requires no external props - other, of course,
than the necessary or desired means of adorning her body.
Not so, however, with a
man! As a rule, he is not so proud of himself as a kind of 'thing-in-itself', but
mostly in relation to what he represents, to the kind of work he does and the
degree of respect or recognition (if any) he can expect from that. Take away his work and you automatically
deprive him of the chief means whereby he can feel admirable to himself. His pride isn't centred, like that of an
attractive woman, directly upon himself but only indirectly, through the medium
of what he has achieved and continues to achieve in life. If he is to be admired, it will be as a
musician, lawyer, sportsman, soldier, doctor, builder, disc jockey, politician,
manager, painter, writer, etc., according to the nature of his temperament,
talents, and social position.
But if he is without
work, then there is very little that he can be genuinely proud of; he is not
encouraged, by nature, to regard himself as admirable in himself to anything
like the same extent as an attractive woman, and so he is inevitably at a
distinct disadvantage to such a woman in the same predicament. For men and women are, and will remain,
fundamentally different creatures.
AGAINST FOLLY: It isn't necessarily unnatural to rebel against
human folly but, more usually, an indirect indication of one's own folly. For even if a man understands the
inevitability and, indeed, absolute legitimacy of folly, even if he recognizes
it as part of a duality which, in antithesis to wisdom, ultimately guarantees
its opposite, there is no reason why he shouldn't continue to rebel against it
precisely because of its periodic prevalence within himself. Hence his own folly will override his
intellectual acknowledgement of its ultimate legitimacy and, consequently,
enable him to continue acting 'unreasonably', or in apparent contradiction of
his theoretical awareness.
However, there is of
course another and perhaps more serious way of viewing the problem - namely,
through the realization that a man naturally looks down on his periodic folly because,
in addition to causing him inconvenience, it forms the negative antithesis to
his wisdom or good sense. After all, a
being who is essentially geared to the positive must consequently take
rather a condescending view of the negative, and so, by rejecting folly, he
really acts 'reasonably'.
Here is further proof,
in explanation of the above contradiction, that the power of practice is
somewhat stronger than that of theory.
No matter what we know, we can only act in accordance with nature which,
in human terms, is far more comprehensive than we may sometimes care to
imagine.
SUSPENDED JUDGEMENT: I have never seen a ghost and have absolutely
no reason to believe in the existence of a spirit world. Where, however, spirits are claimed to
manifest themselves in some way, usually for the benefit of a communion of like
minds gathered together at a séance, it may be assumed that those taking part
in the proceedings have been conditioned to participate in a state of
receptivity or expectation which, if not permitting the entry of hallucinatory
material into each individual consciousness, at least permits a degree of such
material to affect someone, if only the medium.
Taking this contention
at face-value, it would appear that the self-discipline necessary for the
attainment of the requisite atmosphere is of consummate importance in
determining the extent to which one opens the door, as it were, into one's own
'spirit world' and thereupon deceives oneself as to the extent of that world's
objective reality. For if one wasn't
sufficiently disciplined (or deceived) to begin with, there would be very
little chance of either audibly or visually fostering an
hallucinatory condition that would fully satisfy the demands of the occasion.
As, however, for those
comparatively eccentric types who inherit or develop a perverse hankering after
such impalpable entities as spirits, and who have, to be sure, encountered
these entities during the course of their individual travels - can one not
simply presume them to be especially susceptible to this particular form of
hallucination? After all, the human
world is undeniably sympathetic to diverse manifestations of insanity,
stupidity, self-deception, etc., and - if I am not equally deceived in
contending this - it is fairly common knowledge that the human mind is capable
of believing what it chooses or wants to believe, not necessarily what it ought
to!
Of
course, the debate between spiritualists and rationalists will doubtless drag
on for some time to come. But, in
the interests of rational investigation, I can at least posit the hypothesis
that what is commonly taken for a spirit by the spiritualistic fraternity is
nothing more nor less than an apparently external
recognition of internally-induced phenomena, or some such similar
quasi-holographic derangement.... Perhaps, in seeking confirmation of this, one
would do well to consult the writings of Carl Jung for a thorough diagnosis of
what the subconscious mind is capable of engendering!
AGAINST REINCARNATION: If man was wholly rational he wouldn't have
evolved and, in many cases, actually believed in the theory of
reincarnation. For reincarnation is
patently a superstition, and one, moreover, which would seem to presuppose
that, once having left the body of a dead person, a highly-developed and
self-motivated 'live' soul will eventually find its way back to the world via
the vagina of a mother-to-be and, in forcing its way into her womb, somehow
manage to link-up with the incipient foetus there only to reappear, some nine months
later, in the guise of a new-born infant!
Fantastic as that is, one has then got to stomach the even more
fantastic outcome of the parents of this child eventually being able to
recognize it as their own, to discern within and upon its face various traits
of their respective physical and spiritual characteristics, and to thereupon
consider it a legitimate extension of themselves.
Now if, as we were led
to suppose, the child's soul initially came from elsewhere, the basic
composition of this soul must surely be different from that of the parents'
souls either taken separately or in combination - in fact, so different as to
create a largely incongruous human being the heredity of which the parents
would have considerable difficulty in claiming responsibility for.
But, of course, all this
is absolute nonsense, the sort of intellectual nonsense so adroitly exposed by
Bertrand Russell, and generally promulgated with the assistance of such
pompous-sounding terms as metempsychosis and reincarnation, to the lasting
detriment of reason! That mankind must
ever succumb to illusions of one sort or another, we know only too well. But they must be illusions that fool even the
philosophical inquisitors, not ones so well-worn and obviously vulnerable to
rational criticism that we have no choice but to obey our intellectual
conscience and sweep them aside in the interests of new truths.
SUPERSTITION UNIVERSAL: Just as, up to a point, each man's filth
smells sweetly to him alone, so, likewise, does each nation's superstitions
appear feasible to it alone, the religious beliefs of certain other nations
appearing little more than childish by comparison. Yet people are everywhere 'the double and
equal of man', to cite Baudelaire, and thus prone to the creation or maintenance
of similar religious hypotheses themselves, if for no other reason than their
common humanity.
Now occasionally it
happens that a religiously-inclined individual actually 'sees through' the play
of illusions he had previously taken for truths, that he becomes disillusioned
with the superstitions of his community and, without fully realizing that
people are everywhere alike, anxious to compensate himself for this loss by
adopting what he then considers to be the superior and more rational beliefs of
another nation. So off he goes, with a
distinctly supercilious air, to the fresh pastures of Oriental, African, or
Latin American superstition, much consoled by the assumption that he has 'seen
through' the superstitions of his native land and, as a reward for this, is now
about to embark upon the study of a superior culture.
But to just what do you
suppose all this will lead? Either he
will become disillusioned with the new beliefs or, what's worse, fall a prey to
them. And if the latter, then rest assured
that his understanding of human nature, with its rational/irrational
oscillations, will remain forever incomplete.
THE END OF THE WORLD: I have heard talk that the end of the world
will occur at a certain predictable date in the near future, in fact either at
the turn-of-the-century or, according to the stronger views of the more
pessimistic prophets of eschatological clairvoyance and apocalyptic severity,
within the next few months (though one might suppose the world to be already
finished and living past itself and in spite of itself, so to speak, if one
were to take the warnings or predictions of these obsessed prophets of
annihilation at face-value!).
However, considering
that so many discouraging predictions of this type have already outlived themselves
and become thoroughly obsolete, while the world has continued to exist, to
change, and even to progress, it appears only logical to conclude further
developments of this ominous mania equally doomed to irrelevance, ridicule, and
oblivion. Indeed, one might even hazard
a fairly optimistic if not altogether comforting guess that not even a nuclear
war would actually destroy the entire planet, would in fact cause it to
disintegrate. But if the world could survive
such a battering, then what-on-earth can all this 'end-of-the-world'
speculation be about?
Leaving religious
considerations to one side, I would imagine the end of the material world, as
indeed the end of the solar system of which this planet is but a tiny
component, to have intimate connections with the inevitable dissolution of the
sun, an eventuality apparently not liable to occur for another eight-thousand
million years but, nevertheless, one which, if man is to survive drastic
changes of temperature in the meantime and break away from this solar system in
order to establish a better life for himself elsewhere, would seem to
contribute towards justifying the evolutionary thrusts behind the various
space-research programmes, and thereby put a stopper into the fatuous mouths of
those who foolishly imagine that a myopic attention to the affairs of the world
is all that really matters.
ART AS IDEALITY: It is my firm contention that an artist is never
more genuine than when he adheres to ideality and,
like Blake, Dadd, Dali, Turner, Picasso, Bourne-Jones,
Chagall, Burra, Van Gogh, and Kandinsky,
invents a world largely of his own which contrasts with the everyday reality to
which one is normally accustomed. He who
paints me another world, creates unique images or, alternatively, reproduces images
from myth, religion, or literature, I regard as a genuine artist. The others, the portrait painters, realists,
and naturalists, I regard as craftsmen or draughtsmen, men who apply an almost
scientifically literal approach to their work, who create a hybrid which, in
sacrificing imagination to factual reproduction, is neither science nor art but
a mediator between the two, a sort of parallel to academic philosophy, which
usually has its boundaries somewhere between the realms of science and
religion.
But the truly creative
artist deals chiefly with the ideal, the world of the imagination. It is he who establishes an antithesis to
science and temporarily frees us from the oppressiveness and overwhelming
seriousness of factual truth. His greatness is guaranteed by the combination of
two indispensable ingredients - imagination and technique. With only one of these he is not an artist
but, at best, a dilettante or craftsman, depending on the ingredient in
question. With both, however, he is the
true spokesman and practitioner of a discipline which stands in an antithetical
relationship to science - not, be it noted, as its enemy, but as its
complement, the negative pole of a dual integrity and, consequently, a vocation
dedicated to the service of creatures who are unable to live without illusions
but must forever oscillate between the two poles if they are to remain
balanced, or relatively sane.
Yes, in the final
analysis, art is dualistically inferior to science, as illusion to truth. But science is in no way able to exist
without art, not, anyway, while there is anything approximating to a civilized
view of life in the world. For the two
pursuits are interdependent and therefore must remain firmly committed to their
respective tasks.
Strictly speaking, there
is no such thing as 'scientific art' (not to be confused with science-fiction),
any more than there is really such a thing as 'artistic science'. An art which deserts its rightful
responsibility in imagination to serve the cause of science, i.e. by drawing
inspiration directly from scientific fact, is unwittingly hindering both itself
and science by being insufficiently antithetical to it. An art which draws its inspiration from the
'real' instead of the 'ideal' is fundamentally perverse. In fact, it is no longer art at all but, as
mentioned above, a kind of hybrid, and very often a lost cause in a dark age.
No, if art is to do
itself proper justice it must find its chief inspiration within the
imagination, within that strangely disguised mythical world, surreal world,
impressionistic world, expressionistic world, abstract world, fantasy world, or
any other 'illusory' world which affords us an authentic contrast to everyday
reality. Is it any wonder that those
artists whom I listed at the beginning of this essay have all achieved due
recognition as great painters? No, not
if one understands exactly what a true
artist is.
Now what applies to the
art of painting applies no less to the 'arts' of music, literature, and
sculpture, where imagination and technique are still the tools most needed for
the shaping of anything artistically worthwhile. But let us leave the final word on this
subject with Oscar Wilde, whose Decay of Lying remains one of
the most eloquent, lucid, and pertinent dialogues ever written in defence of
art: 'Art begins with abstract decoration, with purely imaginative and
pleasurable work dealing with what is unreal and non-existent. This is the first stage. Then Life becomes fascinated with this new
wonder, and asks to be admitted into the charmed circle. Art takes Life as part of her rough material,
recreates it, and refashions it in fresh forms, is absolutely indifferent to
fact, invents, imagines, dreams, and keeps between itself and reality the
impenetrable barrier of beautiful style, of decorative or ideal treatment. The third stage is when Life gets the upper
hand, and drives Art out into the wilderness.
