literary transcript

 

CHAPTER III

 

Socrates

 

I - THE LIFE OF SOCRATES

 

IN the previous chapter we traced the rise and fall of Athenian democracy.  We must now turn our attention to the one Athenian of this period of whose personality we can claim to have intimate knowledge.  If we look at the portraits which are preserved to us of the great politicians and poets of the fifth century - Aeschylus, Cimon, Themistocles, Alcibiades - we can admire their dignity and poise, but we cannot claim that they gave us any understanding of the men whom they portray.  They are types like the characters in Ben Jonson, not Shakespearian people.  But even a second-rate copy of an original of Socrates is bursting with vitality.  Not even the reticence and austerity of classical sculpture can prevent his personality from dominating the marble and breaking the sculptor's rules.  We get the impression of an individual so unique and so vital that he cannot be fitted into any of the established types.

      Who was this individual whose personality has endured when all the famous men of the period have become thin and ghostly shades, mere names appended to great events?  Socrates was not a famous politician, but an ordinary Athenian citizen who served his city in the normal routine of peace and war.  He was not a great artist or poet: though he wrote poems, they are not preserved.  He was not even a scientist or philosopher, in the usual sense; for he made no discoveries, and, if he wrote any philosophy, not a word of his writings survive.

      Socrates was not famous for anything - except for being Socrates.  In a sense he did nothing, and yet he was and is one of the greatest figures of European civilization.  Of him and of a few others - Jesus and St Francis for instance - it can be truly said that their lives and individualities have moulded the shape of our innermost being and are still the inspiration of the best that is in us.

      For this reason it is impossible to write an account of Socrates' teaching or to analyse and evaluate his philosophy.  To understand Socratic philosophy it is necessary to know the man, and this can only be done by reading the Dialogues of Plato.  For Plato devoted nearly all his literary activity to the composition of dialogues in which Socrates is the leading character.  Many of them are highly realistic descriptions of actual conversations which took place before Plato was born: and to make them true to life Plato took enormous pains to reconstruct Periclean Athens and to recapture the spirit of Athenian democracy, which he himself had never known.

      The chief justification for any description of Socrates is that it may persuade the reader to go to Plato himself and to read the Apology, the Crito, the Phaedo, the Protagoras, and the other dialogues in which Socrates' spirit has been so miraculously preserved.  No modern account of Socrates can pretend to provide any real substitute for reading the dialogues themselves: and in this chapter there can only be a bare outline of his life, and a bare indication of the significance of his teaching.

      Socrates was born in 469 B.C., ten years after the battle of Salamis, and died in 399, four years after Athens had capitulated to Sparta.  Thus he lived through the period of Athens' greatest glory and greatest humiliation.  Scarcely a year of his life passed without some notable victory or defeat for his native country.  He was an Athenian citizen of respectable family and, like all citizens of Athens, he spent a considerable amount of time on active service, and on two occasions at least we hear of his courage on the field of battle.  But the first forty years of his life were otherwise uneventful.  As far as we know, he took no part in politics until he was an old man, and throughout the stress and clamour of the years in which Athens was struggling to achieve supremacy on sea and land, he did no more than fulfil the routine obligations of citizenship and enjoy the life of Periclean Athens.

      Socrates was above all things a citizen of Athens.  He loved the city, with its glorious buildings and its thriving port - the metropolis of the Aegean.  He was proud to claim the privileges of Athenian citizenship and to feel that he was a living part of the city which was 'the school of Hellas'.  Unhindered by aristocratic snobbery or political prejudices, he mixed with all sorts and conditions of men, and in democratic Athens he could talk to generals and statesmen, to artists and craftsmen, to philosophers and scientists, with the easy openness and equality of which Pericles spoke in his funeral speech.  For Athens in the days of her greatness attracted to her everything that was good in Hellenic culture, and within her walls a man could learn to know at first hand all the 'glories that were Greece'.

      It is therefore not surprising that Socrates for most of his life was content to live quietly in Athens.  At first he was probably best known for his extraordinary appearance.  A small, scrubby man, thick-set and clumsy, with an enormous head, and eyes sunk deep below a bulging forehead - he was likened by his contemporaries to an ugly satyr.  But if his appearance was ludicrous he was feared by everyone with whom he talked for his sardonic humour and his 'Socratic irony', that naive innocence and apparent ignorance which could with a single simple question explode a pretentious theory and 'debunk' hypocrisy.  The few who knew him really well loved him for the friendliness which lurked under his grim exterior and the honesty which made his debunking not mere cleverness but a genuine effort to sift truth from falsehood.

      About 430 Socrates suddenly became a public figure.  The Oracle at Delphi was still respected by all Greece as the voice of Apollo.  Before any important enterprise every city would send an embassy to discover whether Apollo was favourable and, for a fee, the Delphic priests would conduct the prophetess to the Holy Chasm, where, inspired with mysterious fumes, she 'spoke with tongues', and her words were interpreted by the priests into riddling poems.  The embassy would then return home and seek to elucidate the miracle of the Oracle.  That the Oracle was corruptible had been proved on many occasions.  The Alcmaeonidae had found it useful and had paid for its services by rebuilding the temple.  It had been notoriously pro-Persian in 480, and in return the Persian invaders had left its riches untouched.  And yet Delphi was still respected.  For its priests were always well-informed and a 'tip' from the Oracle had often saved the city or an individual from destruction.  It was therefore no small thing when in answer to a question from one of Socrates' devotees, the Oracle declared him the wisest man in all Greece.

      It is difficult to analyse Socrates' feelings when he heard the news.  For all his rationalism, he was, as we shall see later, a religious man; and though he may have doubted the motives of the priests, he must have felt that in some sense God had spoken and declared that he knew what no other man knew.  This fact gave him a new sense of vocation.  Hitherto he had been content to enjoy the pleasures of Athenian society: now he became urgently aware of a duty which he must perform and a mission he must fulfil.  No sudden change of life was demanded of him - to the outside observer he behaved precisely as he had behaved before - but the life he had led became charged with a new significance as he perceived that what he had previously done through natural curiosity and dislike of humbug was something essential to the salvation of the Athens which he loved.

     

      To understand the mission to which Socrates from now on devoted his life and in the fulfilment of which he was finally to die, we must consider the effect of the political and social upheavals of the previous hundred years upon the life of the individual Athenian.  The democratic revolution had shaken morality and religion to their very foundations.  Not only in Athens, but all over the Greek world, the destruction of aristocratic authority had brought with it a freedom of spirit new in the history of mankind, a distrust of authority not only in the political but in the religious sphere, and a reliance on human reason as the only proper instrument for the solution of every problem.

      To appreciate this intellectual revolution we have only to consider the effects of the industrial revolution upon the morality and religion of our own age.  Here, too, a new class of manufacturers and technicians pushed its way into political power: an old technique of production and distribution was replaced by a new one, and the class-structure of society was radically reshaped.  These political and social changes were accompanied by an intellectual revolution no less profound than they.  The established order of scientific and ethical philosophy and the established institutions of religion were not adapted to the needs of the new industrial society.  As liberalism challenged the political status quo, so Darwinism challenged the dogmas of the Churches.  In the triumph of liberalism, it was not only the statesmen and the manufacturer who were responsible for victory: the scientist and the philosopher also played their part.

