THE TRIUMPH OF BEING
1. I said at the beginning of this cyclical
project that the principal concern of philosophers was - or should be - being,
and so it is to being that I shall now return at its ending, bearing in mind
that being is characteristic of the essence, or soul, of things, as, most
especially, of the self.
2. I have shown, contrary to the doubts and
moral ignorance of those all-too-modern philosophers who are apt to dismiss
being or the possibility of knowledge thereof, exactly what being is,
and I maintain that there is a hierarchy of being which stretches from the
least essential being of love (in metachemistry) to
the most essential being of joy (in metaphysics) via the less (relative to
least) essential being of pride (in chemistry) and the more (relative to most) essential
being of pleasure (in physics).
3. Thus, because fire is the least essential
(properly apparent) element and air the most essential, fiery being, otherwise
known as love, is the least essential and airy being, otherwise known as joy,
the most essential, while with the less (relative to least) essential (properly
quantitative) element of water and the more (relative to most) essential
(properly qualitative) element of vegetation in between, watery being and
vegetative being, otherwise known as pride and pleasure, are correspondingly
less essential and more essential respectively.
4. Such can also be said of the negative, or
primary, counterparts to the above positive, or supreme, manifestations of
being, viz. hatred, humility, pain, and woe, in sensuality no less than in
sensibility.
5. However, since it has been my design to dwell
on the positive manifestations of being, not their negative counterparts, I
have focused most of my philosophic attention upon love, pride, pleasure, and
joy, the respective idealisms, in religion, of fundamentalism, nonconformism, humanism, and transcendentalism.
6. For being is
religious, and, being religious, it is ever idealistic, even if there are
different kinds of idealism corresponding to the nature and/or unnature of the particular element with which it is
associated.
7. Thus the idealism of love differs
demonstrably - one might say absolutely - from the idealism of joy, as Hell
from Heaven, unnatural/unhuman (inhuman) fundamentalism from subnatural/subhuman
transcendentalism, and these in turn differ from the purgatorial idealism of
pride and the earthly idealism of pleasure, both of which constitute a worldly
antithesis, as germane to the nonconformism of the
supernatural/superhuman on the one hand, and to the humanism of the
natural/human on the other hand.
8. However, while being is to be found in
every elemental context, from metachemistry and
chemistry on the objective, or female, side of life ... to physics and
metaphysics on its subjective, or male, side, it is only chiefly characteristic
of metaphysics, wherein the noumenal element of air
has its essential throne.
9. But if being
is chiefly characteristic of metaphysics, it is not chiefly characteristic of
physics, wherein the phenomenal element of vegetation has its qualitative
throne. Neither is it chiefly
characteristic of chemistry, wherein the phenomenal element of water has its
quantitative throne, nor of metachemistry, wherein
the noumenal element of fire has its apparent throne.
10. On the contrary, if the being of soul most
characterizes metaphysics, then that which most characterizes physics, by
contrast, is the taking of ego, while chemistry and metachemistry
would have to be chiefly characterized by the giving of spirit and the doing of
will, as by glory and power as opposed, on the subjective side of the gender
divide, to form and, in the case of metaphysics, contentment.
11. Thus metaphysics, corresponding in ideological
terms to transcendentalism, is the one element in which being (joy) can truly
triumph, the one element in which, especially in the religious context of
idealism, being is an end-in-itself rather than just an aside to some other -
and false - end or (especially on the objective side of life) means, as the
case may be.
12. In physics, by
contrast, being (pleasure) has to take second place to taking, as to the ego;
in chemistry being (pride) has to take third place to giving, as to the spirit;
and in metachemistry being (love) has to take fourth
place to doing, as to the will.
13. Thus it would be illogical, to the point of
absurdity, to speak of being triumphing, or of the triumph of being,
in any other element than metaphysics, the concern par
excellence of philosophy, and hence of philosophers.
14. For physics, the concern par
excellence of fiction, as of novelists, exemplifies the triumph of taking
(in the ego), while chemistry, the concern par excellence of drama, as
of playwrights, exemplifies the triumph of giving (in the spirit), and metachemistry, the concern par excellence of poetry,
as of poets, exemplifies, in unequivocal terms, the triumph of doing (in the
will).