This is the true decadence, and it is from this that we are now
suffering.'
GREAT ART: What one normally wants from art, to take a particular
if arguably somewhat conservative viewpoint, is a feeling that the work in
question lies far above one's own creative abilities. I mean if, as so often happens nowadays, one
is left with the highly distinctive impression that, had one so desired, one
could have done just as well if not better than the so-called artist oneself,
then the work in question is obviously open to suspicion and probably leaves
one either unmoved or, worse still, dejected.
Now when, by contrast,
one contemplates a Dali, there is usually no doubt in one's mind that the scene
or event it portrays is a work of genius, that skill and imagination have been
combined to virtually the utmost possible extent to produce something both
precious and inimitable. It is great
art, despite its comparatively strange, wayward, and at times positively
horrific nature, because it still manages to convince the viewer of having
something extraordinarily ingenious about it which he could never hope to
emulate himself. With great art one
generally feels oneself to be in the presence of the divinity of man, of man
become great creator through the manipulation of a technique and imagination
which induces in one a feeling of amazement as to the seemingly infinite extent
of man's capacity for artistic greatness.
Unfortunately, however,
modern art so often falls short of artistic greatness (not to mention genuine
art) because, lacking both the requisite devotion and talent for the execution
of anything great, its practitioners have lost track of the essentially
idealistic nature of art and allowed their productions to become perverted into
something so pathetically commercial, and hence dominated by market forces, as
to be anything but artistic. It isn't,
by any account, a straightforward reflection of contemporary life that one
desires from art; for such a reflection can be captured exceedingly well by the
predominantly impersonal use of a journalistic camera. Still less is it the portrayal of a blank
canvas, or of a canvas portraying, at best, a few straight or squiggly lines
and cryptic blotches. On the contrary,
it is the brilliance, skill, imagination, spirit, purpose - in sum, the
personality which a great artist inevitably bestows upon his work that the
genuine art enthusiast desires, not the distressing spectacle of exhibits which
resemble the predictably banal productions of the average junior-school art
class!
NO HEALTH WITHOUT DISEASE: Some people like to imagine that man
will one day conquer disease and that, in accordance with the fruits of social
progress, he will subsequently live in a utopia where health, justice, peace,
happiness, prosperity, sanity, fraternity, beauty, truth, goodness, and love
will reign supreme. Now while not wishing
to deprive such people of their fond hopes for the future, it nevertheless
occurs to me that they are unlikely to materialize in a life conditioned by
dualistic exchanges, as is invariably the case with human life. For it would certainly seem, if precedence is
anything to judge by, that health cannot prevail without sickness, justice
without injustice, peace without some form of war, happiness without sadness,
prosperity without poverty, sanity without insanity, etc., and that, as soon as
man plugs a hole in one context, a fresh hole eventually appears elsewhere, and
with greater determination than on the previous occasion, so that he is forever
juggling reality into new patterns, forever creating new manifestations of the
basic polar attributes.
Admittedly, there is a
fair chance that man may eventually come to terms with the common cold (bearing
in mind that there are a hundred or more different viruses with which to deal),
influenza, cancer (which also comes in many guises), schizophrenia, and other
such contemporary scourges. But no sooner
will he have done so than disease will acquire other manifestations in which to
maintain the polarity of health and sickness, thereby safeguarding the
existence of health while simultaneously providing fresh sources of
investigation for both doctors and scientists alike.
In sum, the fight
against disease can in no way detract from the fundamental integrity of
life. This fight is not an indication of
the imperfection of life, as might at first appear, but a part of its overall
integrity within the human framework, with its dualistic criteria.
ILLNESS NO OBJECTION: Suppressing common illnesses by the regular
use of various drugs and medicines usually reflects an audacious attempt by man
to cheat nature out of its rightful influence.
For whenever a common illness is prevented from running its natural
course, it invariably takes revenge upon the assailant by staging a fiercer
resistance (much as a soldier will put up a stronger fight when forced into a
perilous situation), thereby making one feel a lot worse. Furthermore, it should be remembered that
illnesses are not anomalous occurrences which shouldn't happen but, on the
contrary, very natural occurrences which, if anything, strengthen one's taste
for good health, so that the unnatural and artificial suppression of them tends
(except in the most serious cases) to be utopian rather than realistic, the
sort of disregard for polarity and the interdependence of antitheses which, in
other contexts, would lead to the unhealthy suppression or, more accurately,
attempted suppression of hate for the sake of love, illusion for the sake of
truth, evil for the sake of good, or sadness for the sake of happiness.
But this disregard for
polarity, this attempt to eradicate an illness as quickly as possible (tied-up,
as it undoubtedly is, with the materialistic requirements of a consumer
society), only serves to complicate and aggravate matters - a salutary lesson
which, if properly understood, could lead to the judicious suppression of
meddlesome drugs or medicines and to the adoption, if not on the part of the
medical profession in general then at least on the part of the general public,
of a more dualistic view concerning the legitimacy of illness!
Needless to say, there
is obviously something wrong, ignorant, and even cowardly about a man who, at
the earliest intimation of a common cold, sore throat, headache, stomach ache,
temperature, or some other such minor ailment, rushes to the doctor or chemist
in search of a miracle-working cure when, in accordance with the fundamental
workings of nature, it is only from the illness itself that a genuine cure can
come. Indeed, one might even suppose
that the easy availability of an artificial cure induces people to be less
thoughtful about their health. For is it
not the case that a majority of common illnesses are usually incurred as the
consequence of a stupid action, and can thus be seen as a kind of punishment
and warning to people to be more careful in future!
Be that as it may, one
can nonetheless maintain that illnesses generally contain their own cure, are
by no means superfluous occurrences, and should be left, in nine cases out of
ten, to run their natural course rather than be meddled with by an impatient
consumer society in the grip not only of market forces but of the market as
such, and which too often shies away from the dualistic integrity of life
instead of facing up to and bearing with it for its own good.
THE 'PLIMSOLL LINE' OF SLEEP: A life without sleeping, or a life
where the polarity of being awake and being asleep has broken down, would also
amount, if endurable for any length of time, to a life without waking, i.e. to
a sort of death-in-life, or perpetual consciousness of external reality which,
in its unrelenting intensity, would inevitably prove so intolerable as to drive
one either to suicide or, failing that, an asylum. But a life with its natural quota of sleep
is, by comparison, a fortunate life - indeed, one doesn't realize just how fortunate
until one has regularly had experience of insomnia! For whether or not we realize it, sleep is
the greatest medicine we possess.
Consequently there is
some truth in the notion that a man who lives well also sleeps well. One might contend, in this context, that
sleep becomes a kind of 'Plimsoll line' of correct living, a guideline by which
one can establish an accurate criterion as to whether one is living naturally
or unnaturally, agreeably or disagreeably, sensibly or foolishly. I mean if, as is sometimes the case, we are
not sleeping as well as we believe we should, might it not be an indication
from our subconscious mind that we are living against the grain, as it were, by
either taking too much social and/or occupational responsibility upon ourselves
or, conversely, not taking enough?
Hence our insomnia could
be interpreted as both a warning and a punishment, a method employed by nature
to stir us into taking a remedial course of action. In which case it should be evident that
regular use of sleeping pills is not the
remedial course of action we should take.
For rather than rectifying the situation as it ought to be rectified,
i.e. through action establishing a more healthy and tolerable mode of life,
they usually further complicate it by imposing an artificial sleep upon us
which, by interfering with the subconscious, hardly compensates us for natural
sleep.
Thus we are running away
from ourselves at the very moment when we ought to be facing-up to and
eventually overcoming our personal difficulties, when instead of acting like a
man who, because of various problems in his life, drinks himself into
alcoholism (and thereby makes matters worse for himself), we should be noting
the instructions which emanate from our subconscious mind and subsequently set
about doing whatever we can to obey them, if for no other reason than our own
good. For anything
else is inherently perverse and, as such, it can only aggravate the problem, to
increase rather than decrease our afflictions.
A WIDER VIEW OF VICE: For a majority of people vice is usually
associated with such controversial or taboo subjects as hard-drug addiction,
alcoholism, cigarette smoking, pot smoking, prostitution, masturbation, sodomy,
pederasty, gambling, idleness, lechery, vandalism, hooliganism, and foul
language - a list which, though by no means exhaustive, suffices to indicate
the general trend of popular thinking.
Now in accepting this rather narrow view of vice, it seems quite
unlikely that many people will come to realize how loquacity, temperance,
exuberance, lethargy, chastity, sociability, conscientiousness, athleticism,
art fanaticism, political fanaticism, inquisitiveness, acquisitiveness,
pomposity, presumption, superstition, piety, ambition, reclusion, or anything
else which might ordinarily be regarded as a fairly innocuous if not
praiseworthy inclination often degenerate, when pushed beyond a certain point
of intensity or duration, into some of the most lethal vices of all!
Who, for instance, could
seriously deny that religious superstition or fanaticism of one kind or another
has caused more death and suffering, over the centuries, than hard-drug
addiction, alcoholism, and cigarette smoking put together? Similarly, isn't the phrase 'excessive
political fanaticism' likely to engender rather painful connotations when one
cares to reflect upon world history, and most especially upon recent European
history? And even prolonged chastity -
what a terrible vice that can be for making various people
more argumentative, spiteful, dissatisfied, intolerant, etc., than they would
otherwise have been, if permitted a normal, healthy sex-life!
But, in saying all this,
let us not kid ourselves that vice can or indeed should be completely
eradicated. For, in all probability, one
would first have to eradicate human life.
Either that, or one would have to turn one's back on life to such an
extent that it inevitably took revenge upon one by becoming absolutely hellish,
an inclination, alas, which would seem to have possessed a perverse charm for
considerable numbers of obdurate, would-be ascetics ever since the dawn of
civilization, and one which in no way appears destined to be discarded or
outgrown while man retains a semblance of his innate and altogether
indispensable predilection for virtue.
MISUSED CONCEPTS: It is commonly understood that words are symbols
designating concepts. Our ancestors at
sometime conceived the possibility of a symbol to designate the concept 'a love
of mankind' and named it 'philanthropy'.
They likewise conceived of an antonym to this symbol and named it
'misanthropy', or 'a hatred of mankind'.
Not content with this, they then sought to justify the existence of
these symbols, these concepts, by taking a bold step further and actually
applying them to various individuals, to people whom, in their conceptual
presumption, they somehow regarded as eligible candidates. Now in consequence of this social
indiscretion, later generations gradually became aware of the existence of 'philanthropists'
and 'misanthropists' without apparently realizing that the concepts behind
these symbols had absolutely no foundation in reality, that it was impossible
either to love or hate mankind even for a few moments, considering that
'mankind' is merely an abstraction. Thus
followed the history of an outrageous misunderstanding!
Of course, one can
always love or hate the odd individual here and there,
one can even come to feel similar sentiments towards a few people here and
there. But to actually consider such
love 'a love of mankind' or such hate 'a hatred of mankind' would be more than
a gross misunderstanding: it would be the height of imbecility! For, in reality, one can no more love or hate
mankind than one can love or hate the fish kind, the bird kind, the animal
kind, the insect kind, the vegetable kind, or any other kind. In fact, it is virtually impossible not to
conclude that one can never be a philanthropist or a misanthropist under any
circumstances. For even if, in taking
the terms in a much wider sense, one does good (according to one's notion of
what constitutes 'the good') to one section of the community, it invariably
follows that one will necessarily do bad
to and fall out-of-favour with another section of it, and vice versa.