      The developments in Greece were precisely parallel, save that here the revolutionary process was unprecedented in world history.  If we think for a moment of the great civilizations of Babylon, Egypt and Crete which preceded that of the Greeks, we shall see that religion and reason were there kept rigidly apart.  Reason or intelligence was regarded as useful in ordinary life - the craftsman, the sailor, and the general all applied it to the problems which faced them - but there was a whole sphere of life where the ordinary man was forbidden to use his intelligence at all.  He must not dispute how the world came to be, how the gods ruled the world, what was right and wrong, how sin could be expiated.  These questions were holy and they could be answered only by holy men.  Only the priest had access to the gods.  To the ordinary mortal it was forbidden.  He must be content to accept the answers which the priests gave him, and he must accept them, not because he saw that they were true, but because the authority of the priest was absolute.  The Greeks tore down this dividing wall between religion and intelligence.  They challenged the authority of the priest and set up reason or intelligence was the sole arbiter of what is acceptable and what is not.  In one sense nothing was holy to them because nothing was left unchallenged by reason; in another sense everything was holy because they believed everything was intelligible, finite, clear-cut and amenable to the law of Reason.  It is often said that the Greeks were irreligious people.  To say that is to make religion nothing better than superstition.  True religion cannot forbid the use of reason, or deny the possibility of truth.  It was a deeply religious feeling which inspired the Greek belief that we can understand the world around us, and break down the taboos which lurk in every mountain and tree and stream; it was a profound sense of morality which questioned the primitive religion of human sacrifice and denied the existence of jealous and licentious gods.  The early Greek philosophers were not free-thinkers or materialists, but pious and devout men who discovered that reason can free man from fear and hatred, and teach him the nature of reality.  Their speculations were at the same time an analysis of natural and religious phenomena: and thus they were both the first scientists and the first theologians.

      For this reason we find in the fragments of their writings which we possess a moral exaltation matched by few passages in the Hebrew prophets.  In the Old Testament we are still for the most part in a world of jealousy and fear.  God is still the possession of a people or tribe.  Ritual and ceremonial are confused with morality, and symbols take the place of intellectual concepts.  Sublime visions are dimly seen, but they remain visions, unclarified by reason or analysis.  To turn from the Hebrew prophets to the Greek thinkers of the sixth century is to move into another world, remote from our own, and yet far more akin to it.  For here are men, conscious of the reason which distinguishes them from beasts, and resolved to break through the curtains of symbol and ritual and ceremony, and to see the reality behind them face to face.  The enterprise is dangerous, but it must be attempted.  If man is to follow his divine calling and become rational, then first of all religion and morality must become rational too.

      How closely this attack on priestly authority was connected with the social revolution is shown by the fact that it began in Asia Minor and South Italy in the middle of the age of tyranny.  One after another thinkers arose to substitute for the myths and cosmogonies, which had previously been taken on trust, new scientific accounts of the way that the world came to be.  These early philosophies seem crude and laughable today: Thales, for instance, declared everything to be water.  But such a theory was in reality an amazing advance of human reason. Thales had observed that ice, which is solid, turns into water, water into steam; and he had further noticed how the steam or mist often seems to be drawn up by the sun.  He concluded that there were four prime substances, earth, air, fire, and water, which were transformed into one another in a regular cyclical process.  What is important is not the theory but the method.  He was trying to give an account of the world which squared with his observations, and he was searching for substances whose changes could be understood and shown to account for the observed changes in nature.  We have only to contrast Thales' philosophy with the first chapter of the book of Genesis or the Greek myths to appreciate his achievement.  From this date (about 580) no religion or theology or myth could satisfy the Greek thinker which had not been tested by reason and comparison.

      Fifty years later in South Italy the second discovery was made.  Pythagoras, half mystic and half scientist, the vegetarian believer in the transmigration of souls, founded the study of Pure Mathematics, and may actually have discovered the theorem which bears his name.  Imbued with a profound veneration for magic numbers and figures, he found that these holy entities had properties of their own which only pure thought could discern; a worshipper of the heavenly bodies, he maintained that they moved not in a mysterious but in a mathematical way; trained to find in musical incantations the way to religious ecstasy, he discovered that behind the audible melody there lay numerical ratios, not heard but understood.  In the course of the next half century his followers had laid the foundations of astronomy, geometry, and harmonics.  These sciences seemed to their earliest devotees in no way contradictory to religion, but the beginnings of a new theology which must finally disclose the nature of the supreme perfect Cause whom no eyes could see, the Eternal Being, rational and immutable, the Pure Intelligible Godhead.

      But although the early Greek philosophers were theologians 'intoxicated with reason', to whom it was self-evident that truth was the only priestess and reason the only oracle of true religion, the effect of their teaching on Greek society was revolutionary.  Freed from all the authority and restraint, Greek thought roamed at large over the universe, questioning and denying the accepted order of things.  The collapse of religious authority confirmed the political and social collapse of the aristocratic tradition.  The first results were therefore not a new intellectual discipline to replace the old traditions, but intellectual and social rebellion.  Man, it was felt, had at last been freed from bondage to superstition and from subjection to absolutism.  Since reason and intelligence were now the standards by which worth was measured, the aristocrat and the priest could be treated as ordinary men and judged on their merits.  In future no-one's opinion should carry extra weight because of his family tree or social position or holy office.

      Thus the cult of reason developed into an individualist and equalitarian philosophy, which threatened to break up the whole fabric of society.  Where each man is as good as his neighbour, political parties are inevitable; and the Greek city became a whirlpool of political intrigue.  Where there are political parties there must be propaganda; and rhetoric and oratory became essential to the citizen of a democracy who wanted to compete for social or economical or political success.  Where rhetoric is supreme, the decision of the law-courts will be swayed by brilliant argument and appeals to the emotions; and so in the law-courts it was persuasion, not truth, which prevailed.  A policy, a point of view, a moral principle or a religion came to be valued not for its truth, but for its popular appeal, just as the goodness of an article in modern life is sometimes assessed by its sales.  In the end the substitution of reason for tradition as the supreme criterion produced not freedom for the individual, as had been hoped, but power for the few individuals who were skilled in the arts of salesmanship.

      Another result of these changes was the vogue for science and philosophy amongst the leisured classes.  Knowledge and education became fashionable, and the demand for scientific lectures was satisfied by the Sophists, experts who travelled from town to town, living on their lecture fees.  They gave courses in medicine, astronomy, mathematics, civics, theology, and anything else for which there was a demand.  The demand was forthcoming; for education had become both a fashion and a necessity in the new commercial society.

      Of all the courses which they provided, the most popular and the most dangerous was rhetoric, the art of propaganda.  In democratic Athens, with its passion for litigation, rhetoric seemed essential to any happiness.  It brought political power, wealth, and personal success.  For rhetoric - like propaganda and advertising - was the art of making others agree to a point of view whether that point of view was right or wrong.  Indeed, the falser it was the greater the rhetorical success in persuading someone else to accept it: and conversely, the sounder a doctrine or a legal case or a political judgement, the more the skill required to make it look ridiculous.  Rhetoric, in fact, was the technique of making the worse appear the better and the better the worse cause.  Its connection with the Sophists is shown by our modern word sophistical, and it rapidly became the most highly developed science in all Greece.