15. Therefore it would be as illogical for a poet
to speak of the triumph of being (in the soul) as for a philosopher - and there
have, alas! been some highly prominent ones in recent
times - to speak of the triumph of doing (in the will). The soul (love) of metachemistry
can only be subordinate to the will (in noumenal
objectivity), just as the will (in noumenal
subjectivity) of metaphysics can only be subordinate to the soul (joy).
16. And what applies to the noumenal
elements applies in rather more phenomenal vein to the intermediate elements,
as it were, of chemistry and physics, wherein the spirit will be dominant in
the one and the ego dominant in the other, whether in relation to will or soul
or, indeed, to ego (chemistry) and spirit (physics).
17. Rather than risk getting drawn back into a
discussion of will, spirit, or ego, I should like to stay with the soul, and
hence the context of being which, as we have seen, is never more
idealistic, or religious, than in metaphysics.
18. But metaphysics can
be either of time or space, of sequential time in sensuality (outer) or of
spaced space in sensibility (inner), and therefore metaphysical being has the
capacity to ascend, through time-space evolution, from sensuality to
sensibility, wherein it is saved.
19. Likewise metachemistry
can be either of space or time, of spatial space in sensuality (outer) and of
repetitive time in sensibility (inner), and therefore metachemical
being has a fatality to descend, through space-time devolution, from sensuality
to sensibility, wherein it is damned.
20. Contrariwise, physics can be either of mass or
volume, of massive mass in sensuality (outer) or of voluminous volume in
sensibility (inner), and therefore physical being has the capacity to ascend,
through mass-volume evolution, from sensuality to sensibility, wherein it is
saved.
21. Similarly chemistry can be either of volume or
mass, of volumetric volume in sensuality (outer) or of massed mass in
sensibility (inner), and therefore chemical being has a fatality to descend,
through volume-mass devolution, from sensuality to sensibility, wherein it is
damned.
22. Whether being be of the sort which is
sensual or sensible, outer or inner, 'once born' or 're-born',
it descends in metachemistry through space-time
devolution and in chemistry through volume-mass devolution, whereas in physics
it ascends through mass-volume evolution and in metaphysics through time-space
evolution.
23. Thus far from being exclusively of time or
space, noumenal being can be of time and space on
both space-time and time-space axes - the former objective and the latter
subjective, whether in sensuality or in sensibility.
24. And far from being exclusively of volume or
mass, phenomenal being can be of volume and mass on
both volume-mass and mass-volume axes - the former objective and the latter
subjective, whether in sensuality or in sensibility.
25. Now just as being is never shallower,
or less deep, than in the spatial space of space-time devolution, so it is
never deeper, or more profound, than in the spaced space of time-space
evolution, since space is the plane in which being is sensually metachemical on the one hand, and sensibly metaphysical on
the other hand.
26. In fact, just as being can only be
second-rate on a plane or axis in which taking (the ego) is cardinal, and
third-rate on a plane or axis in which giving (the spirit) is cardinal, so it
can only be fourth-rate on a plane or axis in which doing (the will) is
cardinal, as it most assuredly is on the space-time axis of noumenal
objectivity.
27. Thus the being (love) of space-time devolution
is not only of an inferior order of being to the being (joy) of time-space
evolution, whether in sensuality or sensibility, it is of an inferior order of being
to the being (pride) of volume-mass devolution and to the being (pleasure) of
mass-volume evolution, since of an order that is not simply more essential in
relation to most essential, i.e. physical being in relation to metaphysical
being, nor even less essential in relation to least essential, i.e. chemical
being in relation to metachemical being, but least
essential, because affiliated, in metachemistry, with
that element which, being noumenally objective, is
most apparent, viz. fire.
28. Therefore only that being which, being
metaphysical, is affiliated to time-space evolution can be truly profound, and
only in spaced space is that being sensibly supreme.
29. For while the joy accruing to aural
metaphysics is incontestably supreme (positive), it is the supremacy of
sensuality in sequential time, and therefore an inferior order (cursed) of
metaphysical supremacy to the sensible order (saved) in spaced space.
30. Only respiratory metaphysics can deliver such
an ultimate supremacy, an ultimate positive essence, and for that the ego, duly
metaphysical, must be attuned to transcendental meditation, in order that the
personal self may reap the universal harvest it richly deserves ... of the most
sensible soul in the triumph of inner being, not only the
being-of-beings in relation to other types of being, but the ultimate type of
metaphysical being, in which the subconscious soul is saved for ever more. So be it!