Hence I can only contend
that the world has never produced a single philanthropist: neither Buddha,
Christ, Mohammed, St. Christopher, St. Francis, Shakespeare, Florence
Nightingale, Dickens, Marx, Whitman, Gladstone, Tolstoy, Shaftesbury,
Chamberlain, nor anyone else, and never will produce one; that the world has
never produced a single misanthropist: neither Machiavelli, Swift, Caligula, de
Sade, Bonaparte, Baudelaire, Franco, Dostoyevsky,
Stalin, Lautréamont, Crowley, Nietzsche, Hitler,
Mussolini, nor anyone else, and never will produce one.
Indeed, it isn't an
everyday occurrence either to love or hate anyone at all, even one's closest
companions. But to actually love or hate
someone of whom one has absolutely no knowledge, someone who is no more familiar
to one than the paintings or posters on the walls of the millions of bedrooms
throughout the world, is an utter impossibility! It is something that people are unlikely to
imagine possible so long as, firstly, they acknowledge the exact implications
of human limitations and, secondly, they acknowledge the exact implications of
the concepts they choose to symbolize through words.
AGAINST RACIAL INEQUALITY: Can one seriously contend that an Ash
is superior to a Beech, an Oak superior to a Hawthorn, a Beech superior to an
Oak, an Oak superior to an Ash, a Sycamore superior to an Elm, a Pine superior
to a Yew, a Fir superior to a Rosewood, a Yew superior to an Elm, a Sycamore
superior to a Pine, and so on? If so, on
what criterion does one base one's contention?
Is it enough to base it on the relative number of trees in each species
(those with fewest numbers being the most precious because rare), their
respective size, leafage, colouring, seed, strength, industrial usefulness,
age, etc., or would that ultimately prove somewhat presumptuous?
Admittedly where, for
example, two Oaks that had developed unequally in different environments were
concerned, where one had become sickly and warped because of a lack of fresh
air, moisture, sunshine, space, and official protection against both man and disease,
while the other had developed under the best possible conditions and
consequently become healthy and strong, one would of course be justified in
concluding the latter tree superior to the former. However, what one could not do so confidently
would be to set up a scale of merit applicable to the most well-developed trees
in each species, to assert a Teak categorically superior to a Rosewood, or an
Elm categorically superior to a Hawthorn.
Similarly, in terms of
the human kind (and basing one's judgement solely within the confines of each
class), can one seriously contend that a Slav is superior to an Indian, a Turk
superior to a Teuton, a Latin superior to an
Anglo-Saxon, a Celt superior to a Mongol, an Arab superior to a Zulu, a Mongol
superior to a Latin, a Teuton superior to a Turk, a
Jew superior to a Pict, a Shona
superior to an Apache, an Anglo-Saxon superior to a Zulu, a Bantu superior to a
Kurd, an Eskimo superior to a Lapp, etc., and then, in going far beyond that,
draw-up a definitive scale of racial superiority relative to the total number
of races, or presumed races, currently in existence? Can one?
Would one ever be in a position to do that? Hasn't almost every race produced great men,
attained to outstanding achievements in art, literature, music, philosophy,
architecture, medicine, religion, politics, etc., and thus contributed to both
the development and decline of the many ingenious civilizations which have
appeared throughout the six-thousand years of man's reign on earth?
Surely it would be a
gross stupidity to maintain that an intelligent attitude to life ought to
incorporate an awareness as to which races one's race (if known) is either
inferior or superior to, other than in the relative sense of its being
economically, industrially, militarily, philosophically, culturally,
politically, spiritually, or socially either ahead of or behind certain other
civilized races at any given point in time.
Surely it is quite enough, under the prevailing restrictions imposed
upon us by the absence of various scientific certainties, to know one's race to
be different, the inheritor of particular advantages and disadvantages, and
then to live in accordance with those differences, whatever the consequences,
for as long as that race exists. Truly,
a genuinely inferior race would have died out long ago!
THE TRANSIENCE OF DEATH: Death, as the living
understand it, is not antithetical to life but to birth since, like the
latter, it is a momentary phenomenon rather than something that extends over a long
period of time, the way life usually does.
Once a person has died, the phenomenon of death is consummated and the
corpse thereupon begins to decompose, leaving, after a number of years,
scarcely a trace of its remains. Now
where, in consequence of this process of decomposition, there is nothing or
next to nothing remaining, the word 'dead' has no real applicability. One cannot refer to a hole in the ground with
nothing in it as the hole of a dead person, even if it is still officially a
grave by dint of the fact that a corpse was once buried there in some kind of
coffin. And so it should be fairly
obvious that 'the dead' are really very transient phenomena, nothing to work-up
to the status of an antithesis to the living.
Montaigne's life,
for example, came to an end in 1592, his corpse doubtless quickly began to
decompose, and one would, I guess, be quite justified in believing that by 1610
the former essayist had been reduced to a skeleton, to which one normally
applies an 'it' rather than a 'he'.
Thus, strictly speaking, one cannot say of Montaigne
that 'he has been dead for over four-hundred years' (since the process of death
and decay only lasts as long as there is anything approximating to a 'he'
discernible), but simply that 'he died in 1592'.
Consequently, as an
opposition to life conceived as a period of time during which one is conscious
of existing, we have the not-life, i.e. the period before birth and after death
which embraces both foetus and corpse.
As an opposition to life conceived in terms of that which lives, i.e.
the animate, we have the inanimate. And,
finally, as an opposition to birth we have - death.
PHILOSOPHY VERSES INSULAR INTOLERANCE: One of the most useful
things about the genuine philosopher in relation to both science and religion,
and even to art and politics, is that, being neither partisan to the one nor to
the other, he is in a fairly favourable position to establish a general
perspective as to what the respective adherents of these branches of human
activity are likely to think of each other and, more importantly, what they
each represent. Consequently, inasmuch
as his authority and vocation permit, he can at least draw attention to the
danger inherent in situations whereby the partisans of the one camp become so
obsessed with the furtherance of their own particular perspective that they
completely fail to take account of the other camp's perspective, and duly set
about either undermining it or, worse still, having the other camp done away
with altogether.
Now that may seem a
somewhat exaggerated not to say unlikely possibility in the context of Western
pluralism, but it nevertheless remains a fact that cases of this kind of
insular intolerance and misunderstanding are by no means as infrequent as may
at first appear. There are, for example,
eminent astronomers who, with the most extensive knowledge of astronomical
developments, are of such an ignorance in astrological matters as to be of the
opinion that this latter field of activity is not only infra dig,
but entirely unworthy of the credence of rational minds and, consequently, of
little if any account. Now, in all
probability, there are eminent astrologers who, with a time-consuming
dedication to astrology, are likely to maintain a similarly unappreciative opinion
of astronomy, or of certain astronomical contentions, which, when one considers
the limitations of their perspective, isn't altogether surprising.
This is an example, in a
somewhat simplified and perhaps over-obvious way, of what I believe to be the tendency
of specialists to become so enclosed by the limitations of their own particular
fields of activity that they pose a danger to each other and, by extension, to
those who read them. Here, I think, is
where the philosopher - and the contemporary philosopher more than ever - can
prove of some use in his endeavour to maintain a wider perspective and, if he
cannot directly prevent the representatives of certain other causes from
regularly denouncing one another as enemies of enlightenment, at least draw
attention to the possibility that they themselves may not be as enlightened as
they like to imagine.
As an afterthought (and
in extending our discussion beyond the predominantly occult realm of astrology
into that of religion-proper), it ought to be borne in mind that we live in an
age of science rather than faith, a fact which makes it obligatory for a
majority of us to view life from a more rational angle than was formerly the
case. For where our ancestors mostly
viewed life through 'religious eyes', and thereupon accused those who invented
important scientific instruments or in any way furthered science of blasphemy,
we, in our turn, are for the most part inclined to view life through
'scientific eyes', and to accuse those who still believe in miracles or
religious mysteries of ignorance and superstition. The fact, however, that both viewpoints are
equally lopsided and partial only serves to indicate that a more balanced
perspective between the religious attitude (whatever its subsequent
manifestation) and the scientific attitude has yet to be achieved. Presumably this will come about in some
future age.
In the meantime,
however, a majority of thinking people will doubtless continue to accept their
inheritance as offspring of the twentieth century and, in accordance with its Zeitgeist of
empirical secularity, continue to regard those who possess a vestige of true
religious faith as anachronisms, without wondering whether their future secular
or overly rational equivalents won't be similarly regarded by the more
'balanced' majority of a less sceptical age.
INDIVIDUAL WISDOM: Wisdom consists, amongst other things, in not
understanding everything one reads, not liking everything one reads, not
believing everything one reads, and not remembering everything one reads. A surfeit of wise ideas is, after all,
another kind of folly, and there are many gifted men who foolishly consider
themselves wise on account of the extent of their reading. What, do they not consider themselves wise
enough already? Were they not born with the
rudiments of wisdom, or are they now somewhat uncertain, in this age of
material prosperity, as to exactly what it is?
Well, let us frankly
admit that, irrespective of any aid the dictionary may give us, wisdom is not
something that can be simply defined, since it takes as many forms as there are
people, and what would suit one person, at any given time, could well be the
ruination of another. For we all possess
a wisdom peculiar to our daily circumstances and, depending on the nature of
those circumstances, the kind of wisdom each one of us possesses must
inevitably manifest itself as folly to someone else, to someone who, living in
a different context, is not obliged to adopt identical tactics to us. There is no man who is without his quota of
wisdom. Contend otherwise and you draw
on your capacity for folly. Accept it,
and your wisdom automatically leaps to the fore.
The wisdom of this
moment may give way to the folly of the next.
Whatever you understand to be wisdom here, you may be obliged to pay for
with foolishness elsewhere. You don't
become wiser generally, but only in certain contexts. Your given quota of wisdom remains the same
whether you read all the philosophy of the nineteenth century or exclusively
dedicate yourself to painting. The
wisdom of the philosopher is not the same as that of the painter. Whereas the former may advise you to avoid
taking various contentions of a particular philosopher too seriously and will
indicate, by way of compensation, other contentions which he believes to be of
consummate importance, the latter may warn you against over-using a particular
colour or tone, and will draw your attention, it may be, to certain delicate harmonies
of tonal composition which he feels to be of great beauty and technical
significance. Their different kinds of
wisdom are largely applicable to their respective occupations and, as such,
they are as wise as they need be, each man having to contend with matters
strictly pertinent to his own activity and to no-one else's.
Inevitably, this is the
case for everybody. There is the wisdom
of the monk, stockbroker, lawyer, baker, clerk, postman, teacher, cook,
etc. Each of them knows what he has to do
and, if he wants to survive, each one does it as well as possible, thereby
being as wise as he needs to be within his particular context. Now a poet isn't necessarily wiser than a
clerk; he is simply wiser in his own field.
Much of what he does is only relevant to poets, and consequently much of
what he says will strike a clerk as being somewhat foolish, just as much of
what the latter does and says will strike him as being
somewhat foolish, even though they are both doing and saying what they must.
But is a man any the
less wise for becoming a clerk instead of a poet? Some poets may think so, especially if they
belong to that vainglorious breed of men who always consider their own
profession superior to everyone else's.