 

      Such was the atmosphere in which Socrates grew up.  As a young man he plunged enthusiastically into the maelstrom of new ideas, reading and listening to the famous lecturers, even arguing with Zeno and Parmenides, the propounders of the latest paradoxes of western Greek philosophy.  But soon he began to feel lost in the buzz of speculation and dialectical cleverness.

      A whole-hearted rationalist, he accepted the revolt of reason and its refusal to be bound be prejudice and by tradition.  Greedy for the new science and philosophy, he participated eagerly in the Athenian renaissance and welcomed the new education which the Sophists offered.  Endowed with an overwhelming sense of the value of personality and of true self-realization, he could not deny that the challenge to the established order had left the individual free to develop his own talents and his own apprehension of truth and that the Sophists provided the means to this self-development.  But when he examined Athenian society, he began to see that the old superstitions had been replaced by a materialistic philosophy, and the old education by lessons in salesmanship and propaganda.  Just as democracy by 430 meant not freedom for all, but privilege and political power for one class, so rationalism was coming to mean, not the destruction of all prejudice, but the replacement of one type by another.  Education was not valued as an end in itself, but purchased as a useful weapon for the social struggle.

      Up till the moment when the Oracle was given, Socrates had been an amused and somewhat cynical spectator of the Athenian renaissance.  He had enjoyed picking holes in pretentious theories and exposing the illogicalities in the arguments of the philosophers, and he had not resisted the temptation to apply his destructive criticism to distinguished statesmen and poets.  But he had done this with a light heart.  Now he admitted to himself what he had long suspected.  Life in Athens might well be a glorious adventure, but it was high time to ask precisely where Athens stood, what the democratic revolution really meant, what the empire really was, and what freedom of thought really implied.  The last hundred years had been a period of such colossal changes that no one had had time to stop and consider their significance.  The social process had swept Athens along so fast that no Athenian had had time to see where Athens was going.  Each stage had seemed inevitable, and the pace had been so rapid that there had only been time to prepare for the next stage without asking too carefully about the direction of the final goal.  Now, in Socrates' view, it was time to call a halt and ask those quite simple questions to which everyone had a ready answer on his lips, but about which few had seriously pondered.

      This, then, was his vocation, and this was the meaning of Apollo's words.  Socrates, the man who claimed that he knew nothing, was the wisest man in Greece precisely because he alone realized that the fundamental questions were not being asked by the Sophists and the statesmen and the 'educated' Athenians.  They thought they knew the answers, when they did not.  He at least recognized his own ignorance.  Let us hear his own description of the matter:

      'When I heard the answer of the Oracle, I said to myself: "What on earth can the god mean by this riddle?  I am not conscious of having any wisdom either small or great.  What can he mean by calling me the wisest of men?  He cannot be telling a lie; for that would be against the law of his nature."  For a long time I pondered what he could mean, and then very reluctantly I decided to put the Oracle to the proof.  So I went to a man with a great reputation for wisdom, in the hope that I could thereby refute the Oracle and say to the god, "You said I was the wisest of men, but here is someone who is wiser than I."  The gentleman I approached was a politician - I need not mention his name - and I examined him very carefully.  But the result was that after conversation with him I realized that, although in his own estimation and in that of many others he was a wise man, in fact he was nothing of the kind.  So then I tried to show him that he thought himself wise but was not really wise, and the consequence was that I made an enemy of him and many of those present.  So I left him, saying to myself "I really am wiser than this gentleman.  I suppose neither of us knows anything beautiful and good: but whereas he thinks he knows something when he doesn't, I do at least realize my own ignorance.  In this single trifling way I suppose I am wise than he."  Then I went to someone else with a reputation even greater than his, but I came to the selfsame conclusion about him.  And so I made an enemy of him too and of many others besides." [See APOLOGY, Chapter 21.]

      In this passage Socrates indicated what he held to be the fundamental weakness of Athenian society.  The democratic revolution had swept away the old established order.  The authority of priest and noble had been replaced by the autonomy of individual reason.  But reason must not only destroy the temple of superstition: it must erect a new temple to replace it, more ordered, more beautiful and more true than the old.  To awaken Athens to this task was the bounden duty of any patriot.

      Socrates devoted the last twenty years of his life to the fulfilment of this duty - the exposure of ignorance in high places.  The ordinary Athenian saw in him only a typical Sophist, as he sat, day by day, surrounded by clever young men, demolishing the pretensions of highly respectable citizens.  But, unlike the Sophists, Socrates charged no fees.  Disclaiming all knowledge, he declared himself incompetent to teach, and claimed that he was merely trying to discover the truth.  If anyone should pay, it was he, for he was always the pupil, never the master.  This humility naturally infuriated anyone who had been subjected to the deadly Socratic analysis and had been forced to realize his state of mental confusion.  For it soon became clear that no reputation could survive a conversation with Socrates, the man who knew nothing.

      A few of his closest friends, among them Plato, had some inkling of the meaning of his life: but the conservative politician soon recognized him as a danger to Athenian democracy.  In 423 the playwright Aristophanes attacked him bitterly as a scientific buffoon, a dangerous radical who ridiculed sound tradition and made decent men look fools.  Aristophanes' criticism was politically justified: a degenerate aristocracy hung on Socrates' words and utilized his arguments to discredit the democracy which they wished to supplant.  Alcibiades and Critias and their friends were only waiting their chance to overthrow the regime and inaugurate the counter-revolution: Socrates' methods supplied them with fresh ammunition, which they used unscrupulously against their democratic opponents.  They learnt his dialectical methods and used them, not as Socrates used them to expose half-truths, but to annihilate truth.

      We must remember that the last thirty years of Socrates' life were lived in a period of almost unbroken war.  Athens was fighting for her existence, and it was clear that defeat would mean an aristocratic counter-revolution.  For this reason the party conflict became ferociously bitter, and any criticism of democracy was taken to imply support for the aristocratic opposition.  However scrupulously Socrates avoided taking sides, he could not pretend that democracy was perfect or veil his contempt for many of its spokesmen.  Nor could he deny his association with Alcibiades and Critias, or avoid responsibility for their chequered careers.  By his exposure of ignorance wherever he found it, he had weakened the Government and strengthened the opposition.

      In 404 Critias and his friends at last made their putsch, set up the regime of the thirty tyrants, and capitulated to Sparta.  Socrates took no part whatsoever in their conspiracy: and when an attempt was made to implicate him in its crimes, by instructing him to arrest a wealthy citizen, his refusal nearly cost him his life.  But the fact that Critias was his pupil could not be gainsaid.  When the democracy was restored he was arrested and put on trial ostensibly for worshipping strange gods and corrupting the youth, actually for aiding and abetting the counter-revolution.

      It is probable that the new democracy was reluctant to push the matter to a conclusion.  The legal case against Socrates was known to be weak; his honesty and integrity were widely recognized, and the temper of the day was inclined to toleration.  But Socrates was now seventy years old: the Athens he had loved was gone, never to be rebuilt.  Almost deliberately he seemed to press for a final decision, refusing absolutely to escape from prison or to accept the various offers of help which came from his many friends.  He felt that he had lived his life in the service of Athens.  It was for her sake that he had exposed the ignorance of her politicians and the corruption of her social life.  But his criticism had been either unheeded or reviled or perverted, and now he felt sure that only his death could effect what his life had failed to achieve.  If he were prepared to die at the order of the city which he had served, then perhaps his example would inspire others to continue the work which he had begun.

      And so he remained in prison awaiting death and talking happily to his friends.  Right to the end his loyalty never wavered.  When Crito urged him once more to escape, he only replied: 'Surely you must see that your country is something which you must honour and revere more even than your father or mother or forefathers.  In the eyes of God and of men of understanding it has a higher claim on you than all of these.  If it is angry with you, you must behave towards it with more deference and humility than you do even to your father; and you must either persuade it that you are right or else you must do as it commands and suffer as it commands without complaint.  If it orders you to be beaten or imprisoned, if it sends you to war to be wounded or killed - still you must obey.  For it has the right to demand this of you, and you must not flinch or draw back or desert your post.  On the field of battle, in the courts of law and in all your daily life, you must do whatever the city, which is your country, commands; or else you must succeed in convincing it that you are in the right.  To use force against your mother or your father is wicked.  How much more so against your country!' [CRITO, Chapter 12.]

      At his trial, too, he deliberately courted death.  Refusing to use the usual appeals ad misericordiam, he made his speech for the defence into a brilliant and humorous justification of his whole life.  It was patriotism, he urged, which made it impossible to retract what he had said, or to give an assurance for the future that he would soften his criticism.  Finally, when, according to Athenian practice, he was asked to assess his penalty, he replied that the only penalty which he deserved was a free meal daily in the town hall as a reward for his services.  He was condemned by a small majority to die by drinking hemlock.

      The last hours of his life were spent in conversation with his friends.  Plato has preserved for us an account of them in his dialogue the Phaedo, and had painted the final scene.

      'He took the cup quite serenely, without a tremor or any change of colour or expression, looking steadily at the warder with that peculiar stare of his.  Then he said, "What about pouring a libation?  May I?"  The warder answered, "We only prepare just the correct amount."  "I see," said he, "but I may and must pray to the gods that my journey from this world to the other may be blessed.  That, then, is my prayer.  So be it!"  As he said this he raised the cup and drank it off quite cheerfully and calmly.  Up till then must of us had been able to restrain our tears fairly well: but when we saw him drinking and when we saw that he had drunk the poison, we could do so no longer.  In spite of myself, my tears poured down, and I put my cloak over my face and wept.  It was not for him that I wept but for my own bereavement.  Crito had been unable to restrain his tears and had got up before me and gone aside.  Apollodorus too had been weeping all the time, and now he cried out loud and his passionate outburst made us all break down.  Only Socrates remained calm and said, "Come! Come! What are you doing!  The chief reason I sent the women away was to prevent this sort of scene; for I have been told that death should come to a man in a holy place.  Please be patient and calm."  At these words we felt ashamed and controlled our tears.  Then he began to walk about until he said that his legs were feeling heavy, and lay down on his back, as the warder instructed him.  The man who had given him the poison every now and then examined him, pressing his feet and his legs, and then he squeezed his foot hard and asked if Socrates felt anything.  Socrates said no.  So he squeezed his shins and, moving gradually up the body, showed us that he was growing cold and stiff.  Then he pressed hard again and said that when it reached his heart, he would be gone.

      'Socrates had covered his face with his cloak, but when the chill reached his groin, he pushed back the cloak from his face and said (these were his last words), "Crito, we owe a cock to Aesculapius: don't forget to pay the debt."  Crito said, "Very well, Socrates.  Is there anything else?"  Socrates gave no answer to this question, but after a little while he stirred.  The warder uncovered him and his eyes were glazed.  Crito saw this and closed the eyelids and the mouth.

      'So Socrates, our friend, died.  Of all the men of his time whom any of us met, not one was as fine or as wise or as good as he.'

 

 

II - THE TEACHINGS OF SOCRATES

 

Socrates was condemned to death for corrupting the youth and for worshipping strange gods.  From what we have seen of his life, this charge seems so fantastic that it could hardly have been seriously put forward.  And yet we shall find that the jury's verdict was politically justifiable.  Socrates, the patriotic Athenian and the devoted searcher after truth, was partially responsible for accelerating the Athenian collapse and still further disintegrating the social life of Athens.  His philosophy, because it was incomplete, was pernicious.

      Had this not been the case Plato might never have written his Republic.  For it was the fact that the noblest man whom he had known had been justifiably condemned to death which first forced him to realize the tragic dilemma of Greek civilization, and made him take upon himself  the completion of the task which Socrates had left unfinished.  To understand Plato we must try to see why Socrates was condemned to death.  In so doing we shall perhaps perceive something of the nature of his philosophy.

      We have seen that Socrates was deeply perturbed by the Athenian complacency at the destruction of the old aristocratic religion and morality.  He saw that intellectual freedom degenerates into mere licence unless the free individual voluntarily subjects himself to a new rational discipline.  The old aristocratic order had imposed a discipline and an education upon the citizen.  It had trained him for war and given him a rigid standard of right and wrong.  It had provided an education, though not a rational one.  Inevitably, therefore, the age of reason must develop a rational system of education, if it was to bring happiness and not misery to men.

      Socrates called the new education of which he dreamed philosophy - the search for wisdom.  Athens must be taught not to accept traditional morality, but to discover rational principles of conduct and to base its social life upon them.  The old education had consisted in putting into the minds of the young the orthodox ideas about right and wrong: the new philosophy would try to develop the individual reason in each man so that he only accepted those ideas which he saw to be true and rejected all wickedness, not from fear of punishment but because he understood its folly.

      Thus philosophy, according to Socrates, must be the self-discipline of reason, and it had two main tasks: (1) to examine and to reject those opinions which it found to be false, and (2) to substitute for these false opinions a new set of principles acceptable to reason.  The method of this new education was extremely simple: it consisted of asking for definitions of everyday words like 'justice' or 'courage' or 'piety' and, by a process of discussion, sifting the false from the true.  Socrates did not claim that in these discussions he taught anybody anything at all, but only that he helped others to discover what they really knew already.  He did not provide his hearers with new and interesting ideas, but like a midwife assisted the pregnant mind to bring forth its own truths.  In the early dialogues of Plato we can watch 'the midwife' at work.  He is usually in conversation with an expert or a prominent citizen and after a few minutes of desultory talk pounces on some word which his opponent has used.  What, he asks in conversation with a general, does courage mean precisely?  The general must clearly know in order to do his job properly.  But the general cannot precisely define it and is caught in a maze of inconsistencies.  Various definitions are tried, but even those suggested by Socrates are found to be deficient and the dialogue ends in a complete breakdown.  The only positive result seems to be that one more human being realizes that he does not know what he means by the very simplest words he uses and detests Socrates for having brought him to this realization.