However, people of a philosophic turn-of-mind will incline to think
otherwise. For if a man isn't really
interested in poetry, and is insufficiently gifted in poetic composition to
become a professional poet, then his fundamental attitude to poetry will
probably be either one of mild curiosity or, more likely, general indifference,
so that any suggestion to the effect that he ought to have taken-up with poetry
instead of, say, clerking will meet with little sympathy, its being inferred
that not everyone was born to do the same thing!
Yet the logical
implication of this is something that the self-conceit of certain illustrious
poets may make them overlook - namely that men come in many shapes and sizes,
in consequence of which the means to salvation for one would surely be the road
to damnation of another!
No, it is not for us to
presume a man less wise for becoming a clerk, lawyer, builder, or grocer
instead of a poet, musician, painter, or sculptor, but to assume that whatever
he does he does because he is unable, for a variety of reasons, to do anything
else - in short, because it is the best thing for him. Heaven forbid that the human kind should ever
progress to a point where all men can become poets, composers, artists, or
writers simply because, with further development of machine technology, there
will be little or no requirement for anything else! Heaven forbid that we should look upon human
diversity as an objection, and subsequently endeavour to stamp everybody into
exactly the same mould!
Talented youths often
imagine that life is a battle for honours, a race to acquire the most
prestigious places before it is too late, rather than an exercise, amongst
other things, in finding out what one is especially good at and then in putting
that ability or gift to the service of mankind.
But youth is only a passing folly, an extra boost, as it were, to the
essential nature of the emerging man.
For when he finally emerges from his youthful pretensions into the more
realistic perspective of adulthood, he will realize that it is only within his
power to do a few things really well, and that he must do them to the best of
his ability if he is to pass muster on the world's stage.
Yet as to whether his
particular occupation makes him less wise than any of his differently-occupied
fellows - that is something I must confess to having serious reservations
about! Perhaps he is mostly drawing upon
his foolishness when he does something he has no business doing, working in an
incompatible context, and consequently being a neurotic nuisance to both
himself and everybody else as well.
THE MEANING AND PURPOSE OF LIFE: The meaning and purpose of life
cannot reside in anything which is subject to antithetical evaluation. In other words it cannot reside in happiness,
truth, love, goodness, work, beauty, wisdom, knowledge, reasonableness,
pleasure, virtue, etc., because of the inevitability and even necessity of
sadness, illusion, hate, evil, play, ugliness, folly, ignorance,
unreasonableness, pain, vice, etc., which, by their regular (negative) intrusions,
effectively guarantee the intermittent prevalence of the former (positive)
aspects of life, and are therefore of crucial importance in the overall scheme
of things.
No, the meaning and
purpose of life has to do with what Dr. Jolande Jacobi, the Hungarian psychologist and disciple of Jung,
terms 'the Way of Individuation' - a development of the personality through the
various stages of life, with the invariable consequence of greater knowledge of
the self both in its relation to the individual and to the world
generally. One doesn't foolishly strive
to combat the inherent dualism of life by taking an apparently one-sided though
ultimately self-deceptive stance in it.
One experiences this dualism as an eternal fact which, through its
comprehensiveness, inevitably redeems itself.
One could sum-up by saying that the meaning of life lies in life itself,
whereas the purpose of life is simply to live.
THE INFERIOR NEGATIVE: Whatever exists in a negative relationship
to the positive component of a duality exists as its inferior, viz. night in
relation to day, illusion in relation to truth, evil in relation to goodness,
sadness in relation to happiness, pain in relation to pleasure, ugliness in
relation to beauty, weakness in relation to strength, etc. The proof of this, if it isn't already
self-evident, can be defined in one of two ways, depending on the nature of the
duality under consideration.
The case, for example,
of night in relation to day brings to our attention the fact that the night is
simply a time without sunlight, a time when one half of the earth has turned
away from the sun. Hence the night is
quantitatively inferior to the day because it lacks something that the day
possesses - namely sunlight. The case,
however, of pain in relation to pleasure brings to our attention the difference
of quality between a sensation which is disagreeable and one, by contrast,
which is agreeable, the former being undesirable and hence inferior to the
latter.
Thus it can be contended
that dualities are essentially divisible into two categories: those which
permit one to judge the negative component quantitatively inferior to the
positive one on account of its lacking something which the latter possesses
and, similarly, those which permit one to judge the negative component
qualitatively inferior to the positive one on account of its undesirable
feeling or sensation value. Examples in
the first category include night in relation to day, silence in relation to
sound, darkness in relation to light, ugliness in relation to beauty, weakness
in relation to strength, evil in relation to good, illusion
in relation to truth. Examples in the
second category include pain in relation to pleasure, sadness in relation to
happiness, fear in relation to hope, hate in relation to love, humility in
relation to pride, dejection in relation to elation, anger in relation to
humour. The first category implies
objective phenomena, either internal or external, that we perceive but do not
feel. The second category implies
subjective phenomena, either internal or external, that we feel but do not
perceive.
FOUR CATEGORIES: Dualities may be further subdivided, as I hinted
above, into four categories, viz. those which pertain to the Internal
Objective, those which pertain to the External Objective, those which pertain
to the Internal Subjective, and those, finally, which pertain to the External
Subjective.
Those in the category of
the Internal Objective are dualities which we perceive internally but do not
feel. Those in the category of the
External Objective are dualities which we perceive externally but do not
feel. Examples of the former include
illusion/truth, sickness/health, past/future, absent/present. Examples of the latter include night/day,
dark/light, girl/boy, moon/sun.
Those in the category of
the Internal Subjective are dualities which we feel internally but do not
perceive. Those in the category of the
External Subjective are dualities which we feel externally but do not perceive. Examples of the former include fear/hope,
hate/love, pain/pleasure, sadness/happiness. Examples
of the latter include cold/hot, rough/smooth, liquid/solid, soft/hard.
Thus it can be seen that
both the Internal Subjective and the Internal Objective signify abstract
phenomena, whereas both the External Subjective and the External Objective
signify concrete phenomena.
NEGATIVES SERVE: Of what use would knowledgeable men be in any
given subject if there were no ignorant men in that same subject to learn from
their knowledge? And of what use would
ignorant men be in any given subject if they were insufficiently ignorant to be
of use to its knowledgeable men?
But let us not deceive
ourselves into imagining the positive component of a duality to be in the
service of its negative component, i.e. that which commands ... to be in the
service of that which obeys, or that which helps ... to be in the service of
that which hinders, or that which hopes ... to be in the service of that which
fears, or that which loves ... to be in the service of that which hates when,
in reality, it is invariably the other way around.
Now as ignorance is
negative in relation to knowledge, one can only conclude the ignorant men in
any given subject to be in the service of its knowledgeable men. Paradoxically, it is the pupil/student who
serves the teacher/tutor rather than vice versa.
SUCCESSFUL FAILURES: No man is absolutely or strictly a failure;
he is only a failure intermittently.
Whatever the level of life on which he happens to be living, he will
experience his periodic successes together (though not simultaneously) with his
periodic failures. A failure per se,
if such a person could exist, would be totally without successes. But to be totally without successes would
also mean to be totally without failures, since the former cannot exist without
the latter, the former are a consequence of the latter and therefore dependent
upon the latter for their existence.
We assume a person to be
a failure when he hasn't achieved something he desired, but overlook the fact that
he may have achieved something else, if only to disillusion himself with the
desire in question. Now many people whom
we customarily and perhaps even naively regard as successes on account, for
example, of their current wealth, status, fame, etc., may often regard
themselves in quite a different light - a light, I mean, in which only they can
see, and which exposes, amongst other things, their frustrated ambitions.
For where it may be the
ambition of one man to attain fame, a man who is already famous will have other
ambitions, some of which he may realize, others of which he may not. But, irrespective of their personal
circumstances, both men will experience similar feelings as regards their
respective ambitions, since they will be subject to the same conditions -
namely those of success and failure.
POSITIVELY SELFISH: No man can be genuinely satisfied with the
overall pattern of his life as long as he leads a relatively negative
existence, which is to say as long as he is insufficiently selfish during
the day. For whereas after a day of
comparative selfishness one's selflessness is established to a greater extent
in the evening, it is one's selfishness that is established to a greater extent
in the evening after a day of comparative selflessness. Hence to live in a relatively positive
manner, a manner in which an intelligent person should live, one would have to
adopt the former mode of existence and be comparatively selfish, i.e.
industriously preoccupied in a manner suitable to one's nature and abilities,
during the day, since, by contrast with the day, the evening is always
negative, and a relatively positive approach then will, of necessity, be
somewhat reduced both in its strength and its effect.
As is well known, the
evening is generally a time of repose, of acceptance and resignation, a
negative counterbalance to the positive struggles one is usually obliged to
experience during the day. It is not,
ideally, a time for selfishness. Only
those who are compelled, against their wishes, to lead a relatively negative
existence during the day would endeavour to make it so, though their
selfishness will, as already remarked, lose much of its effect and intensity in
the process.
A POSTHUMOUS B.C.: It seems difficult for someone accustomed to
referring to pre-Christian dates in terms of B.C. to realize that such dates
are only applicable to those who, like ourselves, look back from a Christian or
post-Christian society, not to those who actually lived in
pre-Christian times. The ancient Greeks,
for example, would not have thought in terms of 350 or 300 B.C., for the simple
reason that they had no idea that a man named Jesus Christ would appear in the
world approximately a few centuries later (in their future) and, unbeknown to
himself, subsequently become the source of the Christian calendar. Thus Socrates would not have been aware of
the fact that he lived from 430-399 B.C., since it was the Greek calendar which
prevailed in his time, rendering his concept of epoch considerably different
from ours.
Therefore it should be
apparent that reference to any date preceding the Christian era in terms of
B.C. is strictly a Western invention, a scale of historical reference only
relevant to those living in the A.D. centuries.
However, the fact that we are constantly deceiving ourselves in this
matter of affixing specified Western dates to peoples and individuals who would
not have recognized them should, I feel, be in some way more generally
acknowledged, especially by those who have a genuine interest in the study of
earlier civilizations, so that, as offspring of a later age, they may come to a
better understanding of the amount of fiction they habitually impose upon their
historical 'facts'.
SCHISMATIC CHRISTIANITY: The decline of Christianity began not, as
is generally believed, in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries but, rather,
in the sixteenth century, which is to say with the formulation of the 'Augsburg
Confession' by Melanchton in 1530, which officially
signalled the beginnings of Protestantism and, unknowingly at the time,
precipitated the downfall of Christianity.
For with the rise of Protestantism came an era of inter-Christian wars,
of what we may term the 'cannibalism of Christianity', when, ostensibly in the
name of the same God, Protestant killed Catholic and Catholic killed
Protestant, and the Christian civilization slowly bled itself to death.
Hitherto, in the various
guises of Catholicism, Christianity had fought as a single unit against
Mohammedanism and thus involved itself in religious wars, or wars between
different world religions. But with the
rapid rise of Protestantism in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries, the
chief conflict was fought not without but within the Church, which became plagued
by increasingly violent schisms from then onwards.
As a single unit
Christianity had become an extremely formidable force - indeed, so formidable as to be religiously totalitarian. But when divided into mutually hostile units,
Christianity weakened itself in a manner which no eighteenth- or
nineteenth-century rationalist ever did.
In a very real sense Protestantism was a form of early rationalism, a
forerunner of the Age of Enlightenment, and a force without which that age
could not have come into existence. For
by dividing the Church, Protestantism questioned the professed sovereignty of
the established faith and thereby considerably detracted from its claim to
omnipotence. As the ferocity of the
subsequent inter-Christian wars testified, once the divide had been created it
could never be repaired. And so the
'cannibalism of Christianity' continued to wreak havoc until such time as, with
the progressive weakening and decline of the Church, there was very little
spiritual flesh left to devour, and wholesale materialism accordingly became
the order of the day.