      On first reading, these dialogues seem entirely destructive.  Frequently the argument is unsound and Socrates is guilty of what looks like deliberate unfairness.  The modern reader will sympathize with the jury who condemned him, and ask what possible use his verbal cleverness can be.  But if we study them more carefully we shall notice that - however negative the conclusions may be - these dialogues are in one sense positive.  This method of analysis - the attempt to define precisely the meanings of common words - is the great contribution of Socrates to modern philosophy: for if we do not know precisely the meaning of the words we use, we cannot discuss anything profitably.  Most of the futile arguments on which we all waste time are largely due to the fact that we each have our own vague meanings for the words we use and assume that our opponents are using them in the same sense.  If we defined our terms to start with, we could have far more profitable discussions.  Again, we have only to read the daily papers to observe that propaganda (the modern counterpart of rhetoric) depends largely for its success on confusing the meaning of the terms.  If politicians were compelled by law to define any term they wished to use, they would lose most of their popular appeal, their speeches would be shorter, and many of their disagreements would be found to be purely verbal.  Thus Socrates believed that the first task of philosophy was to clear away confusion and misrepresentation by defining the meaning of words.

      But that was only a preliminary.  The true task of philosophy was not to define words but to discover reality.  As we have seen, Socrates had studied the attempts of the scientists and the mathematicians to find in the workings of nature a rational plan.  Mathematicians had disclosed the possibility of deductive proof and logical certainty.  No-one who had understood Pythagoras' theorem could doubt it or regard it as merely probable: for the mathematician it was eternally and absolutely true.  Socrates observed that mathematics depended on precise definition of terms, but he also noticed that it did not consist solely of definitions: it was an ordered and consistent body of knowledge.  It seemed to him possible to apply to human relations the mathematical method, and he believed this to be the task of philosophy.  If we could know justice and truth and beauty, understanding their properties and interrelations as we understand Euclid, then life would be rational and happy.  What the scientists and mathematicians were doing for the world of nature, philosophy must accomplish for human society.

      The philosophical discipline is never popular: it is indeed the most exasperating torture to which the human mind can be subjected.  It hunts out our dearest prejudices and shows that they have no rational foundations, and it exposes what we thought to be a logical theory as a mass of contradictions.  Although it is directed to the development of the individual, it does not satisfy our ordinary ideas of self-realization since it calls on each of us to relegate most of his personal interests to second place.  It does not press for the free development of individual tastes, but demands that the individual should voluntarily regulate his life by the dictates of reason.

      Socrates believed that this discipline alone could save Athenian democracy from collapse.  Now that the bonds of tradition had been broken, the individual citizen must forge for himself the new morality.  And education must be concerned to produce that change of heart which was necessary if he was to be willing to undertake these great responsibilities.  For this reason Socrates was as much opposed to the type of culture and education which the Sophists were popularizing, as he was to the point of view of the ordinary uneducated businessman.  He saw that education and intellectual training can be used for purely materialist ends.  Men can be naturally clever and highly educated, and yet totally unphilosophic.  They can allow reason to be the slave of their passions, or of other people's passions: and education can be merely a useful weapon of self-assertion.  Socrates believed that the teaching provided by the Sophists was little better than this.  It gave to men techniques for getting what they wanted, and the Sophists were interested not in the spiritual health of their pupils but in providing something useful for which people were prepared to pay.  Socrates agreed with the conservatives that such education was no substitute for the old-fashioned discipline of aristocratic Athens.  It put new power into the hands of the intellectual, but it gave him no principles for the use of that power.  For this reason it produced a reckless individualism and disregard for the good of the community.  Once the restraints of morality and religion had been destroyed, the individual citizen was free to do as he pleased; and education was merely embittering the social conflict instead of healing it.

      This, in Socrates' view, was the disease from which Athenian democracy was suffering.  Class-conflict and imperialism were the results of a laissez-faire philosophy of individual licence; and if Reason could not produce a new self-discipline, then the belief that might is right would rule in Athens.  As the great war dragged on, it became yearly more clear that this was happening.  For all its faults, Athens in the age of Pericles had been inspired by an exalted patriotism and a real sense of pan-Hellenic responsibility.  Now these motives were being submerged by faction and self-interest.  No impartial observer could deny the terrible decline in the standards of Athenian life which set in after the death of Pericles.

      The most sober and therefore the most ruthless critic of this degeneration was Thucydides, an Athenian general exiled for his failure on a campaign, who composed a detailed history of the great war between Athens and Sparta.  One quotation is sufficient to indicate the analysis which he made.  It is taken from 'the Melian dialogue' in which Thucydides describes how Athens subdued a small island called Melos. [For a complete version see THUCYDIDES V, 85.]

      'Athens also made an expedition against Melos.  The Melians are of Spartan descent and were therefore unwilling to become subject to Athens.  At first they remained neutral.  Then when Athens committed acts of wanton aggression, they were forced into open warfare.  Athens sent an expeditionary force but before opening hostilities the Athenian generals entered into negotiations with the Melians.  The following conversations ensued:

 

ATHENS: We do not intend to waste time making flowery speeches to justify our Empire on the ground of our services to Greece against Persia, or to pretend that our present invasion is motivated by any past misdemeanours of yours.  We suggest therefore that you, too, should omit such arguments.  Do not waste time describing how, although you are of Spartan descent, you have not joined the Spartan alliance against us, or how our aggression is unprovoked.  Let us negotiate on the basis of our real feelings and of the situation as it really is.  We all know that justice in this world is only possible between two powers of equal strength.  Power extorts all it can: weakness concedes all it must.  We are here to strengthen our Empire.  We wish to include you within it with a minimum of trouble, in order that your existence in future may be of profit to us both.

MELOS: You will certainly benefit from conquering us.  How should we benefit by accepting subjection to you?

ATHENS: You would have the advantage of submitting before the worst occurred: we should gain by not destroying one of our subjects.

MELOS: You refuse then to allow us to remain neutral and on friendly terms with you?

ATHENS: Yes, in the eyes of our subjects your neutrality is a sign of our weakness: your hostility will occasion a display of our strength.  Our subjects believe that if any state maintains its independence the reason is to be found in its strength which makes us hesitate to attack it.  Your subjection, therefore, would at the same time extend our Empire and increase our security.

MELOS: But surely your security would be best advanced if we remain neutral; for if you attack us, you will alienate the sympathies of all the states which are now neutral.  When they see how you are treating us, they will expect their turn to come soon.  In fact, you will be strengthening the forces against you and driving anyone who has not yet taken sides into the enemy camp.  Furthermore, if you are willing to take the risks which you admit are necessary to maintain your Empire, you must agree that we should show a contemptible lack of spirit if we do not do everything we can to preserve the independence we still possess.

ATHENS: Not if you take an objective view of the matter.  You have to decide not whether you should engage in a war between two sides equally matched, but how you can preserve yourselves against an enemy of vastly superior strength.  The question is not one of honour but of prudence.

MELOS: But we know that victory does not always go to the big battalions.  If we surrender now we give up all hope; if we fight, there is at least a chance we may survive.

ATHENS: Hope is indeed very comforting in moments of danger, and those who have something else to depend on may not be ruined by accepting her comforts.  But do not be deluded by hopes.  Though your position is desperate, a rational method of self-preservation is still open to you.  Do not make the silly mistake of pinning your hopes in such a situation upon the supernatural and upon the favours of heaven.

MELOS: We recognize the danger we are in.  But our cause is just and yours is not, and in the eyes of God we shall at least find no less favour than you.  As for our weakness, it will be compensated by the support of the Spartans.  They are of common stock with us and cannot refuse us help.  Our confidence, therefore, is not so blind as you suppose.

ATHENS: We expect to receive as much favour from on high as you.  Our attitude in religious matters is scrupulously correct: our mundane aims are not abnormal.  There is a law of nature which declares that every living creature extends its empire to the limits of its power.  We know this is true of the human species: we believe that it applies in heaven as well.  We did not make this law, nor were we the first to implement it.  We inherited it from our fathers, we act upon it in our own lives, and we expect to bequeath it to posterity for ever.  We are also aware that you, like everyone else, would do as we are doing had you at your disposal the forces which are at ours.  So much for the favour of heaven.  As for Sparta, if you imagine that she will assist you from a sense of honour, we can but admire your innocence; we do not envy your folly.  Sparta is a country of high moral standards in home affairs: its loyalty to national institutions is very great.  Of its foreign policy we could say a good deal.  Suffice it now to state that it is second to none in identifying national interests with international honour, national expediency with international justice.

     

      'The Athenians left the conference: the Melians after consultation resolved to persevere in their refusal to surrender.  The Athenian delegation then returned to the army and the generals immediately commenced hostilities.  Later on, Melos was closely besieged and whispers of treachery began to be heard in the city.  She therefore made an unconditional surrender to Athens.  The Athenians executed all the men and enslaved all the women and children.  They repopulated the island with five hundred colonists.'

      Thucydides did not pretend that this was a verbatim account of the negotiations at Melos, or that Athenian statesmen ever talked in this way.  It is doubtful indeed if any of them had analysed their own motives or thought out the principles of their foreign policy so carefully as the cool objective spectator.  The Melian dialogue is not literal history, but an attempt to lay bare the real underlying causes of Athenian imperialism and to show what an Athenian diplomatist would have had to say if he had been honest enough to think out the implications of his country's policy.  It is certain that Socrates would regard the Melian dialogue as a fair analysis.

      Thucydides was an historian: he stated the facts and analysed them without drawing conclusions.  But there were men at Athens prepared to draw them, and to assert not only that Athenian foreign policy was ruthlessly imperialistic but that it was right to be so.  This school of Realpolitik was never a popular movement (it was too philosophical for that), but it deeply influenced the young intellectuals and its slogans were quickly picked up by the demagogues and popular lecturers.  It maintained (as its modern counterparts maintain) that all politics are and must be power-politics: state against state, class against class, man against man.  The survival of the fittest is the only law of human society, and self-interest the only motive of individual men.  Not only international law and morality, but social morality as well, are tricks and devices for the enslavement of one group by another.  The position is admirably summarized by Callicles, a character whom Plato introduces in his dialogue the Gorgias to represent the philosophy of the younger generation.

      'I believe that the laws are framed by the weak and common crowd.  They frame them for their own benefit and according to their taste they concoct the code of moral praise and censure.  They use them to terrify the few dominant spirits who could stake out a decent claim for themselves: to prevent them from doing well or getting the better of their inferiors.  They are content was a fair or just distribution of wealth precisely because they are inferior.  And so, Law tells us, it is unfair and disgraceful to try to do better than the common herd, and they tell us it is morally wrong to do so.  But the real truth is that the better man ought to do better than the worse, and the more capable than the less capable.  There is plenty of evidence to support this.  Look at the behaviour of animals, look at the history of cities and of nations.  Here you see Right means that the strong should rule the weak and do better than the weak.  What right had Xerxes to attack Greece?  I believe Xerxes and his like were doing what is really and truly right; they were acting by the real law of nature, though they may well have been transgressing the laws we frame.  We take the finest of our children and we tame them like lion cubs, curbing their spirits with moral spells and superstitions.  And so we enslave them, telling them they must only take their fair and proper share and that fairness and justice are right is fine and right.  But if a man should arise with a spirit great enough for the task, he would shake off this morality: he would burst the chains of convention and make himself free: he would trample underfoot our codes and hypocrisies and superstitions and all our unreal laws.  The slave would rise up and show himself to be our master and true righteousness would shine forth.'

      This type of argument was as common in fifth-century Athens as it is today, and then, too, it seemed overwhelmingly persuasive to a generation which had grown impatient of the catchwords and speeches of democracy.  Socrates must have heard it almost daily, and recognized in its triumphant despair of human nature a genuinely revolutionary tone.  The young men who revelled in their immorality and denounced human kindness as a fraud were largely justified in their contempt for current morality.  Socrates agreed with them that imperialism and class-way were the two main elements in the politics of their day.  He agreed that most people in their private lives were moral and decent and righteous only because and so long as it paid them to be so: they kept their promises, paid their debts and fulfilled the laws from a mixture of fear and habit and common sense.  And finally he agreed that at bottom the respectable citizen was often actuated by the same motive as Callicles - self-interest: the one accepted and the other renounced the social code, but the motive of self-interest was the same in both cases.  But though he agreed with the Realpolitiker thus far, he parted company with them when they went on to affirm not only that men did, but that they should behave in this way.  For here he saw the difference between philosophical and sophistical education.  For the former was concerned to find a new self-discipline based on rational moral principles: the latter regarded all morality as a brake on individual freedom.  To Socrates the philosophy that might is right was the inevitable result of neglecting true philosophy and allowing education to fall into the hands of irresponsible Sophists.  Class conflict and imperialism had dominated Athenian life because genuine philosophy had never been taught: and now a spurious philosophy had arisen designed to preserve precisely those evils which philosophy should suppress.  Realpolitik was, in fact, the philosophy of Unreason, the justification of those false educational ideals which regarded knowledge and reason as merely useful instruments for the furtherance of personal of class-interests.

      Socrates opposed this new philosophy of Unreason as firmly as he opposed the Sophists, and many of his fiercest arguments were directed against it.  But the tide was against him.  In a period of open class-war it seemed a hopeless task to educate Athens to moral and intellectual self-discipline: it was self-evident that in order to survive man must be prepared to fight for himself and disregard the obligations which reason and common decency alike imposed.  The philosophy of Unreason at least offered a positive solution of the problems of life.  It was concrete, specific, and 'true to life'.  In opposition to it Socrates could offer nothing clear-cut or definite; his whole philosophy forbade him to teach a dogma.  He could only try to put others on their way upon the search for truth.  He could show that in the long run 'Might is Right' is self-destructive, and that the philosophy of Unreason is the denial of all philosophy: but this was of little use to a generation filled with scepticism and despair.