LIVE SYMBOLS: Words without spirit are dead symbols, devoid of
meaning. But it is only the appropriate
use of spirit that gives life to the word and thereby makes it meaningful in
the contexts by which we live. One can
imagine the effect created on a group of listeners by someone who said 'I feel
great' in an apathetic tone-of-voice - a droll effect to say the least! And, similarly, someone who said 'I feel
sick' in an exuberant tone-of-voice would inevitably create a strange effect on
his listeners, one they would have considerable difficulty not equating with a
form of schizophrenic derangement!
Indeed, the extent to
which words, as symbols of conditions and things, are dependent
upon the requisite use of spirit would undoubtedly amaze a person unaccustomed
to hearing the many relevant feeling-values and variations in pitch with which
we customarily invest them in conversation.
And it is highly doubtful that, even in the case of a highly intelligent
recipient, such a person would be able to understand so much as a fraction of
all the things said to him through words which had been deprived of spirit
altogether, or at least to the extent of being delivered in the form of a
tedious monotone.
In this respect, the
written word is usually less good than the spoken one. For although the writer should have informed
his writings with an appropriate use of spirit and thereby granted them a
certain recognizable colouring and timbre, it remains for the reader to
assimilate the written word into his own spirit, including of course the
condition of his spirit at the time, and if possible instantaneously translate
it into the spirit it was intended to convey - a thing that isn't always very
easy to do and, to cite personal experience, something that isn't always done!
Thus, on account of this
complicated process of spiritual translation, the written word is often
misconstrued and the writer misunderstood.
But with the spoken word, where intellect and spirit are usually in
harmony and therefore can be simultaneously comprehended, there is no need for
spiritual translation. So all it is
necessary for the listener to do is to assimilate it and then react
appropriately - a fact, it seems to me, which testifies to the eternal
superiority of the spoken over the written word!
INTERPLANETARY EQUILIBRIUM: Throughout the history of civilized
man people have often posed the question 'Why is there life on earth?' and
endeavoured to answer it in a variety of ways, some religious, others
scientific. The different viewpoints
appertaining to the reasons for life on this planet, and man's relationship to
whichever of the heavenly bodies he has hitherto been aware of, have ensured
that, with each succeeding generation, the question is posed and answered in a
different way or, at any rate, in a manner considered most suitable to the
understanding of the people of the time.
At present it is the
scientific viewpoint which prevails over the religious one where the
interpretation of this perennial mystery is concerned, and so it is to science,
in its manifold guises, that a majority of people look for a solution to those
problems which have vexed the greatest minds of the past. True, unlike religion, science does not and
cannot lay claim to omniscience in these matters. But with its largely empirical if not
hypothetical basis, it does at least suffice to draw one's attention to
possibilities which religion, grounded on a 'rock of faith', would
categorically deny, and thus facilitate the way for further and more detailed
inquiry. And so the question 'Why is
there life on earth?', considered scientifically, demands an answer that will
appeal to the contemporary mind in terms it will understand rather than in any
previous or outdated terms. Admittedly,
I am not a scientist. But, as a
philosophical writer, I can at least draw conclusions and formulate hypotheses
roughly compatible with a scientific outlook.
Hence the most obvious answer to the difficult question we have posed
is: 'Simply because life on earth was made possible.'
Of the major planets
currently known to man in the Solar System, it is a general assumption that the
earth is the only one with any form of intelligent life and, in all
probability, any life at all. We no
longer believe in Martians or the possibility of autonomous life on Mars, and
with our growing interest in the more distant planets we are fast coming to the
conclusion that life of whatever kind would be even less likely to exist on
them. And so if the earth is the only
life-sustaining planet, it may well puzzle some people what the other planets
are for, why, in fact, they exist at all.
My own theory of this
is, I think, a fairly plausible one - plausible, that is, for those who suffer
from a need to justify the prevailing cosmic order-of-things in this part of
the Galaxy. Whether or not the other
planets exist primarily to serve the earth, it seems that their existence,
willy-nilly, guarantees the life-sustaining power of the earth simply
by keeping it in a position, relative to themselves, where life is made
possible, but where the absence of one or more planets from the prevailing
order of things would so alter its orbital distance from the sun as to render
life on it utterly impossible or, at the very least, extremely improbable. Therefore we must assume that there exists an
interplanetary equilibrium which renders no planet superfluous, but keeps them
interdependent in the interests of a given planetary system. Life is made possible on the earth because
its distance from the sun - in part established by the gravitational pull of
each individual planet - gives rise to the formation of a life-sustaining
atmosphere, an atmosphere which could not exist on any planet positioned either
closer to or farther away from the sun.
Thus life could only be made impossible on the earth by something which
destroyed the prevailing interplanetary equilibrium, removing one or more of
the planets and thereby necessitating the establishment of a different
equilibrium - one which would so alter the earth's position vis-à-vis the sun
as possibly to transform it into the rough equivalent of Venus or Mars.
Now if, in consequence
of the destruction of Mercury, Venus was 'pulled in' to a much closer position
to the sun, it is highly probable that the earth would also be 'pulled in' to a
much closer position to it, and that Mars, which would also be drawn-in closer
to the sun, might duly find itself in a position where life was made possible
there in consequence of the formation, over a long period of time, of a
different atmosphere from what it now possesses. Thus Mars would become the rough equivalent
of the earth and, willy-nilly, the earth the rough equivalent of Venus, where
the maximum surface temperature is believed to be somewhere in excess of 800°F,
which is to say about 3¾ times that of boiling point. However, the difference of mass, volume,
density, etc., between the various planets would undoubtedly affect their
relative positions in the Solar System if such a change were to occur, so we
cannot be certain that Mars would necessarily take up a position exactly
corresponding to the one currently held by the earth. But an approximation there could well be, and
if this approximation of Mars to the earth was such that the formation of a
life-sustaining atmosphere became possible, then there would almost certainly
be life-forms on Mars after a number of millennia.
But in returning from
such 'far out' speculation to the Solar System as it now stands, we cannot be
sure to what extent the prevailing interplanetary equilibrium is governed by
the sun and to what extent it is also governed by the nearest foreign stars in
the Galaxy (as indeed the Galaxy and perhaps even the Universe as a
whole). It is, at any rate, unlikely
that the Solar System is a self-contained and totally-isolated unit which
exists independently of the rest of the Galaxy, of which the sun is but a
comparatively minor star. My own theory
is that the equilibrium of the Solar System is predominantly governed by the
sun but not exclusively so. Likewise, if
the core of this planet is molten hot and becomes progressively cooler and
harder towards the surface, my own theory as to the mechanism underlining this
equilibrium is that there are other planets that also possess a molten core
which exists, like the earth's, in an antithetically magnetic relationship to
the sun, but which is prevented from being sucked-in to it by the magnetic
influences being gravitated by certain other stars in the Galaxy which to a
certain extent counteract the sun's magnetic influence and thus produce the
tension necessary to maintaining the orbital variations of the individual
planets. Of course, I have to admit that
all this is purely speculative. For as
far as a comprehensive knowledge of the Galaxy and the workings thereof are
concerned, we are still in our infancy, not even having acquired a
comprehensive knowledge of the Solar System!
However, as to the
question 'Why is there life on earth?', I think the fact of its position vis-à-vis
the sun must be taken as the most credible answer, so that our attitude towards
the other planets should encompass an awareness of their function as a means,
effectively, to keeping a life-sustaining atmosphere in existence.
MAGNETIC RECIPROCITIES: If, to expand on the above hypothesis of
interplanetary equilibrium, we assume that our planet exists in a magnetically
antithetical relationship to the sun, which is literally hundreds of times
bigger than the earth, then it is difficult for us not to assume the core of
the former to be radically different from the core of the latter, so that the
innermost parts of the respective bodies signify a kind of north/south pole
antithesis which makes possible a magnetic reciprocity between them. At present we know next-to-nothing about the
innermost regions of planets and stars, although it has long been a general
hypothesis that the core of the former is likely to be different from the core
of the latter. Planets, it is assumed,
have a hard core while stars have a soft one, and, at face value, this does
seem to be the most sensible theory.
However, my own theory
is at present inclined to the contrary assumption - namely that planets have a
comparatively soft core and stars, by contrast, a hard one, so that the
external reality of both kinds of phenomena may be presumed to exist in an
antithetical relationship to their internal reality. Thus the earth would seem to be burning up
inside, in its innermost core, while the sun's innermost core is producing the
energy and providing the material upon which the outer parts burn. The sun would therefore be burning with a
positive energy, i.e. one generated from its innermost core, and the earth, by
contrast, with a negative energy, or one dependent upon the materials lying
closest to hand, upon which it sustains itself.
Thus a magnetic reciprocity would be established between them, by dint
of the nature of their respective types of energy.
Furthermore it would
seem that if, by circling the sun, the earth exists in an antithetical
relationship to it, then the moon, which circles the earth, must of necessity
exist in a like relationship to the earth, and one, moreover, which presupposes
a natural affinity with the sun. Here
again my hypothesis begs to differ from the general assumption relating to the
nature of the moon vis-à-vis the sun.
For instead of being antithetical to the sun, I would argue that the
moon is a kind of dead sun, a weak and negative sun of the night which shines
with a borrowed light (from the earth), and the hard core of which forms a
positive antithesis to the earth's soft one.
Now just as I argue that the earth is largely prevented from being
sucked-in to the sun by the competitive magnetic forces being exerted by
various other stars in the Galaxy, many of which are far greater than the sun
and may be presumed to be in perpetual struggle with one another for mastery
over particular planets, so it is logical for me to contend that the moon is
prevented from being sucked-in to the earth by the competitive magnetic forces
being exerted by various other planets in the Solar System, which likewise
struggle with one another for mastery over particular moons and, by attracting
the earth's moon to themselves, keep it in motion around the earth.
From this hypothesis it
should follow that, just as the largest stars in the Galaxy will have the most
number of circling planets, so the largest planets in the Solar System will
have the most number of circling moons - a contention which can, in fact, be
confirmed by an investigation of the relative number of moons attaching to each
of the planets. Jupiter,
the largest planet, has twelve moons, three more than Saturn, which is the next
largest. Then comes Uranus with
its five moons, Neptune with two, the earth with one, and finally Mars with two
extremely small moons, the larger of which (Phobus)
is merely ten miles in diameter. Mercury
and Venus, the two planets nearest to the sun, have no moons, probably because
they are too close to the sun to require any, that is to say because it is far
too hot for a negative sun (moon) to exist there, the overwhelming positivity of the sun preventing the possibility of any
such development. Likewise Pluto, the
farthest planet from the sun (though there is another planet or, at any rate,
asteroid still farther from it which has only been discovered comparatively
recently) has no moon, and probably because, extremes being virtually equal, it
is too far away from the sun to require one, which is to say because it is too
cold for a negative sun (moon) to exist there, the overwhelming negativity of
that part of the Solar System again precluding the possibility of any such
development. One cannot really contend
that such extreme planets as these have no moons simply because they are too
small. For, although a contention of
that nature might pass muster with regard to Mercury, which, as the smallest
planet in the Solar System, is a mere 2900 miles in equatorial diameter, it is
unlikely to do so with regard to both Venus and Pluto, the former, with an
equatorial diameter of 7700 miles, being a mere 227 miles smaller than the
earth, and the latter, with an equatorial diameter of approximately 9000 miles,
being at least 1300 miles larger than the earth. Thus it would seem that size (e.g. mass, volume, surface gravity, escape velocity) and position in
relation to the sun are the two principal factors in determining the number of
moons a given planet is likely to possess.