      For this reason Socrates' philosophy could make no headway against Realpolitik.  Its simple patriotism and sense of duty sounded archaic and naive, and its refusal to offer a ready-made solution of any problem made it seem nebulous and unworldly.  But to the outsider Socrates and his opponents were much of a madness.  For up to a point both philosophies had a common aim, the exposure of hypocrisy: and where they differed - in the positive side of their teachings - Socrates' views were obscure and vague.  Thus the two conflicting educational ideals were lumped together by the ordinary Athenian as the clever revolutionary propaganda of aristocratic intellectuals whose purpose was the corruption of the youth and the destruction of all respect for the democratic tradition.  This judgement may have been strictly incorrect, but it showed a certain political common sense.  For, in fact, the products of Socrates' teaching were not distinguishable from those of the Sophists.  Alcibiades was an unprincipled careerist, Critias a sadistic and ruthless politician.  Looking at them the man in the street could not be blamed for assuming that Socratic philosophy was only another brand of subversive sophistry.

      To appreciate, therefore, the tragedy of Socrates' execution, we must realize that it was politically justifiable.  The statesman must consider the results of a policy or a creed, and not merely the motives behind it.  Looked at from this point of view, Socrates' guilt was proved up to the hilt.  His teaching had inspired the counter-revolution, and his theology had produced, not a puritan revival, but a ruthless and cynical gang of wealthy adventurers.  The fact that he had denounced their philosophy of force did not make any material difference.  His disciples had welcomed his attacks on current morality, and disregarded the positive side of his creed.

      The responsibilities of the teacher are great.  He must consider not only whether his teachings are true, but what effect they will have on his pupils.  In the eyes of the practical politician it is no justification of Socrates as a teacher to show that he denounced wickedness, if his virtuous teachings, in fact, promoted it.  However blameless his life and pure his motives, the effects on Athenian life had been disastrous.  When we remember this, we cannot blame the jury which found him guilty of corrupting the youth.

 

      We have seen how Socrates failed to impart to his pupils the rational self-discipline which he himself practised, and we have suggested that this failure was due to his inability to give any positive content to his notion of Reason which was acceptable to an Athenian audience.  And yet Socrates had a positive gospel: and it was this gospel which was attacked in the second part of his charge which accused him of worshipping strange gods.

      Here, too, we are faced with a paradox.  Socrates was a respectable Athenian.  There is no reason to believe that he was ever blasphemous or disrespectful to Athena of the Acropolis.  How, then, could he be condemned upon this charge?  From all that we hear of him, there is no doubt that he was a deeply religious man.  He often talked of his 'inner voice' which would suddenly forbid him to do something which he had in mind, and he believed that on those occasions God had spoken.  He was something of a mystic and would sometimes fall into trances.  Once when he was serving in the army in Northern Greece, he was observed in the early morning standing quite still meditating.  There he stood all day deep in thought.  As night fell some of his fellow soldiers dragged their beds out into the open to watch him.  All night he stood there quite still, and with the return of light he offered up a prayer to the sun and went on his way.

      The inner voice and the trances were the most obvious signs of a religious sense which permeated Socrates' whole life.  Religion for most Greeks at this time was a matter of observance and ceremony.  Piety and godliness meant doing a number of things at the proper time; for the gods were 'powers' to be appeased by offerings.  The respectable citizen made his offerings, but religion did not demand that he should behave in any special way in his ordinary life, or offer him any very cheerful prospect in the next world.  Greek gods were capricious and somewhat mercenary - a bad man, who made the proper offerings, was pleasing to heaven: a good man, who by some mischance failed to make them, was punished.

      Socrates' religion was very different.  All his life he had a mystical awareness of the supernatural world, and felt himself a citizen of the heavenly city.  This otherworldly belief was held by certain sects called Orphics, which had grown up during the fifty years before he was born.  For the Orphic, human life was a vale of woe to which man had been banished by God, and the body was a tomb in which the immortal soul had been imprisoned.  To gain true happiness it must be freed from the trammels of the flesh, and return to its natural dwelling-place in heaven.  But this release could only be achieved if it renounced wealth and power and bodily pleasure and resolved to live the good life here on earth.

      All men alike, said the Orphic, are banished souls, so all are brothers.  Cities and empires and earthly glory are nothing but vanity.  We must renounce them and renounce our citizenship of this world.   For the community of the elect is not bound by ties of kinship or of nationality, but by the brotherhood of its common purpose - its resolution to escape the world and seek God.  This for the Orphic, religion was no mere formal observance or empty ritual, but the very life of man.  And his morality in the same way ceased to be the customs of the city he lived in, and became the way of life which the individual soul must follow if it is to be freed from the prison of the body and return to heaven.

      Orphism often degenerated into a mystery cult hawked around by quacks and mendicants as a cheap ticket to heaven.  But Socrates met the very exalted form of it which had been developed by the Pythagoreans.  As it permeated their mathematics and made of them not merely a new science or technique, but a new theology, so it permeated his new dialectical analysis of the meanings of words and gave it a strange passion and intensity.

      'Perhaps, then, there is a "narrow way" which leads us to our goal.  For as long as we have the body with us in our search, so that the soul is contaminated by its evilness, we shall never get complete possession of that truth which we desire.  The body must be fed and so it constantly disturbs us.  It is liable to disease and so it hinders our search for reality.  It fills us with passions and appetites and fears and all sorts of fantasies and foolishness so that it really never gives us a chance of knowing anything properly.  War and dissension and battle are all due to the body and its appetites, since every war is fought in order to acquire wealth, and it is the body which forces us to acquire it.  And so we are enslaved to its service, and are so busy that we have no time for philosophy.  But, worst of all, if the body does ever give us a little spare time and we begin to make some investigation, it constantly butts in, in the middle of our research, and disturbs and upsets us, and prevents us from seeing the truth.  It is, in fact, obvious that if we are to gain any pure knowledge, we must get rid of the body so that the soul by itself can look on reality by itself.  Only then shall we attain that knowledge which must be the object of our desire, since we claim to be "lovers of knowledge".  Our argument proves indeed that we shall never know in this life, but only when we are dead....

      'The true philosophers really practise dying and they are less afraid of death than anyone.  Look at it in this way.  They are at loggerheads with the body and they want to free the soul of all encumbrances.  Wouldn't it be very unreasonable then if they were afraid and upset when this happened, and were sorry to go to the place where there is a hope of gaining what they longed for all through their lives, and of ridding themselves of the companion with whom they were always at loggerheads?  Many have been glad to die when the boy or wife or son whom they loved has been taken from them, simply because they hoped in the other world to see those whom they longed for and to be with them again.  And so, I suppose, if a man is in love with knowledge and passionately believes that he cannot really find it except in the other world, he cannot be upset at dying, but will gladly leave this world.  Surely this must be so if he is really a philosopher?  For he will be passionately convinced that he can only really find pure knowledge there.  If this is so it would be very unreasonable for him to be afraid of death, wouldn't it?'

      In this passage from the Phaedo [PHAEDO, Chapters 11 and 12.] we find a clear statement of Orphic religious faith.  It can be summarized as follows: (1) The Soul is immortal. (2) Happiness means the achieving of immortality by renunciation of this world. (3) All men are brothers whatever their conditions here on earth.  But to these three beliefs Socrates, under Pythagorean influence, adds a fourth - virtue is knowledge - transforming Orphism from a mystery cult into a rational philosophy.  For now the immortal part of the soul is Reason, and happiness means freedom for Reason to contemplate reality.  At one stroke the new scientific spirit becomes the instrument of true religion, and philosophical inquiry the proper method of theology, which alone can satisfy man's rational nature and impose upon his passions order and restraint.