Also it is worth noting that the largest planets possess the largest
moons, Jupiter, for example, possessing two (Ganymede and Callisto)
with a diameter of over 3000 miles, Saturn possessing one (Titan) with a
diameter of over 3000 miles, Uranus three (Ariel, Titania,
and Oberon) with a diameter of 1500 miles, and Neptune one (Triton) with a
diameter probably in excess of 3000 miles.
Consequently, there can
be little doubt that planets struggle with one another for moons and possess a
number of moons in accordance with their capacity to support them. Likewise, it should follow that stars
struggle with one another for planets and possess planets in accordance with
their supportive capacity. Hence the
largest stars should possess either the largest or the most number of planets and
thus form the greatest solar systems, the greatest of all presumably being
positioned midway between the innermost and outermost stars of the Galaxy, i.e.
in a galactic position corresponding to the solar-system positions of the
largest planets, rather than actually nearest to the governing star. For it is likely that the actual nucleus of
the Galaxy, about which we know absolutely nothing, possesses a star, or ruling
body, of such magnitude as to govern not merely a solar system peculiar to
itself but, additionally, the courses of the 100,000 million-odd stars which
revolve around it in the fulfilment of their respective 'cosmic years'.
Thus we find ourselves
confronted by the possibility of a three-way system of reciprocal magnetic
influence. We have the central star of
the Galaxy which, whatever its actual nature, dictates the paths of individual
stars; we have the stars, which dictate the paths of individual planets; and
finally we have the planets, which dictate the paths of individual moons. A sun, we have assumed, forms the main positive
influence in a given solar system, the planets, drawn into circulation around
that sun, being comparatively negative.
However, the planets 'take revenge', so to speak, upon their sun by
dictating the paths that moons are to take around them
in a given solar system. For we must
assume that, although the planets are largely negative in relation to their
moons, their negativity is nevertheless far more powerful than the weak positivity of the moons' hard core. Now just as a large magnet with a south pole
will draw a smaller north-pole magnet towards itself, so the planets are able
to govern the orbits of individual moons.
As an afterthought, I
should like to point out the similarity of these cosmic speculations with those
of Newton and, conversely, their dissimilarity from Einstein's. For, as we know, Newton based his work on the
hypothesis of a magnetically-conditioned interplanetary equilibrium which gave
central power to the sun in determining the orbital inclinations of the various
planets in the Solar System. Einstein,
by contrast, developed the theory that space is curved and that all the planets
really do is to follow the natural curves mapped out for them, as it were, by
the curvilinear nature of space itself.
The sun, in other words, was not recognized by Einstein as the
all-important magnetic force it had been to Newton. Consequently, Einstein did much to
revolutionize the position of scientific speculation in this respect, causing
quite a stir in the world of early twentieth-century Western science, and
largely because he brought what might be described as an Eastern standpoint to
a world which, traditionally, had been dominated by force and mass in a kind of
open-society deference to cosmic fact.
Now this is not to say
that force and mass was incorrect or a misconception of what literally took
place in the Universe. But it was bound
to be challenged sooner or later by a standpoint that scorned the brute facts
of the matter in favour of a convenient fiction which would enable man, from
that time onwards, to perceive the workings of the Universe through a mystical
veil, as it were, in deference to transcendental criteria and a refusal, in
consequence, to recognize brute reality.
Such an anti-imperialist
and anti-autocratic concept as curved space surely has much to recommend it to
the future! But intellectual honesty
compels me to say that Newton was literally right and Einstein literally wrong,
even though his wrongness transpires to being an expedient 'right' so far as
the future is concerned, and not one that I, despite the apparent Newtonian
bias of this essay, would seriously wish to undermine. Certainly, I do not share Spengler's
view in this matter which, however true it may be in relation to the brute
facts of the Universe, can only obstruct evolutionary progress by prolonging
the kind of system and mentality which the Nazis were subsequently to bring to
a head in unequivocal deference precisely to those autocratic and imperialistic
tendencies which spring from an enslavement to such brute facts.
UNIVERSE OR UNIVERSES: If the moon revolves around the earth and
the earth revolves around the sun and that in turn revolves around the centre
of the Galaxy, then it seems feasible to contend that the centre of the Galaxy
revolves around the centre of the Universe and that maybe even the centre of
the Universe revolves around something greater than itself, and so on, in a
process without end. The concept of
multiple universes could then present itself to our comprehension as a
continuous manifestation of greater and greater degrees of revolution around a
central something which is always one step ahead, so to speak, of that which
revolves around it.
However, the logic of
this does entail a serious flaw. Why,
you may wonder, doesn't something
smaller than the moon revolve around the moon, and something smaller than the
something which should therefore revolve around the moon revolve around it, and
so on? Clearly, if there is a downwards
limit as to what revolves around what, the moon having nothing revolving around
it in the manner of planetary revolution around the sun, then it seems highly
probable that there must also be an upwards limit which is established if not
at that point where suns revolve around the centre of their particular galaxy,
then almost certainly at that point where the centres of galaxies revolve
around the centre of the Universe. If
the Universe is still understood to imply the totality of existing galaxies,
then the concept of multiple universes is still beyond our comprehension and
possibly no more than a figment of the imagination.
But if multiple
universes do exist, then the Western concept of a unitary universe is smashed
to pieces, the totality of galaxies becoming merely a phenomenon appertaining
to a tiny area of total space in which other universes - or immense galactic
clusters - exist as logical entities at virtually incalculable distances from
one another, and revolve in toto around
a body or bodies greater than themselves.
Probably the concept of
multiple universes derives, in any case, from a more evolved point-of-view
which can accommodate the notion of alternative atomicities
and thereby avoid being limited to just one monadic absolute such as would
correspond, in theological terms, to the Father at the expense not only of the
Son but of the Holy Spirit as well, and which would accordingly limit us to a
force/mass autocracy in traditional subservience to a unitary cosmos.
BETWEEN GOOD AND EVIL: The inorganic may be beneath good and evil
but nothing organic is. It is especially
in man that the concepts of good and evil attain to their greatest clarity,
that what is felt to be either the one or the other is given verbal definition
and understood in the context to which it pertains. Everything organic beneath man, from the
higher animals to the lower forms of plant life, is also subject to varying
degrees and kinds of good and evil, though their respective experiences are
merely felt rather than defined as being specifically good or evil. It is only with the inorganic, with the blind
forces of wind, rain, hail, snow, heat, etc., that good and evil have no
meaning, and therefore cease to apply.
Hence a violent
thunderstorm is no more evil in itself than a fine midsummer's day is
inherently good. A violent thunderstorm
may be interpreted as evil by a dog that hides under the bed or by a man who
runs for shelter somewhere other than under the branches of a tree, but it is
only such in relation to the organic, especially to the higher forms of organic
life. And the same, of course, applies
to a fine midsummer's day with a brilliantly clear sky and the sun shining down
onto the bodies of holiday-makers enjoying themselves on a sandy beach. They may interpret the favourable conditions
as being good, but the fact remains that such conditions are only 'good' in
relation to themselves as sentient beings.
For beneath the realm of the sentient, good and evil have no
applicability.
The good may be defined
as that which accompanies or engenders positive feelings, thereby making one
conscious of being happy or hopeful. The evil, by contrast, as that which accompanies or engenders
negative feelings, thereby making one conscious of being sad or fearful. A fine midsummer's day may well engender
positive feelings in one's mind in consequence of its favourable conditions and
thereupon be interpreted as a good, a veritable blessing. Thus anything that makes one feel either
pleased with oneself or pleased with life in general comes within the realm of
'the good' by dint of the positivity it
engenders. However, in the case of a
thunder storm it will be found that the noise of thunder, flashes of lightning,
torrents of rain, bleak clouds, etc., engender negative feelings in one's mind
and are thereupon instinctively interpreted as evil. Anything that makes one's hair stand on end
comes within the realm of 'the evil' by dint of the negativity it engenders,
the worst experiences being those which engender the most negativity.
If one had a scale for
both positive and negative feelings ranging, for example, from 1-10 in each
direction, one could ascertain the extent of 'the good' or of 'the evil' being
experienced by simply taking note of one's feelings at the time. We do not, of course, have an exact means of
doing this, but if we remember that good and evil are inextricably bound-up
with our feelings, then we can always acquire an approximate indication as to
where we stand in relation to them at any given time. The greatest good will be
manifested in feelings of bliss, the greatest evil in feelings of sheer agony
or dejection. The degree of pleasure one
experiences in any given context stands in direct proportion to the extent of
'the good', the degree of pain, by contrast, in direct proportion to the extent of 'the evil'.
It is foolish to pretend
that one should live solely in 'the good', or that evil is something which
should be eradicated from the world in the interests of life. On the contrary, so long as there is life,
good and evil must co-exist in its interests.
One cannot experience pleasure if one knows nothing of pain, one cannot live in 'the good' unless one is regularly
accustomed to also living in 'the evil'.
Strange as it may seem, every time one experiences evil, i.e. negative
feelings, whether engendered by a nightmare, thunderstorm, quarrel, fall,
rebuff, cold, stomach ache, toothache, contempt, hatred, anger, worry,
derision, etc., one is unconsciously earning one's subsequent good, i.e.
positive feelings, whether engendered by a kiss, beautiful dream, glass of
wine, pleasant walk, favourite music, pride, complacency, love, respect,
admiration, etc.
The interdependence of
good and evil is indisputable and cannot be torn apart. One can, of course, deceive oneself as much
as one likes. One can call one's evil
experiences good and reject the theory that good and evil are inextricably
bound-up with the nature of one's feelings.
But even then one will be as subject to their influences as anyone else
and be unable to do anything to alter them.
The nightmares will continue regardless, and so, too, will the physical
maladies which regularly beset one. If
life was entirely evil, we could condemn it.
But the fact that it is also given to good, which is ultimately
dependent upon 'the evil' for its authenticity, its place in life, obliges us
to accept life's overall logic for what it is, and thus resign ourselves to
living it. We may condemn life under
pressure of unfavourable circumstances, but we are just as likely to extol it
when circumstances become favourable. That is the
human condition, and that is what we have to face!
PART TWO:
ESSAYISTIC APHORISMS
1. We all possess a
tendency to progressively underestimate a book, whether prosodic, philosophic,
or poetic, which we had previously read and enjoyed, and mainly because we have
forgotten most of what delighted us about it at the time. We may, for example, have been highly
enthusiastic about Hamsun's Mysteries at the
time of reading it. A year or two later
we recall a few shreds of memory associated with our favourite passages from
the novel, and these in turn we may couple to a vague recollection that Mysteries was a
great book. But largely because our
minds have moved on to fresh literary pastures, the initial enthusiasm
engendered by this novel has if not altogether disappeared then considerably
subsided, and we quickly discover the potential for flippancy, superficiality,
indifference, oversimplification, irony, exaggeration, hostility, etc., lurking
dangerously beneath the fragile surface of our judgement of it. In truth, one is always obliged to outgrow a
previous experience. The author of a
brilliant book yesterday may well become the author of a comparatively
uninspiring one today - at least, as far as the reader is concerned!
2. If as writers and
thinkers you cannot clear the ground of what has gone before, you will never
have room to raise your own constructions.
All great writers are also destroyers.
Not only do they create new works but, in the process, destroy the
reputations of old ones, especially those whose reputations were ripe for
destruction. But when is the
reputation of an old work ripe for destruction?
As soon as a writer has found a substantial hole in it, which is to say
as soon as he has exposed the lie in it!
Then and only then is it in the wrong and he in the right. But until they are 'found out', even the most
undeserved reputations, or decrepit foundations, will remain intact.
3. As
a final product, a literary translation is never more than a combination of
author and translator, a creation which, strictly speaking, stems neither from
the one nor the other. Hence Nietzsche's
Also Sprach Zarathustra
effectively becomes, when translated into English, the product of a third
factor - that of the author and translator combined. Thus Nietzsche's work, translated into
English by Hollingdale, effectively becomes the work
of 'Nietdale', or something of the sort. For we are reading neither
Nietzsche's words nor Hollingdale's thoughts.
4. I distinguish between
three kinds of literary masterpiece, viz. the small, the medium, and the
large. The small applies to a work of
under 200 pages in length, the medium to a work of 200-399 pages, and the large
to a work in excess of 400 pages. To
give an example of each kind of literary masterpiece, I regard Camus' The Outsider as a small
masterpiece, Hamsun's Mysteries as a
medium-sized masterpiece, and Joyce's Ulysses as a large
masterpiece. As might be expected, it is
then logical for me to contend Ulysses to be greater than both Mysteries
and The Outsider, but Mysteries to be greater than The
Outsider.
5. There are always authors
who refrain from drawing attention to the works of certain other authors not,
as might at first appear, because they don't particularly like their works (or,
for that matter, their authors), but primarily because they are acutely
conscious of the striking similarities between their own work and the works of
these others, or acutely conscious, it may be, of how profoundly influenced
they were by them, and therefore do not wish to be regarded as mere
plagiarists.
6. There are those who not
only regard their collection of books as a kind of 'work of art' in itself,
that is to say as a carefully-determined, pre-arranged, and almost
regimentally-ordered selection of interrelated material, but, more importantly,
as a kind of 'intellectual shrine' in the presence of which they often pay
unconscious, and sometimes conscious, homage to the deity of their literary
obsessions. One doesn't act unseemly,
i.e. flippantly or disrespectfully, in the presence of one's array of choice
books. On the contrary, one retains an
appropriate decorum which testifies to an almost religious awe and devotion
vis-à-vis the proximity of intellectual greatness, as though one's bookcase
were a kind of altar to the intellect upon which the vertical columns of books
repose in sanctified beatitude.
7. All Christians who
genuinely believe in Heaven and Hell should be aware of the fact that the
concept of Heaven is only feasible because of the antithetical concept of Hell,
and that unless, in strict accordance with the intrinsic dualism of Christian
theology, 'the wicked' were destined for Hell, 'the good' themselves would
never be able to enter Heaven. In short,
their presumed future salvation partly depends upon the damnation of 'the
wicked'. They are in great need of 'the
wicked' if there is to be any salvation at all.
8. Many of those rather
insular people who believe in the concept of a Creator 'up above', a Creator
who is Lord of the Universe, tend to overlook the fact that there is
undoubtedly a great deal more to the Universe than they naively imagine, and
that, in all probability, it also extends to an incalculable extent 'down
below'. But let us not ignore the fact
that an Englishman and an Australian would each be pointing in opposite
directions if they stood in their own country and posited a Creator 'up above'. The Englishman's 'above' would be the
Australian's 'below', and vice versa.
9. If one could distinguish
between priests who take those aspects of the Bible literally which were better
taken symbolically and, conversely, those who take symbolically that which
appears literal, I feel certain that, even these days, there would be more
priests in the former category than in the latter one. In other words, there would be more priests
who would believe material relating, for example, to the Garden of Eden to be
an historical documentation of something that actually existed and happened
than ones who, taking it symbolically, regard it as an account of man's rise to
consciousness and the inevitable break with an unconscious, and comparatively
blissful, identification with nature which this attainment necessarily entailed,
as, outgrowing the animal plane, man became fully human and was obliged to
abandon nature, or the 'Garden', for the toil and struggle of the world, with
its redemptive promise. Thus could the
clerical wheat be divided from the clerical chaff, as one sought to distinguish
the more imaginative and possibly intelligent priests from their comparatively
simpleminded, fundamentalist, and Bible-punching colleagues!
10. Man is neither an angel
nor a demon but a being who incorporates aspects of
both the angelic and the demonic.
However, to refer to him as both angel and demon would hardly be nearer
the truth! For such arbitrary
designations presuppose absolutes, or ideal beings, which exist independently
of each other and are thus incapable of mutual reconciliation. All one can reasonably contend is that there
is a 'watered-down' angel and a 'watered-down' demon in every man; a part which
aspires towards the angelic and, conversely, a part which aspires towards or,
rather, stems from the demonic, without ever being in a position to make man
either wholly the one or the other.
11. Whether, in fact, there
was only one First Cause or, alternatively, numerous First Causes ... is
something about which we have no definite knowledge at this point in time. Although scientists are inclined to reason,
probably in deference to a monotheistic tradition, in terms of a single First
Cause, a 'Big Bang', as it is somewhat colloquially called, the probability is
that there were many creative influences, though not necessarily in this galaxy
(of which our solar system is but a tiny and relatively insignificant
component), but throughout the universe of galaxies as a whole. After all, polytheism preceded monotheism in
the evolution of religion from gods to God, and it could be that the concept of
a First Cause is simply a more evolved scientific point-of-view than that of
First Causes - one analogous to monotheism.
12. It should always be
remembered that the use of the term 'First Cause' indicates a scientific
point-of-view, the use of the term 'God' or 'Creator', by contrast, a religious
one. Strictly speaking, the scientists
are no more wrong to reject God than the priests to reject the First
Cause. What we are dealing with here are
two ways of looking at the Universe, a factual and a figurative, a scientific
and a religious, and anyone who specializes in the one can hardly be partial to
the other, since they tend to be as mutually exclusive as monarchs and popes.
13. When we say that the sun
is in the region of 93,000,000 miles away, we indicate that at least we know in
theory what an immense distance the sun is from the earth. As, however, to knowing in practice what
93,000,000 miles are, none of us will ever do so, and consequently our
knowledge of this astronomical fact remains incomplete or, at best, highly
partial. Modern science presents us with
a considerable number of fantastic figures to swallow, many of which are
considerably more fantastic than the simple example cited above. Though, for all its breathtaking achievements
in this context, we are usually left little or no wiser in the long run!
14. I can state that the
average human brain is composed of approximately a billion neurons, or nerve
cells, but I cannot expect you to know exactly what a billion of anything
actually means, still less how we arrived at this fantastic figure. You will, of course, have the impression that
a tremendous number of neurons are involved in the brain's composition. But that, alas, is as much as you can
gather! Our fantastic figure will remain
an isolated fact, not really telling us very much about anything at all. Thus we are regularly confronted, in modern
science, by what may be termed the triumph of facts and figures over meaning. Unfortunately, the greater the lacunae
between these facts and figures and our practical understanding of them, the
greater is the danger of our becoming the dupes and victims of abstractions
which exist beyond the pale of rational comprehension. In this respect, modern science has to a
significant extent annexed the premium on faith formerly held by orthodox
religion.
15. To suggest that we
humans live in a man's world would be as presumptuous as for ants to suggest,
assuming they could speak, that they live in an ant's world, or for flies to
suggest that they live in a fly's world, since there are as many different
kinds of worlds as there are living species.
However, it is of course fair to suggest that we live in a man's world
insofar as we are human beings, just as it would be reasonable for ants or
flies to suggest that they live in their own respective worlds insofar as they
are different kinds of insects. But
their worlds, the contexts in which they live, would not qualify them to know
for a fact that the earth belonged to them, any more than our world, the
context in which we live, qualifies us to know for a fact that it belongs to
us. All we can really be certain of is
that we live on it, and that our lives co-exist with those of the many other
species who co-inhabit it. For we are
dealing here with an ecological balance which affects everyone ... from the
smallest of the small to the biggest of the big, and which ultimately serves to
indicate the eternal interdependence of the many species who subsist on a
common planet.
16. Our flight from boredom,
time, pain, worry, etc., often leads us to turn simple wisdom into complex
folly. We are never satisfied that we
know enough, even though we usually know far more than we need to know in order
to survive, as well as far more than is generally good for us, and are
consequently led to undermine the intrinsic value of much of our
knowledge. Beyond a certain point
knowledge acquires the same treatment as material possessions: the more of it
we have the less value do we attach to its individual parts and the more value,
by sheer force of habit, to accumulating as much of it as possible. Knowing too much is the spiritual counterpart
of possessing too much, and all extremities are equally fatal!
17. The picture one has of
the world is so related to the nature of one's intelligence that the most
intelligent people will never appear recognizable as such to those of lower
intelligence, to those, in other words, who have no compatible criterion by which
to evaluate and/or appreciate their intelligence. What one sees of a person of greater
intelligence is only what one's intelligence permits one to
see, not the greater intelligence itself.
Hence one is always restricted to a partial and necessarily misleading
perspective of people more intelligent than oneself.
18. An extremist in one
context will always be moderate in another.
Indeed, one wouldn't know anything about moderation at all unless one
was also extreme, unless one's extreme tendencies served both as a goad and as
a counterbalance to one's moderate tendencies, since, without their periodic or
intermittent prevalence, there would be no moderation at all. Hence an 'extreme man' and a 'moderate man'
are both essentially figments of the imagination. It is as impossible to be exclusively the one
as it is to be exclusively the other.
19. What one is conscious of
in oneself one generally assumes other people to be conscious of as well. A man who is conscious of the fact that he is
untidily dressed, as he walks along the street, and who at the same time feels
ashamed of it, is virtually compelled, on such an occasion, to assume that
every time another person looks at him, particularly when that other person is
smartly dressed, it is for no other reason than to secretly criticize him for
being untidily dressed. Whatever one
feels internally inevitably conditions one's relationship to the external
world. One is for the most part inclined
to project oneself into the world without in the least being aware that that is
all or what one is actually doing.
20. One often feels, after
having recovered from an illness, that one has 'paid one's dues' to illness for
some time to-come, in consequence of which there is little or no possibility of
one's immediately becoming ill again. So
one can afford to be a little more reckless or a little less cautious in one's
attitude to health for a while - this, at any rate, is how one generally feels
at the time. Unfortunately, there always
comes another time when, in being more reckless or less cautious, one pushes
one's luck too far and consequently succumbs to a fresh illness through the
folly of believing oneself to be almost immune to illness, of putting too much
confidence in one's health. Yet one
isn't necessarily wrong to do so.
Perhaps one's deeper self required a fresh illness just at that time in
order to correct one's mistaken perspective of the relationship between health
and sickness, and thereby rejuvenate one's pleasure in health? For to be well all of the time would probably
amount to a grave affliction, something in which few if any of us would be able
to take much lasting pleasure, and certainly something of which few if any of
us would have much lasting experience!
21. Travelling is another
means of increasing one's sense of power.
Ultimately, one runs the risk of only associating with people who are
widely travelled, the most powerful, in this context, being those who have
visited the most number of countries, especially the most distant countries. Like religion, politics, science, sport,
etc., travel is just another way of dividing people. And yet, it isn't simply egocentricity or
vanity which creates the divisions but, more usually, the need to associate
with people who can appreciate one's experiences. Then it is that they can be properly
understood and objectively evaluated.
For a person with little interest in travel would fail to appreciate the
nature of those experiences and thereby considerably detract from one's sense
of power. It is, above all, the need to
assert, foster, and witness one's power that drives one in search of 'kindred
spirits'.
22. How often we find the
word 'idealism' used in a context where instead of making matters better, the
ideas behind it would ultimately make them worse? Is not 'idealism' one of the most misused
expressions in the English language?