      At first sight it is not clear why Socrates' religion should have brought him into conflict with Athenian public opinion.  Athens, too, had her own Eleusinian mysteries - a cult of Demeter and Persephone - which offered some hope of immortality, though it is doubtful whether the ordinary citizen regarded it as more than a kind of Freemasonry, a ceremonial observance which satisfied a deep unconscious craving.  Why, then, was Socrates condemned to death for worshipping strange gods?

      There are several answers to this question.  In the first place Pythagoreanism was an aristocratic creed, which challenged the sovereignty of the popular will and the authority of the elected citizen.  In South Italy, indeed, a sort of dictatorship oft he elect had been set up by Pythagoreans, like Calvin's City of God at Geneva.  If knowledge must be supreme and reason control the passions, it was easy to see that the freedom which the merchants and town proletariat had won by a century of struggle would have to be surrendered to a stricter absolutism of theological kings.  Athens rightly felt that the new puritanism was essentially undemocratic and that the Pythagorean, who was harmless enough when he confined his speculations to mathematics and the other world, would become a menace to the existing order if he applied his analysis to society.  But this was precisely the task to which Socrates felt himself called - to use the new mathematical method of reasoning in testing the consistency and the correctness of the current morality and statesmanship.  In so doing he must challenge the basic principles of Athenian democracy.

      Secondly the Athenian was bound to ridicule the Socratic ideal of practising immortality.  In a city where the pleasures of this world were so keenly appreciated, it seemed absurd to suggest that Puritanism could bring happiness.  Socrates spoke constantly of the need to sacrifice all for psyche, the immortal rational part of the soul.  But to the Athenian the psyche meant the breath of life; and if he conceived it to be immortal, it was only as a thin shade in Hades craving to return to the body.  For him it was the things of the body and of this world which brought pleasure and made life worth living, and he felt repelled by a doctrine which taught that man must lose his life in order to save it.

      Thirdly, the Socratic theology contradicted what little religion he still had.  Athena of the Acropolis and the rest oft he Olympic throng were for the new theologians myths or allegories and nothing more.  The sun and moon and stars were physical objects and studied as such by science.  Homer, who was almost a Greek bible, was mercilessly criticized and the sexual foibles of his deities were denounced.  It was unreasonable to expect that the respectable citizen should distinguish between a theologian who thus trampled on tradition and a vulgar atheist.  Socrates for him was not only a Sophist and a crank - he was blasphemous as well.

      But all this is not sufficient to explain why Socrates was brought to trial for his religious beliefs.  Athens was not a modern dictatorship and her citizens could think what private thoughts they pleased.  It cannot have been Socrates' theology alone to which objection was taken, but its political effects.

      What these were it is easy to see.  Socrates taught that the religion which was ordinarily practised was merely a myth, a symbol sometimes of truth, sometimes of falsehood.  He believed that religion no less than morality must be purged by reason and that, before any real knowledge of God could be reached, the lumber of superstition and ceremony must be seen for what it was.  In his own mind this exposure of superstition was only a preliminary before the real search for reality began.  But for his pupils the preliminary stage was quite sufficient.  They were delighted with his ridicule of Homer and all the sacred books of Greek morality.  Rebels against tradition and orthodoxy, they wanted nothing better than a proof that religion was nonsense.  Socrates gave it to them.  Thus the effect of Socrates' teaching was not the restoration of true religion, but the destruction of any little religious feeling which Alcibiades and his friends still possessed; and the new theology had the same result in Athens as the new philosophy - it destroyed belief but was unable to put anything in its place.  The young aristocrats may have picked up a smattering of Pythagorean teaching from their master, but they were only interested in its antidemocratic bias.

      Socrates was the lover of truth who could only make men sceptics, the lover of God who converted his pupils to atheism, the patriot whose hearers became convinced that patriotism was a mere delusion.  Preaching the rule of reason, he taught a technique of argument which was used to justify the rule of might.  Concerned above all to challenge the selfish individualism of the Athenian intelligentsia, he produced by his teaching the worst specimens of that type.

      Perhaps we can now understand why he refused to escape from prison and preferred to court death.  He knew that he had failed in his life to fulfil the mission which the Oracle had given him.  He knew, on the other hand, that his teaching was sound and that along the way which he had marked lay the only hope of salvation for the individual and for the State.  For his philosophy was not wrong, but incomplete.  He preached the rationality of man and of God, and he urged that unless we believe in these two things there can be no sound education or happy society.  His life had shown that this belief is insufficient and that without knowledge of the principles of human conduct, and of the nature of God, it can become positively harmful.  But he believed that his death would inspire others to discover those things, the existence of which he could only take on trust.

      We have said that it is the personality of Socrates, not his actions or teaching, which is really important.  That he was justifiably condemned to death is true; but it is irrelevant to his greatness.  That he made no important discoveries is also true and also irrelevant.  What mattered to Plato and what matters to us is his life and death.  In them he showed that a man could be found who believed so passionately in the cause of truth that he would follow it whatever its political or social effects.  Such people there must always be if civilization is to be preserved.  They are so uncompromising that they are quite unpractical: so simple that they make wise men look fools.  Oblivious of the disastrous results of their idealism, they demand truth even where it may ruin a class or a nation: and if their wickedness is pointed out to them, they merely reply, 'where truth is concerned, compromise is impossible'.  All that is free in our Western culture has sprung from this spirit, whether it is found in scientists, or priests, or politicians, or quite ordinary men and women who have refused to prefer politic falsehoods to the simple truth.  In the short term, they often do great harm: but in the end their example is the only force which can break the dictatorship of force and greed.  Socrates was the first of these men and women of whose personality history has preserved a record.

      For he was the first man who really saw what intellectual integrity implied and yet preferred it to everything else.  He was the spirit of inquiry, incorruptible, intolerant of sham, greedy for every variety of human experience, insatiable in discussion, ironic and yet serious.  Such a spirit is generally intolerable to any well-organized community.  The statesman who is responsible for 'carrying-on', the priest who preaches the orthodox faith, the professor who repeats the traditional dogmas, will all unite to suppress the free spirit of reason which respects no authority save that of truth.  In the face of completely candid criticism every established authority must resort to the most irrational of defences - force.  There is no other weapon against the conscientious objector: and Socrates showed that philosophy is nothing else than conscientious objection to prejudice and unreason.  Perhaps in the last resort it cannot solve the problems of human right and wrong, and it will have no simple answer to the questions of the hour.  Regarding force as irrational, it will refuse to use it and ceaselessly demand that those who are prepared to do so should ask themselves precisely what their purpose and their motives are.  The Athenian democracy had no answer to this question, and so Socrates died.

      Socrates will always be compelled to die, his death will always be politically justifiable, and it will always be condemned by succeeding generations, who see so easily in retrospect that truth is ultimately preferable to any established falsehood, however efficient it may appear.  Condemning the death of the historical Socrates, each generation kills its own.