Indeed, one has to be extremely careful here, to tread one's way with
cautious feet, lest one inadvertently upsets the precarious balance of realism
and idealism in favour of an idealism that would not only transpire to making
matters worse than they were already, but would simultaneously poison one's
sense of realism and thereby transform one into the most pernicious kind of
idealist. For an idealist in this sense isn't
necessarily a man without any realism.
On the contrary, he is usually a man who stands reality on its head, in
order that he may have the perverse pleasure of disparaging it in the name of
an impossible existence. And sometimes
he isn't even that; sometimes he is a man who is merely - playing with words!
23. The
more one conceives with the mind, the faculty of thought, the less one can
perceive with the senses. Eventually,
the senses begin to atrophy and the thinker, insofar as he is permitted, either
accepts the situation for what it is or, if worried by the noticeable
deterioration in the condition of his sensual perception, attempts to give more
attention to the senses, even to the extent of becoming a sort of sensualist. But the most likely way for a thinker to do
so is, of course, to think on the value of the senses and then possibly write
in praise of sensuality,
establishing a subtle self-deception in the interests of
thought. For a thinker is always
prepared to turn his private mistakes or shortcomings into a public lesson,
albeit duly disguised under the mantle of objective thought.
24. The
more one utilizes one's energies and talents in one context, the less one can
utilize them in another. If, as a
writer, one spends a few months typing-up a work which one had previously
drafted in ink, one will become a fairly good typist but a comparatively poor
writer, and, in returning to one's notebook at a later date, will probably have
to persevere with a certain degree of creative incompetence or impotence for a
few days, while retraining one's mind to slot into the groove of creative
writing again. Thus it could be
contended that habit rather than talent or intelligence is the fundamental
mainstay behind the literary achievements of creative writers. Without routine all is lost. The mind goes where we send it, and if we
send it away from our creative tasks, then we have only ourselves to blame when
it proves less than responsive to creation at a later date. We shouldn't accuse it, on returning from
some other preoccupation, of being insufficiently creative when, as often
happens, we hadn't conditioned it to being such!
25. To
be a thinker, in the deepest sense of that term, one must have all day in which
to cultivate the difficult art of thinking, all day in which to live as a
philosopher. One cannot be a thinker in
one's spare time, after one has done one's duty elsewhere. For one will not only have to contend with
the relative negativity of the evening (assuming one works during the day), the
shortage of time in which to collect and develop one's thoughts, the fact of
knowing oneself to be an amateur thinker on account of one's diurnal occupation
and its possibly humbling effects upon one's psychology (not to mention the
humbling effects that certain fellow workers may have on it), the reduction of
energy and commitment one experiences in consequence of the effects of that
occupation, the possibility of neighbour or family distractions, and the
temptation to relax, to indulge in reading, listening to music, watching
television, holding conversation, etc., as a natural inclination,
but, in addition to some or all of these factors, one will also have to contend
with the virtual inevitability that one's objectively-oriented conditioning
during the day, far from enhancing one's ability to think deeply, actually
reduces it, so that, in spite of any good intentions one may have, one would
ultimately be fighting a lost cause. In
sum, one can only be a thinker professionally, not in one's spare time!
PART THREE:
APHORISMS (MAXIMS)
1. Evil is the root of all
goodness.
2. The truth of an
obsession is the illusion of free-will.
3. Where men of similar
capabilities are concerned the man just past his prime is naturally inferior to
the one just approaching it.
4. Sleep is our natural
drug.
5. Women teach men the true
value of man just as men teach women the true value of woman.
6. Just as man represents
the positive principle of life without being entirely positive, so woman
represents its negative principle without being entirely negative. A creature who was entirely the one thing or
the other would be unable to exist.
7. Procreation is a virtue
of 'the negative', copulation a vice of 'the positive'.
8. There are many so-called
philanthropists who help one section of humanity chiefly by hindering another.
9. One lies just as much by
feigning emotions as by not telling the truth.
10. Nothing is more certain
than death, but, then again, nothing is more uncertain than when it will come.
11. A man who shoulders more
responsibility than he can reasonably carry is being just as irresponsible as
one who doesn't shoulder enough.
12. Truth is never more
difficult to accept than when it comes from the lips of someone we dislike.
13. Were it not for the
demerits of the ugly one would never be able to appreciate the merits of the
beautiful. A man who loves beauty should
never be one to rid the world of ugliness!
14. One should always be a
good despiser for the sake of those whom one admires.
15. Ignorance is the root of
all knowledge.
16. One would only have the
right to consider all men equal if one had never felt either inferior or
superior to anyone.
17. Astrology is to some
extent a substitute for the Intervention of
18. Were it not for our
folly it is highly doubtful that we would take as much interest in wisdom as we
do.
19. If there is anything
worse than the spectacle of an uneducated man who is ashamed of his ignorance,
it can only be that of an educated one who is ashamed of his knowledge.
20. The human kind is no
more a particularly pleasant species than it is a particularly unpleasant
species. It is a combination of both.
21. Where physical love is
concerned, it is mainly the man who gives and the woman who takes. But where emotional love is concerned, it is
mainly the woman who gives and the man who takes.
22. There is no good and
evil beyond the actions of living beings.
23. Sky is an illusion of
the day, space a truth of the night.
24. One can relate to
something in everyone, to everything in no-one.
25. What one says about
other people usually reflects what one thinks about oneself.
26. A man who lacked a
capacity for cruelty could never be genuinely kind.
27. One always overlooks the
things one's memory remembers when criticizing it for something it forgot.
28. In order to compensate
women for the fact that men are generally physically stronger than themselves
nature has generally taken care to endow them with more spirit.
29. Truth is the object of
science, illusion the subject of art.
30. We are more readily
inclined to forget the wrongs we have done to others than to forget the wrongs
others have done to us.
31. Our virtues are often
vices in disguise.
32. A rich man with bad
health is more unfortunate than a poor one whose health is good.
33. Just as we are ignorant
of the extent of our knowledge, so we have no knowledge of the extent of our
ignorance.
34. As
a rule the head prevails over the heart in man, the heart over the head in
woman.
35. A deeply emotional man
is as unusual as a highly intellectual woman.
36. Just as one would soon
find the daylight intolerable if it wasn't frequently interrupted by the dark,
so one would soon find goodness intolerable if it wasn't frequently interrupted
by evil.
37. Nature is a sovereign
power that will not tolerate being dictated to by man.
38. Where emotion was high
the memory is long.
39. If women possess more
vivid memories than men it is primarily because they are more emotional.
40. It is as foolish to
apply religious criteria to science as to apply scientific criteria to
religion.
41. It is better to be
rational than irrational but, all the same, one shouldn't endeavour to be too
rational.
42. There is a conservative
element in every 'radical', a radical element in every 'conservative'.
43. Just as atonal music is
against tonality, so an atheist is against theism.
44. An atheist may be
someone who disbelieves in the existence of God, but he isn't necessarily one
who disbelieves in the Devil.
45. The harder one works the
easier one plays.
46. If the future stands in
an antithetical relationship to the past, then the present must stand in a like
relationship to the absent.
47. People differ as widely
in their conception of good and evil as in their conception of truth and
illusion.
48. The only consolation for
being a realist in practice is to become an idealist in theory.
49. There is nothing painful
in life which doesn't ultimately contribute towards one's pleasure in it.
50. For all her emancipation
and new-found power, woman remains - and will doubtless continue to remain - in
the service of man. Every 'negative'
principle exists in a like serving capacity.
51. What Christians call
'faith' is to be found to some extent in every man, though not necessarily
within the context of Christianity.
52. Better to be materially
poor but rich in spirit than materially rich but poor in spirit.
53. The material universe
only exists because there is a spiritual universe behind it - astrology in
relation to astronomy.
54. It is as inconceivable
that the Universe should be entirely rational as that it should be entirely
irrational. It can only be both.
55. Mind is a consequence of
matter, not something that exists in an antithetical relationship to it, like a
space, a vacuum, or a void.
It is formed in and by the brain.
56. Never forget that the
two chief functions of the mind, viz. dreaming and thinking, are interrelated,
so that he who dreams well is all the better qualified to think.
57. The path of wisdom lies
in naturalness. Only the jungle of
artifice obscures it.
58. The perfect humanistic
society is always evenly balanced between competition and co-operation.
59. No man can consider
himself wise who does not accept his folly.
60. One should beware of
regarding life and death as antithetical.
For the only real antithesis to life is the not-life, the only real
antithesis to death is - birth.
61. Were it not for the
strength of our pride, it is highly doubtful that we would be able to survive
life's many humiliations.
62. Shame of ignorance is a
mark of ignorance, not of knowledge.
63. If there is a limitation
to human knowledge it isn't something of which we should feel ashamed, any more
than a bird should feel ashamed for being unable to fly above a certain height.
64. Inasmuch as it is the
duty of politics to take care of the 'body' of a nation, it is the duty of
religion to take care of its 'soul'.
65. Doctors and
psychiatrists exist in a negative relation to politicians and priests. For whereas the former endeavour to rid the
individual of his sickness, the latter endeavour to maintain the health of the
community.
66. Status is usually
conferred upon a man in proportion to the extent of his intelligence, upon a
woman in proportion to the extent of her beauty.
67. One inevitably pays for
one's abstract thought with the coinage of concrete experience.
68. To the true Christian a
Satanist is less of an enemy than an atheist.
69. There is nothing a
comedian is more serious about than the telling of jokes.
70. If one could reverse
time one might not make all the same mistakes again, but one would certainly
make a lot of new ones!
71. Were it not for his
illusions, a scientist would be in no way qualified to deal with truth. Likewise, were it not for his truths, an
artist would be in no way qualified to deal with illusion.
72. There are a number of
grounds for believing that people of different race but similar temperament
have more in common with one another than people of different temperament but
similar race.
73. The
ego rules by day, but the soul rules at night.
74. The 'objective man' is
as much a figment of the imagination as the 'subjective man'. One can only be both.
75. A tolerable life is
always found between multitude and solitude, never exclusively in either
extreme.
76. There is nothing more
attractive to the eyes of a natural man than the sight of a beautiful
woman. But, conversely, there is nothing
more unattractive to him than the sight of an ugly one.
77. Even in the most
intimate of relationships, what we know about a person is usually a very
limited affair compared with what is ordinarily concealed from our knowledge.
78. The act of prayer is
man's most sublime form of egotism.
Through it the weak individual attains to a personal relationship with
'The Almighty'.
79. Sleep is the one
phenomenon that no man grows tired of.
80. One best respects the
essentially feminine in women by despising woman.
81. Only a teacher can
regularly ask a question to which he already knows the answer without feeling
particularly eccentric.
82. There is only one
certain remedy for a man who doesn't work in accordance with his desires -
namely, neurosis.
83. When we cannot boast of
our successes we take a perverse pride in grumbling of our failures.
84. To die for a cause is
usually to give birth to an effect.
85. It is rather
difficult for human beings to appreciate, but the fact nonetheless remains that
cats have absolutely no desire to regard themselves as 'cats'.
86. Those who
endeavour to take delight in that which doesn't deserve to be delighted in ...
inevitably weaken their ability to take delight in what does.
87. There are some things
which it is important to take for granted in order not to take everything for
granted.
88. If it is true to say
that we often forget much of what we intended to remember, it is no less true
to say that we often remember much of what we intended to forget.
89. It is questionable
whether any great artist has ever been ahead of his day. In matters relating to his art, most of the
public have usually been behind it.
90. A truly great artist
should possess the ability to arouse the aesthetic sensibility of even the most
philistine temperament.
91. Those who imagine that
art should mirror life inevitably cast a poor reflection upon themselves.